Skip to main content

Part of the book series: Perspectives in Pragmatics, Philosophy & Psychology ((PEPRPHPS,volume 20))

  • 506 Accesses

Abstract

Jennifer Saul’s puzzle, a generalized version of Frege’s puzzle concerning opacity, poses troublesome triads such as: (i) Superman = Clark Kent; (ii) Superman does not wear glasses; (iii) Clark Kent does wear glasses. Proposed resolutions of the puzzle variously deny the identity claim (i) (Graeme Forbes, Joseph Moore, David Pitt); deny one or other of the predication claims (ii)/(iii) (Jennifer Saul, David Braun, Alex Barber, Alessandro Capone); or postulate equivocation (Stefano Predelli, Laurence Goldstein). I myself develop an equivocation account, using the resources of cognitive semantics (e.g. Gilles Fauconnier, George Lakoff, and Ray Jackendoff). My work shares Saul’s psychologistic turn but reaches very different conclusions. Whereas Saul regards (i) as semantically true, and others regard it as false, I regard each of (i–iii) as both true and false (true in one way and false in another). This is not to say that they are lexically, structurally, or illocutionarily ambiguous; but they do possess a kind of pragmatic indeterminacy that generates what I call ambivalence ambiguity. If my account is correct, ambivalence ambiguity is due to inconsistencies intrinsic to our mental models. My mentalist account of linguistic interpretation is both clarified and supported by analogy to cartographic interpretation, and it is additionally supported by virtue of its power to solve problems that confront referential semantics: the notorious aspect problem and the heretofore unrecognized parity problem.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Challenging the relevance of (5), Moore (2000) suspects that ‘successful’ induces opacity because it implies an attitude. Moore is correct if success is understood in terms of attractiveness, but success could just as well be measured by sexual activity. I’m not suggesting that male success with women should be measured that way, only that that’s surely the intent behind (5). Moore’s objection therefore misses the point.

  2. 2.

    Material in this paper is part of two larger projects. In one I apply my thesis, that aspects are projections, to the problem of personal identity. In the other I develop solutions for puzzles involving the opacity of identities and non-identities beyond those discussed in the existing literature, including names, predicates, and other syntactic types. Some of the material herein has been presented at Semantics & Philosophy in Europe (Bochum, Germany, 2011) and the International Conference on Pragmatics and Philosophy (Palermo, Italy, 2016). For stimulating comments, I thank James Myers and the event organizers and audiences, especially Jay Atlas and Mitch Green. This work is dedicated to the memory of Justin Leiber.

References

  • Armstrong, D.M. (1973). Belief, truth, and knowledge. Cambridge UP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Atlas, Jay. (1989). Philosophy without ambiguity. Oxford UP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Atlas, Jay. (2005). Logic, meaning, and conversation. Oxford UP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barber, Alex. (2000). A pragmatic treatment of simple sentences. Analysis 60: 300–308.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Borges, Jorge. (1975). A universal history of infamy (translated by Norman de Giovanni). London: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Braun, David & Jennifer Saul. (2002). Simple sentences, substitution, and mistaken evaluations. Philosophical Studies 1–41.

    Google Scholar 

  • Capone, Alessandro. (2016). Embedding explicatures. This volume.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carroll, Lewis. (1893). Sylvie and Bruno concluded. London: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, Noam. (2000). New horizons in the study of language and mind. Cambridge UP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cruse, D.A. (1986). Lexical semantics. Cambridge UP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davis, Wayne. (2003). Meaning, expression, and thought. Cambridge UP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, Daniel. (1987). The intentional stance. MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fauconnier, Gilles. (1994). Mental spaces, 2/e. Cambridge UP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Forbes, Graham. (1997). How much substitutivity? Analysis 57: 109–113.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Forbes, Graham. (1999). Enlightened semantics for simple sentences. Analysis 59: 86–91.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frege, Gottlob. (1918). The thought. Translated in Mind 65: 289–311 (1956).

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldstein, Laurence. (2009). Wittgenstein and situation comedy. Philosophia 37: 605–627.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hoffman, D., M. Singh, and C. Prakash. (2015). The interface theory of perception. Psychonomics Bulletin & Review 22: 1480–1506.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jackman, Henry. (2017). William James’s naturalistic account of concepts and his ‘Rejection of Logic’. Philosophy of mind in the 19th century, ed. Sandra Lapointe. Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackendoff, Ray. (1983). Semantics and cognition. MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jaszczolt, K. (2005). Default semantics. Oxford UP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kirkham, Richard. (1992). Theories of truth. MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lakoff, George. (1987). Women, fire, and dangerous things. University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maier, Emar. (2016). Attitudes and mental files in discourse representation theory. Review of Philosophy and Psychology 7: 473–490.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moltmann, Friederike. (2003). Propositional attitudes without propositions. Synthese 35: 77–118.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moltmann, Friederike. (2014). Propositions, attitudinal objects, and the distinction between actions and products. Canadian Journal of Philosophy.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moore, Joseph. (1999). Saving substitutivity in simple sentences. Analysis 59: 91–105.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moore, Joseph. (2000). Did Clinton lie? Analysis 60: 250–254.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Panshin, Alexei & Panshin, Cory. (1989). The world beyond the hill. Los Angeles: Jeremy Tarcher.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pitt, David. (2001). Alter egos and their names. Journal of Philosophy 98: 531–552.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Predelli, Stefano. (2004). Superheroes and their names. American Philosophical Quarterly 41: 107–122.

    Google Scholar 

  • Price, Huw. (2013). Expressivism, pragmatism, and representationalism. Cambridge UP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Recanati, Francois. (2007). Perspectival thought. Oxford UP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Recanati, Francois. (2013). Mental files. Oxford UP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Saka, Paul. (1991). Lexical decomposition in cognitive semantics. Linguistics dissertation, University of Arizona.

    Google Scholar 

  • Saka, Paul. (1998). Meaning and the ascription of attitudes. Philosophy dissertation, University of Illinois, Urbana-Champaign.

    Google Scholar 

  • Saka, Paul. (2007a). The argument from ignorance against truth-conditional semantics. American Philosophical Quarterly 44: 157–170.

    Google Scholar 

  • Saka, Paul. (2007b). How to think about meaning. Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Saka, Paul. (2010). Rarely pure and never simple: tensions in the theory of truth. Topoi 29: 125–136.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Saka, Paul. (2017). Blah. blah, blah: quasi-quotation and unquotation. The semantics and pragmatics of quotation, ed. Paul Saka and Michael Johnson. Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Saul, Jennifer. (1997). Substitution and simple sentences. Analysis 57: 300–308.

    Google Scholar 

  • Saul, Jennifer. (1999). Substitution, simple sentences, and sex scandals. Analysis 59: 106–112.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Saul, Jennifer. (2000). Did Clinton say something false? Analysis 60: 255–257.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Saul, Jennifer. (2007). Simple sentences, substitution, and intuitions. Oxford UP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, John. (1969). Speech acts. Cambridge UP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, John. (1979). Expression and meaning. Cambridge UP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Snyder, John. (1993). Flattening the Earth: two thousand years of map projections. University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sorensen, Roy. (2001). Vagueness and contradiction. Oxford UP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Talmy, Leonard. (2000). Toward a cognitive semantics, v. 1. MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zuber, Richard. (2006). Possible intensionality of the verb phrase position. Analysis 66: 255–256.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2019 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Saka, P. (2019). Superman Semantics. In: Capone, A., Carapezza, M., Lo Piparo, F. (eds) Further Advances in Pragmatics and Philosophy: Part 2 Theories and Applications. Perspectives in Pragmatics, Philosophy & Psychology, vol 20. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-00973-1_10

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-00973-1_10

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-030-00972-4

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-030-00973-1

  • eBook Packages: Social SciencesSocial Sciences (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics