Skip to main content

Space, Imagination and the Cosmos in the Leibniz-Clarke Correspondence

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Space, Imagination and the Cosmos from Antiquity to the Early Modern Period

Part of the book series: Studies in History and Philosophy of Science ((AUST,volume 48))

  • 457 Accesses

Abstract

The famous correspondence between Leibniz and Clarke deals with fundamental physical and metaphysical questions, such as the soul-body interaction, the freedom of will, the composition of matter, the possibility of a vacuum, miracles, gravity, and the nature of space and time. With respect to most of these issues the disagreement between Leibniz and Clarke results from their conflicting views on God’s role in the world. While Clarke blames Leibniz for turning God into a necessary agent, Leibniz accuses Clarke of having a wrong notion of God’s power and wisdom. The aim of this chapter is to show how theological, metaphysical and cosmological considerations shape Leibniz’ and Clarke’s respective theories of space. In his letters, Leibniz repeatedly invokes the Principle of Sufficient Reason and the Principle of the Identity of Indiscernibles in order to argue, against Newton and Clarke, that space cannot exist independently from, and prior to, physical bodies. Clarke, in turn, appeals to imaginary scenarios of medieval origin in order to show that the metaphysical principles that underlie Leibniz’s theory of space imply a limitation of God’s freedom. The chapter analyses in detail the role that imaginary scenarios play in the discussion concerning the ontological status of space, and attempts to provide a new interpretation of the function of the Principle of the Identity of Indiscernibles in the Correspondence.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Shapin 1981, 192.

  2. 2.

    Discourse on Metaphysics, in Leibniz 1989, 36.

  3. 3.

    Ibid., 39.

  4. 4.

    Both in the text and in the footnotes I use the letters ‘C’ and ‘L’ to indicate the respective author of the letter, roman numerals to indicate the number of the letter, and Arabic numerals to indicate the paragraph. L.IV, post scriptum, Alexander 1956, 44.

  5. 5.

    L.I.4, ibid., 12.

  6. 6.

    C.IV.22–23, ibid., 50.

  7. 7.

    C.II.1, ibid., 20.

  8. 8.

    C.IV.15, ibid., 49.

  9. 9.

    L.II.1, ibid., 16.

  10. 10.

    Ibid.

  11. 11.

    Clarke 1998, 74.

  12. 12.

    CII.1, Alexander 1956, 21.

  13. 13.

    Ibid., 20–21.

  14. 14.

    L.III.5, ibid., 26.

  15. 15.

    Cf. Rickles 2008, 33.

  16. 16.

    L.III.5, Alexander 1956, 26.

  17. 17.

    L.III.6, ibid., 27.

  18. 18.

    C.III.2, ibid., 30–31.

  19. 19.

    Ibid., 31.

  20. 20.

    Arthur 2017, 118.

  21. 21.

    C.III.4, Alexander 1956, 32.

  22. 22.

    Chernoff 1981, 132.

  23. 23.

    Ibid. E.J. Khamara writes, along similar lines: “Hence Clarke allowed the following suggestion (which I shall call Clarke’s hypothesis) to be a coherent logical possibility: that the material universe as a whole should, for any period of time and without any internal alterations, be in a state of uniform rectilinear motion along a certain absolute direction” (Khamara 2006, 99). See also Alexander 1956, xxvii.

  24. 24.

    Grant 1981, 249.

  25. 25.

    Quoted in Grant 1979, 230 (my emphasis).

  26. 26.

    Grant 1996, 124. As Algra’s Chapter 2 in this volume recalls, the first extant version of this thought experiment is found in the work of the Stoic philosopher Cleomedes .

  27. 27.

    Grant 1976, 241.

  28. 28.

    L.IV.2, Alexander 1956, 36.

  29. 29.

    Ibid.

  30. 30.

    In the Confessio philosophi (1672–1673), Leibniz had admitted the possibility that two identical bodies, for example two eggs, might be distinguished only by their situation in space. In a letter to Casati , written in 1689, Leibniz used the same example of two eggs in order to argue that there are not two things in nature which differ only extrinsically. A close examination will reveal that two apparently identical eggs are discernible ‘in themselves.’ See Rodriguez-Pereyra 2014, 84–92.

  31. 31.

    L.IV.4, Alexander 1956, ibid., 36.

  32. 32.

    L.IV.6, ibid., 37.

  33. 33.

    Dainton 2010, 178.

  34. 34.

    Leibniz IV.13, Alexander 1956, 38.

  35. 35.

    Leibniz IV.15-16, ibid., 38–39.

  36. 36.

    Lin 2016, 455.

  37. 37.

    Leibniz IV.13, Alexander 1956, 38.

  38. 38.

    L.IV.21, ibid., 39–40.

  39. 39.

    C.IV.21, ibid., 50.

  40. 40.

    C.IV.13, ibid., 48.

  41. 41.

    Arthur 2017, 120. See also Arthur 1994, 221 and Vailati 1997, 132–133. Newton ’s sixth corollary states that “If bodies are moving in any way whatsoever with respect to one another and are urged by equal accelerative forces along parallel lines, they will all continue to move with respect to one another in the same way as they would if they were not acted on by those forces,” Newton 1999, 423.

  42. 42.

    L.V.29, Alexander 1956, 63–64.

  43. 43.

    L.V.52, ibid., 74.

  44. 44.

    C.V.26–32, ibid., 100–101.

  45. 45.

    Ibid., 102.

  46. 46.

    C.V.52-53, ibid., 104–105.

  47. 47.

    Chernoff 1981, 137. Jolley 2005, 86, also points to a tension between a contingent and a necessary version of the PII.

  48. 48.

    Rodriguez-Pereyra 2014, 120.

  49. 49.

    Ibid., 25–26.

  50. 50.

    L.III.5, Alexander 1956, 26.

  51. 51.

    Cf. Chernoff 1981, 130; Rodriguez-Pereyra 2014, 163.

  52. 52.

    L.IV.6, Alexander 1956, 37.

  53. 53.

    Rodriguez-Pereyra 2014, 122.

  54. 54.

    L.IV.15, Alexander 1956, 38–39.

  55. 55.

    L.IV.4, ibid., 36.

  56. 56.

    C.IV.3-4, ibid., 46.

  57. 57.

    C.IV.15, ibid., 49.

  58. 58.

    L.V.4-5, ibid., 56.

  59. 59.

    Rodriguez-Pereyra 2014, 28.

  60. 60.

    L.V.57, Alexander 1956, 76.

  61. 61.

    L.V.58, ibid., 76–77.

  62. 62.

    L.V.21, ibid., 60–61.

  63. 63.

    L.V.25, ibid., 62.

  64. 64.

    Rodriguez-Pereyra 2014, 124.

  65. 65.

    L.V.58, Alexander 1956, 70–71.

  66. 66.

    L.IV.13, ibid., 38.

  67. 67.

    L.III.5, ibid., 26.

  68. 68.

    L.IV.7, ibid., 37.

  69. 69.

    Futch 2008, 50. Futch who, somewhat unexpectedly, does not discuss the thought experiment of God displacing the world in a straight line, maintains that according to Leibniz the PII is incompatible not only with Newtonian space, but also with empty space. Nicholas Rescher also attributes to Leibniz the view that void is impossible (Rescher 1967, 94).

  70. 70.

    Suarez 1597, Disputatio 51, sectio 1, 24. See Brown 2016, 209, n6. Ezio Vailati (1997, 117) believes, like Brown, that Leibniz regarded extramundane space as metaphysically possible.

  71. 71.

    Grant 1981, 412, n86.

  72. 72.

    C.III.2, Alexander 1956, 31.

  73. 73.

    L.V.29, ibid., 63 (my emphasis).

  74. 74.

    L.V.33, ibid., 64.

  75. 75.

    L.IV.21, ibid., 39–40; L.IV. post scriptum, ibid., 44.

  76. 76.

    C.V.52–53, ibid., 104.

  77. 77.

    For an analysis of various ancient versions of this thought experiment, see Ierodiakonou 2011.

  78. 78.

    This and other Lockean thought experiments are discussed in Soles and Bradfield 2001.

  79. 79.

    Locke 1975, 175–176.

  80. 80.

    Leibniz 1996, 150–151.

  81. 81.

    “Le véritable infini ne se trouve point dans un tout, composé de parties.” (Leibniz 1875–1890, VI.6, 7).

  82. 82.

    See Arthur 2001; Van Atten 2011.

  83. 83.

    Leibniz 1875–1890, II, 304, quoted in Arthur 2001, 112.

  84. 84.

    Futch 2008, 24.

  85. 85.

    L.V.31, Alexander 1956, 64.

  86. 86.

    Khamara 2006, 42.

  87. 87.

    C.V.52–53, Alexander 1956, 104.

  88. 88.

    L.V.52, ibid., 74.

  89. 89.

    L.V.53, ibid.

  90. 90.

    See, among others, Alexander 1956, xxvi; Cook 1979, 50ff; Vailati 1997, 131; Arthur 1994, 231.

References

  • Alexander, Robert Gavin, ed. 1956. The Leibniz-Clarke Correspondence, With Extracts from Newton’s Principia and Opticks. Manchester: Manchester University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arthur, Richard. 1994. Space and Relativity in Newton and Leibniz. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 45: 219–240.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2001. Leibniz on Infinite Number, Infinite Wholes, and the Whole World: A Reply to Gregory Brown. The Leibniz Review 11: 103–116.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2017. Thought Experiments in Newton and Leibniz. In The Routledge Companion to Thought Experiments, ed. Michael T. Stuart, Yiftach Fehige, and James Robert Brown, 111–127. London: Routledge.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Brown, Gregory. 2016. Leibniz on the Possibility of a Spatial Vacuum, the Connectedness Condition on Possible Worlds, and Miracles. In Leibniz on Compossibility and Possible Worlds, ed. Gregory Brown and Yual Chiek, 201–226. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Chernoff, Fred. 1981. Leibniz’s Principle of the Identity of Indiscernibles. The Philosophical Quarterly 31: 126–138.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clarke, Samuel. 1998. A Demonstration of the Being and Attributes of God. And Other Writings, ed. Ezio Vailati. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cook, John W. 1979. A Reappraisal of Leibniz’s Views on Space, Time, and Motion. Philosophical Investigations 2: 22–63.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dainton, Barry. 2010. Time and Space. 2nd ed. London/New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Futch, Michael J. 2008. Leibniz’s Metaphysics of Time and Space. Dordrecht/Boston: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Grant, Edward. 1976. Place and Space in Medieval Physical Thought. In Motion and Time, Space and Matter, ed. Peter K. Machamer and Robert G. Turnbull, 136–166. Columbus: Ohio State University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1979. The Condemnation of 1277, God’s Absolute Power, and Physical Thought in the Late Middle Ages. Viator 10: 211–244.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1981. Much Ado about Nothing: Theories of Space and Vacuum from the Middle Ages to the Scientific Revolution. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1996. The Foundations of Modern Science in the Middle Ages: Their Religious, Institutional and Intellectual Contexts. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ierodiakonou, Katarina. 2011. Remarks on the History of an Ancient Thought Experiment. In Thought Experiments in Methodological and Historical Contexts, ed. Katarina Ierodiakonou and Sophie Roux, 37–49. Leiden: Brill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jolley, Nicholas. 2005. Leibniz. London/New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Khamara, Edward J. 2006. Space, Time and Theology in the Leibniz-Newton Controversy. Frankfurt: Ontos.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm. 1875–1890. Die philosophischen Schriften, ed. Carl Immanuel Gerhardt, 7 vols. Berlin: Weidmann.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1989. Discourse on Metaphysics. In Philosophical Essays, eds. and trans. Roger Ariew and Daniel Garber. 35–68. Indianapolis: Hackett.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1996. New Essays on Human Understanding, eds. and transl. Peter Remnant and Jonathan Bennett. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lin, Martin. 2016. Leibniz on the Modal Status of Absolute Space and Time. Noûs 50: 447–464.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Locke, John. 1975. An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, ed. Peter Nidditch. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Newton, Isaac. 1999. The Principia: Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy, ed. and trans. I. Bernard Cohen and Anne Whitman. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rescher, Nicholas. 1967. The Philosophy of Leibniz. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rickles, Dean. 2008. Symmetry, Structure, and Spacetime. Amsterdam: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rodriguez-Pereyra, Gonzalo. 2014. Leibniz’s Principle of the Identity of Indiscernibles. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Shapin, Steven. 1981. Of Gods and Kings: Natural Philosophy and Politics in the Leibniz-Clarke Disputes. Isis 72 (2): 187–215.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Soles, David, and Katherine Bradfield. 2001. Some Remarks on Locke’s Use of Thought Experiments. Locke Studies 1: 41–61.

    Google Scholar 

  • Suarez, Francisco. 1597. Metaphysicarum disputationum, in quibus et universa naturalis theologia ordinate traditur, et quaestiones omnes ad duodecim Aristotelis libros pertinentes accurate disputantur tomus prior. Salamanca: Renaut.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vailati, Ezio. 1997. Leibniz and Clarke: A Study of Their Correspondence. Oxford/New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Atten, Marc. 2011. A Note on Leibniz’s Argument against Infinite Wholes. British Journal for the History of Philosophy 19: 121–129.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Carla Rita Palmerino .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2018 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Palmerino, C.R. (2018). Space, Imagination and the Cosmos in the Leibniz-Clarke Correspondence . In: Bakker, F., Bellis, D., Palmerino, C. (eds) Space, Imagination and the Cosmos from Antiquity to the Early Modern Period. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, vol 48. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-02765-0_12

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics