Skip to main content

Free Will and Neuroscience: Revisiting Libet’s Studies

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Is Science Compatible with Free Will?

Abstract

Benjamin Libet contends both that “the brain ‘decides’ to initiate or, at least, prepare to initiate [certain actions] before there is any reportable subjective awareness that such a decision has taken place” and that “If the ‘act now’ process is initiated unconsciously, then conscious free will is not doing it.” Elsewhere, I have argued that the claims I just reported are not justified by the data Libet and others offer in support of them. Here I review some of the problems one encounters in attempting to move from Libet’s data to his conclusions.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Elsewhere, Libet writes: “the brain has begun the specific preparatory processes for the voluntary act well before the subject is even aware of any wish or intention to act” (1992, p. 263).

  2. 2.

    For a useful discussion of what the initiation of an action might amount to and of connections among action initiation, Libet’s data, and free will, see Bayne (2011).

  3. 3.

    Try to imagine that you intend to eat some pie now while also intending not to eat it now. What would you do? Would you reach for it with one hand and grab the reaching hand with your other hand? People who suffer from anarchic hand syndrome sometimes display behavior of this kind. Spence and Frith suggest that these people “have conscious ‘intentions to act’ [that] are thwarted by … ‘intentions’ to which the patient does not experience conscious access” (1999, p. 24).

  4. 4.

    Kilner et al. produce evidence that, as they put it, “the readiness potential (RP)—an electrophysiological marker of motor preparation—is present when one is observing someone else’s action” (2004, p. 1299).

  5. 5.

    I did not suggest that the estimates are influenced only by events that follow action. For evidence that the estimates are also influenced by events that precede action, see Haggard (2011, pp. 19–22).

  6. 6.

    Would subjects’ conscious, silent “now!”s actually express proximal decisions? Perhaps not. To see why, consider an imaginary experiment in which subjects are instructed to count—consciously and silently—from 1 to 3 and to press a button just after they consciously say “3” to themselves. Presumably, these instructions would be no less effective at eliciting pressings than the “now!” instructions. In this experiment, the subjects are treating a conscious event—the conscious “3”-saying—as a go signal. (When they say “3,” they are not at all uncertain about what to do, and they make no decision then to press.) Possibly, in a study in which subjects are given the “now!” instructions, they would not actually make proximal decisions to press but would instead consciously simulate deciding and use the conscious simulation event as a go signal. However, the possibility of simulation is not a special problem for studies featuring the “now!”-saying instructions. In Libet’s own studies, some subjects may be treating a conscious experience—for example, their initial consciousness of an urge to flex—as a go signal (see Keller & Heckhausen, 1990, p. 352).

  7. 7.

    Parts of this article derive from Mele, 2009. This article was made possible through the support of a grant from the John Templeton Foundation. The opinions expressed in this publication are my own and do not necessarily reflect the views of the John Templeton Foundation. I am grateful to an audience at a Social Trends Institute Experts Meeting (Barcelona, October, 2010) for comments on a presentation of this article.

References

  • Banks, W., & Isham, E. (2009). We infer rather than perceive the moment we decided to act. Psychological Science, 20, 17–21.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Bayne, T. (2011). Libet and the case for free will skepticism. In R. Swinburne (Ed.), Free will and modern science. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haggard, P. (2005). Conscious intention and motor cognition. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 9, 290–95.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Haggard, P. (2006). Conscious intention and the sense of agency. In N. Sebanz & W. Prinz (Eds.), Disorders of volition. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haggard, P. (2011). Does brain science change our view of free will. In R. Swinburne (Ed.), Free will and modern science. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haggard, P., & Eimer, M. (1999). On the relation between brain potentials and the awareness of voluntary movements. Experimental Brain Research, 126, 128–33.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haggard, P., & Magno, E. (1999). Localising awareness of action with transcranial magnetic stimulation. Experimental Brain Research, 127, 102–07.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hallett, M. (2007). Volitional control of movement: The physiology of free will. Clinical Neurophysiology, 118, 1179–92.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Keller, I., & Heckhausen, H. (1990). Readiness potentials preceding spontaneous motor acts: Voluntary vs. involuntary control. Electroencephalography and Clinical Neurophysiology, 76, 351–61.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Kilner, J., Vargas, C., Duval, S., Blakemore, S., & Sirigu, A. (2004). Motor activation prior to observation of a predicted movement. Nature Neuroscience, 7, 1299–1301.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Lau, H., Rogers, R., & Passingham, R. (2007). Manipulating the experienced onset of intention after action execution. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 19, 81–90.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Libet, B. (1985). Unconscious cerebral initiative and the role of conscious will in voluntary action. The Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 8, 529–66.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Libet, B. (1992). The neural time-factor in perception, volition and free will. Revue de Métaphysique et de Morale, 2, 255–72.

    Google Scholar 

  • Libet, B. (1999). Do we have free will? Journal of Consciousness Studies, 6, 47–57.

    Google Scholar 

  • Libet, B. (2001). Consciousness, free action and the brain. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 8, 59–65.

    Google Scholar 

  • Libet, B. (2004). Mind time. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Libet, B., Wright, E., & Gleason, C. (1982). Readiness potentials preceding unrestricted ‘spontaneous’ vs. pre-planned voluntary acts. Electroencephalography and Clinical Neurophysiology, 54, 322–35.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Logan, G. (1994). On the ability to inhibit thought and action: A users’ guide to the stop signal paradigm. In E. Dagenbach & T. Carr (Eds.), Inhibitory processes in attention, memory, and language. San Diego: Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mele, A. (1997). Strength of motivation and being in control: Learning from Libet. American Philosophical Quarterly, 34, 319–32.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mele, A. (2003). Motivation and agency. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mele, A. (2006). Free will and luck. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mele, A. (2009). Effective intentions. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pockett, S. (2006). The neuroscience of movement. In S. Pockett, W. Banks, & S. Gallagher (Eds.), Does consciousness cause behavior? An investigation of the nature of volition. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roediger, H., Goode, M., & Zaromb, F. (2008). Free will and the control of action. In J. Baer, J. Kaufman, & R. Baumeister (Eds.), Are we free? Psychology and free will. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spence, S., & Frith, C. (1999). Towards a functional anatomy of volition. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 6, 11–29.

    Google Scholar 

  • Trevena, J., & Miller, J. (2010). Brain preparation before a voluntary action: Evidence against unconscious movement initiation. Consciousness and Cognition, 19, 447–56.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • van de Grind, W. (2002). Physical, neural, and mental timing. Consciousness and Cognition, 11, 241–64.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Wegner, D. (2002). The illusion of conscious will. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Alfred R. Mele .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2013 Springer Science+Business Media, LLC

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Mele, A.R. (2013). Free Will and Neuroscience: Revisiting Libet’s Studies. In: Suarez, A., Adams, P. (eds) Is Science Compatible with Free Will?. Springer, New York, NY. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-4614-5212-6_13

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics