Skip to main content

Psychology and the Aims of Normative Ethics

  • Reference work entry
  • First Online:
Handbook of Neuroethics
  • 674 Accesses

Abstract

This chapter discusses the philosophical relevance of empirical research on moral cognition. It distinguishes three central aims of normative ethical theory: understanding the nature of moral agency, identifying morally right actions, and determining the justification of moral beliefs. For each of these aims, the chapter considers and rejects arguments against employing cognitive scientific research in normative inquiry. It concludes by suggesting that, whichever of the central aims one begins from, normative ethics is improved by engaging with the science of moral cognition.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 999.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 999.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    There is one sense in which no one doubts the relevance of empirical findings to normative ethics. That is in applying settled normative views to actual circumstances. Obviously psychology – and ordinary daily experience – can aid us in learning how to bring about the moral goals we have set, once those goals are already determined. What is at issue in this chapter is something different: Can empirical moral psychology play a role in helping to determine what the moral goals themselves ought to be?

  2. 2.

    Some clarification about terms: The use of “empirical moral psychology” is meant to be ecumenical, encompassing research by psychologists, neuroscientists, biologists, behavioral economists, sociologists, and experimental philosophers. “Normative ethics” refers to the branch of moral philosophy concerned with how we ought to live our lives, what things we ought to value, and what practical decisions we ought to make. This chapter does not discuss certain related topics, such as free will and moral responsibility, or naturalistic moral ontology.

  3. 3.

    The clearest statement of Kant’s view on this point comes in Book 3 of his Groundwork for the Metaphysics of Morals (Kant 1785). Interpreting Kant is always a delicate matter, and there is not space here to fully explicate the interpretation given in the text, which mostly follows Korsgaard (1996a).

  4. 4.

    Kant (1785), Ak 4:389. Kant is quite strident on this point; he goes on to insist that an empirical approach to fundamental moral principles gives only a “base way of thinking,” “disadvantageous to the purity of moral themselves… a bastard patched together from limbs of quite diverse ancestry” (4:425–426).

  5. 5.

    Kant often certainly sounds as if he is making a metaphysical claim, where adopting the practical perspective entails denying that the world really contains deterministic natural laws. But this is not the only interpretation available. See Korsgaard (1996a).

  6. 6.

    (Korsgaard 1996b, p. 17). For a related discussion specifically regarding psychological findings, see Kamm (2009, p. 469).

  7. 7.

    Although objections to step (1) are possible, one might challenge the idea of agency itself, or at least the idea that reflective endorsement is a necessity for it. Doris (2009) makes an argument of this sort. Alternately, one might suggest that the connection between steps (1) and (2) is less clear. See van Roojen (1999) for an argument that the kinds of reasons relevant to moral agency do not map onto the kinds of motives discussed in psychological theory.

  8. 8.

    Similar comments apply to the phenomenon of moral disagreement. Knowing how and why people come to hold diverging moral views – between various communities (Moody-Adams 2002; Haidt 2012) or even within individual minds (Cushman and Young 2009) – might provide clues as to how to deal with them.

  9. 9.

    Piaget, in fact, aims his work squarely at addressing Kant’s challenge to empirical psychology. Piaget’s developmental account is explicitly intended to reveal the nature of moral agency (or autonomy). For a development of Piaget’s views on normative ethics, see Rini (unpublished manuscript).

  10. 10.

    (Kohlberg 1971, p. 224). For a critical appraisal of Kohlberg’s normative claims, see Goodpaster (1982). Kohlberg’s findings have also been criticized on empirical grounds, especially by his former collaborators (Gilligan 1982) and (Turiel 1983). For more recent work in the developmental tradition, see Rest et al. (1999) and Narvaez and Lapsley (2009).

  11. 11.

    The linguistic analogy has been criticized both for its normative claims (Daniels 1980) and its empirical grounding (Dupoux and Jacob 2007; Prinz 2008). For general discussions of descriptive interpretations of reflective equilibrium, see Scanlon (2002) opposed, and Rini (2011, Chap. 3), in favor. A closely related research program, focused on describing the causal role of intention-ascription in moral judgment, provides a detailed example of what careful empirical work can uncover (Knobe 2003; Young and Saxe 2008; Cushman 2008).

  12. 12.

    For examples of the linguistic formulation of the is-ought gap, see Stevenson (1944, pp. 271–276) and Hare (1952, pp. 17–55). Williams (1985, pp. 121–131) argues that the linguistic formulation does not clarify matters.

  13. 13.

    Flanagan 1993, p. 32. See also a related argument in Appiah (2008, pp. 22–23).

  14. 14.

    See also Gigerenzer (2008, p. 6) and Moody-Adams (2002, p. 140) for other applications of “ought”/“can” to limitations on cognitive or imaginative human capacities.

  15. 15.

    (Rawls 1971, p. 138). Rawls continued to draw attention to this role for psychological findings in his later work (Rawls 1974, p. 294, Rawls 1987, p. 24). Rawls’ attention to psychological realism has brought his method criticism as overly conservative, but an ought-implies-can argument like the one sketched in this section may actually show this sort of conservatism to be a theoretical virtue. See Rini (2011, Chap. 3).

  16. 16.

    Even Peter Singer, usually quite uncompromising about the demandingness of morality, allows moral theory to bend for certain psychological limitations. For instance, Singer notes that partiality toward family runs contrary to impersonal consequentialist theory. However, he says, familial partiality is so biologically entrenched that it is better to harness it – and so secure reliable concern for local welfare – than to attempt to fight it. See Singer (1981, pp. 33–36).

  17. 17.

    (Churchland 2000, p. 294). This negative argument is related, but not identical, to Horgan and Timmons’ (2009) frame problem, discussed above. For further related arguments, see Stich (1993) and Johnson (1996).

  18. 18.

    Rawls stresses that his method of reflective equilibrium is meant to operate only upon “considered moral judgments,” which are a class of intuitions rendered according to constraints like these. See Rawls (1951, p. 179) and Rawls (1971, pp. 47–48).

  19. 19.

    There is a difficult issue here about what type of norm plays this role: Intoxicated intuitions might be excluded on epistemic grounds (intoxication being though not conducive to truth in any domain), while the self-interest exclusion may represent a distinctively moral norm. But such issues can be set aside here.

  20. 20.

    It should be noted that in Haidt’s later work (Haidt 2012), he downplays the centrality of emotion and instead focuses on automated cognition. For critical discussion of Haidt’s view, see Pizarro and Bloom (2003); Kennett and Fine (2009); Liao (2011); Huebner (2011), among others.

  21. 21.

    See Greene (Greene et al. 2001, 2004) for the psychological background. For further discussion, see the references given in parenthesis (Singer 2005; Nichols and Mallon 2006; Allman and Woodward 2008; Kamm 2009; Kahane and Shackel 2010; Kumar and Campbell 2012). Berker (2009) offers a particularly comprehensive criticism of the empirical and normative aspects of Greene’s argument.

  22. 22.

    For more on moral heuristics, see the references given in parenthesis (Baron 1994; Horowitz 1998; van Roojen 1999; Kamm 1998; Sunstein 2005; Gigerenzer 2008; Appiah 2008). Sinnott-Armstrong (2008) makes a related, and still more ambitious, argument, claiming that the influence of morally irrelevant factors like framing effects or presentational order is so pervasive as to cast an epistemic shadow over all moral intuitions. This sort of argument is not unique to the moral domain – see Weinberg (2007); Alexander (2012, Chap. 4) for related criticism of the role of intuition in all areas of philosophy.

  23. 23.

    Many responses to the moral heuristics argument and Greene’s argument, including most of those mentioned in footnotes above, involve challenging their particular empirical or normative premises. Another response, suggested by Levy (2006), claims that a constructivist meta-ethic can immunize us to many of these challenges. If one holds that morality simply is whatever our intuitions (or some suitably restricted class of them) correspond to, then there is little danger of our intuitions turning out driven by “morally irrelevant” factors – the psychological findings will simply tell us what our moral beliefs have been committed to all along.

  24. 24.

    See Rini (2013) for discussion of a broader theoretical framework for arguments of this sort. Similar moderate approaches – sympathetic to empirical investigation, but issuing cautionary qualifications – can be found in the references given in parenthesis (Stevenson 1944, p. 123; Baier 1985, p. 224; Noble 1989, p. 53; Held 1996, p. 83; Appiah 2008; Tiberius 2010; Kahane 2013). But see Machery (2010) for a skeptical argument, accusing the moderate approach of circularity.

  25. 25.

    The contents of this chapter benefited significantly from discussions with Tommaso Bruni, Nora Heinzelmann, Guy Kahane, and Felix Schirmann, and from written comments by Stephan Schleim and an anonymous referee. This research was part of the project “Intuition and Emotion in Moral Decision Making,” funded by the VolkswagenStiftung’s European Platform for Life Sciences, Mind Sciences, and the Humanities (grant II/85 063).

References

  • Alexander, J. (2012). Experimental philosophy: An introduction (1st ed.). Cambridge, UK: Polity.

    Google Scholar 

  • Allman, J., & Woodward, J. (2008). What are moral intuitions and why should we care about them? A neurobiological perspective. Philosophical Issues, 18(1), 164–185. doi:10.1111/j.1533-6077.2008.00143.x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Annas, J. (2005). Comments on john Doris’s lack of character. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 71(3), 636–642.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Anscombe, G. E. M. (1958). Modern moral philosophy. Philosophy, 33(124), 1–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Appiah, K. A. (2008). Experiments in ethics. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baier, A. (1985). Theory and reflective practices. In Postures of the mind. Minneapolis: Univ of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baron, J. (1994). Nonconsequentialist decisions. The Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 17(01), 1–10. doi:10.1017/S0140525X0003301X.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berker, S. (2009). The normative insignificance of neuroscience. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 37(4), 293–329. doi:10.1111/j.1088-4963.2009.01164.x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Casebeer, W. D., & Churchland, P. S. (2003). The neural mechanisms of moral cognition: A multiple-aspect approach to moral judgment and decision-making. Biology and Philosophy, 18(1), 169–194.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Churchland, P. (2000). Rules, know-how, and the future of moral cognition. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 30(Supplement), 291–306.

    Google Scholar 

  • Churchland, P. S. (2011). Braintrust: What neuroscience tells us about morality. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (1996). Connectionism, moral cognition, and collaborative problem solving. In L. May, M. Friedman, & A. Clark (Eds.), Minds and morals: Essays on cognitive science and ethics (pp. 109–127). Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cushman, F. (2008). Crime and punishment: Distinguishing the roles of causal and intentional analyses in moral judgment. Cognition, 108(2), 353–380. doi:10.1016/j.cognition.2008.03.006.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cushman, F., & Young, L. (2009). The psychology of dilemmas and the philosophy of morality. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 12, 9–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Daniels, N. (1980). On some methods of ethics and linguistics. Philosophical Studies, 37(1), 21–36. doi:10.1007/BF00353498.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Darley, J. M., & Batson, C. D. (1973). “From Jerusalem to Jericho”: A study of situational and dispositional variables in helping behavior. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 27, 100–108.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Waal, F. (2006). Primates and philosophers: How morality evolved. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Doris, J. M. (2002). Lack of character: Personality and moral behavior. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Doris, J. M. (2009). Skepticism about persons. Philosophical Issues, 19(1), 57–91.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Doris, J. M., & Stich, S. (2007). As a matter of fact: Empirical perspectives on ethics. In F. Jackson & M. Smith (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of contemporary philosophy (1st ed., Vol. 1, pp. 114–153). Oxford: Oxford University Press. Retrieved from http://www.oxfordhandbooks.com/oso/public/content/oho_philosophy/9780199234769/oxfordhb-9780199234769-chapter-5.html

  • Dupoux, E., & Jacob, P. (2007). Universal moral grammar: A critical appraisal. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 11(9), 373–378. doi:10.1016/j.tics.2007.07.001.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, R. (1996). Objectivity and truth: You’d better believe it. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 25(2), 87–139.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dwyer, S. (2006). How good is the linguistic analogy? In P. Carruthers, S. Laurence, & S. Stich (Eds.), The innate mind: Culture and cognition. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eskine, K. J., Kacinik, N. A., & Prinz, J. J. (2011). A bad taste in the mouth: Gustatory disgust influences moral judgment. Psychological Science, 22(3), 295–299. doi:10.1177/0956797611398497.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Flanagan, O. (1993). Varieties of moral personality: Ethics and psychological realism. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Flanagan, O. (1996). Ethics naturalized: Ethics as human ecology. In L. May, M. Friedman, & A. Clark (Eds.), Minds and morals: Essays on cognitive science and ethics (pp. 19–43). Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foot, P. (2003). Natural goodness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frankfurt, H. G. (1971). Freedom of the will and the concept of a person. Journal of Philosophy, 68(1), 5–20.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fried, C. (1978). Biology and ethics: Normative implications. In Morality as a biological phenomenon: The presuppositions of sociobiological research (pp. 187–197). Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gigerenzer, G. (2008). Moral intuition = fast and frugal heuristics? In W. Sinnott-Armstrong (Ed.), Moral psychology (The cognitive science of morality: Intuition and diversity, Vol. 2, pp. 1–26). Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilligan, C. (1982). In a different voice: Psychology theory and women’s development. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodpaster, K. E. (1982). Kohlbergian theory: A philosophical counterinvitation. Ethics, 92(3), 491–498.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Graham, P. A. (2011). “Ought” and ability. Philosophical Review, 120(3), 337–382. doi:10.1215/00318108-1263674.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Greene, J. D. (2008). The secret joke of Kant’s soul. In W. Sinnott-Armstrong (Ed.), Moral psychology (The neuroscience of morality: Emotion, brain disorders, and development, Vol. 3, pp. 35–80). Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Greene, J. D., Sommerville, R. B., Nystrom, L. E., Darley, J. M., & Cohen, J. D. (2001). An fMRI investigation of emotional engagement in moral judgment. Science, 293(5537), 2105–2108. doi:10.1126/science.1062872.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Greene, J. D., Nystrom, L. E., Engell, A. D., Darley, J. M., & Cohen, J. D. (2004). The neural bases of cognitive conflict and control in moral judgment. Neuron, 44(2), 389–400. doi:10.1016/j.neuron.2004.09.027.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haidt, J. (2001). The emotional dog and its rational tail: A social intuitionist approach to moral judgment. Psychological Review, 108(4), 814–834.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haidt, J. (2012). The righteous mind: Why good people are divided by politics and religion (1st ed.). New York: Pantheon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haidt, J., & Bjorklund, F. (2008). Social intuitions answer six questions about moral psychology. In W. Sinnott-Armstrong (Ed.), Moral psychology (The cognitive science of morality: Intuition and diversity, Vol. 2, pp. 181–218). Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haney, C., Banks, W. C., & Zimbardo, P. G. (1973). A study of prisoners and guards in a simulated prison. Naval Research Review, 30, 4–17.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hare, R. M. (1952). The language of morals. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harman, G. (1999). Moral philosophy meets social psychology: Virtue ethics and the fundamental attribution error. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 99, 315–331.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hauser, M. D. (2006). The liver and the moral organ. Social Cognitive and Affective Neuroscience, 1(3), 214–220. doi:10.1093/scan/nsl026.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Held, V. (1996). Whose agenda? Ethics versus cognitive science. In L. May, M. Friedman, & A. Clark (Eds.), Minds and morals: Essays on cognitive science and ethics (pp. 69–88). Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hooker, B. (1990). Rule-consequentialism. Mind, 99(393), 67–77.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Horgan, T., & Timmons, M. (2009). What does the frame problem tell us about moral normativity? Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 12(1), 25–51.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Horowitz, T. (1998). Philosophical intuitions and psychological theory. Ethics, 108(2), 367–385.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Huebner, B. (2011). Critiquing empirical moral psychology. Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 41(1), 50–83. doi:10.1177/0048393110388888.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hume, D. (1739). A treatise of human nature. London: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hursthouse, R. (2002). On virtue ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, M. L. (1996). How moral psychology changes moral theory. In L. May, M. Friedman, & A. Clark (Eds.), Minds and morals: Essays on cognitive science and ethics (pp. 45–67). Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Joyce, R. (2006). The evolution of morality (1st ed.). Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kahane, G. (2013). The armchair and the trolley: An argument for experimental ethics. Philosophical Studies, 162(2), 421–445.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kahane, G., & Shackel, N. (2010). Methodological issues in the neuroscience of moral judgement. Mind and Language, 25(5), 561–582. doi:10.1111/j.1468-0017.2010.01401.x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kamm, F. M. (1998). Moral intuitions, cognitive psychology, and the harming-versus-not-aiding distinction. Ethics, 108(3), 463–488.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kamm, F. M. (2009). Neuroscience and moral reasoning: A note on recent research. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 37(4), 330–345. doi:10.1111/j.1088-4963.2009.01165.x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kamtekar, R. (2004). Situationism and virtue ethics on the content of our character. Ethics, 114(3), 458–491.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (1785). Groundwork for the metaphysics of morals. (trans: Wood, A.W.). New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kennett, J., & Fine, C. (2009). Will the real moral judgment please stand up? The implications of social intuitionist models of cognition for meta-ethics and moral psychology. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 12(1), 77–96.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (2011). The ethical project. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Knobe, J. (2003). Intentional action and side effects in ordinary language. Analysis, 63(279), 190–194. doi:10.1111/1467-8284.00419.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Knobe, J. (2010). Person as scientist, person as moralist. The Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 33(4), 315–329. doi:10.1017/S0140525X10000907. discussion 329–365.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kohlberg, L. (1971). From “is” to “ought”: How to commit the naturalistic fallacy and get away with it in the study of moral development. In T. Mischel (Ed.), Cognitive development and epistemology. New York: Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Korsgaard, C. M. (1996a). Creating the kingdom of ends: Reciprocity and responsibility in personal relations. In Creating the kingdom of ends (pp. 188–223). Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Korsgaard, C. M. (1996b). The sources of normativity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kumar, V., & Campbell, R. (2012). On the normative significance of experimental moral psychology. Philosophical Psychology, 25(3), 311–330.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levy, N. (2006). Cognitive scientific challenges to morality. Philosophical Psychology, 19(5), 567–587. doi:10.1080/09515080600901863.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levy, N. (2009). Empirically informed moral theory: A sketch of the landscape. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 12(1), 3–8. doi:10.1007/s10677-008-9146-2.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Liao, S. M. (2011). Bias and reasoning: Haidt’s theory of moral judgment. In T. Brooks (Ed.), New waves in ethics. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Machery, E. (2010). The bleak implications of moral psychology. Neuroethics, 3(3), 223–231. doi:10.1007/s12152-010-9063-7.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • MacIntyre, A. C. (1981). After virtue: A study in moral theory. South Bend: Notre Dame Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mackie, J. L. (1977). Ethics: Inventing right and wrong. London: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mikhail, J. (2011). Elements of moral cognition: Rawls’ linguistic analogy and the cognitive science of moral and legal judgment (3rd ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Milgram, S. (1973). Obedience to authority. New York: Harper Torchbooks.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moody-Adams, M. (2002). Fieldwork in familiar places: Morality, culture, and philosophy (Newth ed.). Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moore, G. E. (1903). Principia ethica. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, T. (1978). Ethics as an autonomous theoretical subject. In G. S. Stent (Ed.), Morality as a biological phenomenon: The presuppositions of sociobiological research (pp. 198–205). Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, T. (1986). The view from nowhere. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, T. (1997). The last word. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Narvaez, D. (2010). The emotional foundations of high moral intelligence. New Directions for Child and Adolescent Development, 2010(129), 77–94. doi:10.1002/cd.276.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Narvaez, D., & Lapsley, D. K. (Eds.). (2009). Personality, identity, and character: Explorations in moral psychology (1st ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nichols, S. (2004). Sentimental rules: On the natural foundations of moral judgment. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nichols, S., & Mallon, R. (2006). Moral dilemmas and moral rules. Cognition, 100(3), 530–542. doi:10.1016/j.cognition.2005.07.005.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Noble, C. N. (1989). Normative ethical theories. In S. G. Clark & E. Simpson (Eds.), Anti-theory in ethics and moral conservatism (pp. 49–64). Albany: SUNY Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, M. C. (2003). Upheavals of thought: The intelligence of emotions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Petrinovich, L., & O’Neill, P. (1996). Influence of wording and framing effects on moral intuitions. Ethology and Sociobiology, 17(3), 145–171. doi:10.1016/0162-3095(96)00041-6.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Petrinovich, L., O’Neill, P., & Jorgensen, M. (1993). An empirical study of moral intuitions: Toward an evolutionary ethics. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 64(3), 467–478. doi:10.1037/0022-3514.64.3.467.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pizarro, D. A., & Bloom, P. (2003). The intelligence of the moral intuitions: Comment on haidt (2001). Psychological Review, 110(1), 193–196. discussion 197–198.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Prinz, J. J. (2008). Resisting the linguistic analogy. In W. Sinnott-Armstrong (Ed.), Moral psychology (The cognitive science of morality: Intuition and diversity, Vol. 2, pp. 157–170). Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. (1951). Outline of a decision procedure for ethics. Philosophical Review, 60(2), 177–197.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. (1971). A theory of justice (1st ed.). Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. (1974). The independence of moral theory. Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association, 48, 5–22. doi:10.2307/3129858.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. (1987). The idea of an overlapping consensus. Oxford Journal of Legal Studies, 7(1), 1–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rest, J., Narvaez, D., Bebeau, M. J., & Thoma, S. (1999). Postconventional moral thinking: A Neo-kohlbergian approach. Mahwah: Psychology Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rini, R. A. (2011). Within is the fountain of good: Moral philosophy and the science of the nonconscious mind. Doctoral Thesis. New York: New York University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rini, R. A. (unpublished manuscript). Kantian autonomy and piagetian autonomy.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rini, R. A. (2013). Making psychology normatively significant. The Journal of Ethics, 17(3), 257–274

    Google Scholar 

  • Ross, L., & Nisbett, R. E. (1991). The person and the situation (70th ed.). New York: Mcgraw-Hill College.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sabini, J., & Silver, M. (1982). Moralities of everyday life. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sabini, J., & Silver, M. (2005). Lack of character? Situationism critiqued. Ethics, 115(3), 535–562.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scanlon, T. M. (2002). Rawls on justification. In S. Freeman (Ed.), The Cambridge companion to Rawls (pp. 139–167). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Schleim, S., & Schirmann, F. (2011). Philosophical implications and multidisciplinary challenges of moral physiology. Trames, 15(2), 127–146.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schnall, S., Haidt, J., Clore, G. L., & Jordan, A. H. (2008). Disgust as embodied moral judgment. Personality & social psychology bulletin, 34(8), 1096–1109. doi:10.1177/0146167208317771.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sherman, N. (1990). The place of emotions in Kantian morality. In O. Flanagan & A. Rorty (Eds.), Identity, character and morality: Essays in moral psychology. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sidgwick, H. (1907). The methods of ethics. Hackett.

    Google Scholar 

  • Singer, P. (1981). The expanding circle: Ethics and sociobiology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Singer, P. (2005). Ethics and intuitions. Journal of Ethics, 9(3–4), 331–352.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sinnott-Armstrong, W. (2008). Framing moral intuition. In W. Sinnott-Armstrong (Ed.), Moral psychology, vol 2. The cognitive science of morality: Intuition and diversity (pp. 47–76). Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sripada, C. S. (2005). Punishment and the strategic structure of moral systems. Biology and Philosophy, 20, 767–789.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stevenson, C. L. (1944). Ethics and language. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stich, S. (1993). Moral philosophy and mental representation. In M. Hechter, L. Nadel, & R. Michod (Eds.), The origin of values (pp. 215–228). New York: Adine de Gruyer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, P. F. (1974). Freedom and resentment. In his Freedom and resentment and other essays. Routledge:London: Methuen and Co. pp. 1–25.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strohminger, N., Lewis, R. L., & Meyer, D. E. (2011). Divergent effects of different positive emotions on moral judgment. Cognition, 119(2), 295–300. doi:10.1016/j.cognition.2010.12.012.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sunstein, C. R. (2005). Moral heuristics. The Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 28(4), 531–542.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tiberius, V. (2010). Appiah and the autonomy of ethics. Neuroethics, 3(3), 209–214. doi:10.1007/s12152-010-9064-6.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Turiel, E. (1983). The development of social knowledge. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Valdesolo, P., & DeSteno, D. (2006). Manipulations of emotional context shape moral judgment. Psychological Science, 17(6), 476–477. doi:10.1111/j.1467-9280.2006.01731.x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Roojen, M. (1999). Reflective moral equilibrium and psychological theory. Ethics, 109(4), 846–857.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weinberg, J. M. (2007). How to challenge intuitions empirically without risking skepticism. Midwest Studies In Philosophy, 31(1), 318–343. doi:10.1111/j.1475-4975.2007.00157.x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wheatley, T., & Haidt, J. (2005). Hypnotic disgust makes moral judgments more severe. Psychological Science, 16(10), 780–784. doi:10.1111/j.1467-9280.2005.01614.x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williams, B. (1985). Ethics and the limits of philosophy. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Young, L., & Saxe, R. (2008). The neural basis of belief encoding and integration in moral judgment. NeuroImage, 40(4), 1912–1920. doi:10.1016/j.neuroimage.2008.01.057.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Regina A. Rini .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2015 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this entry

Cite this entry

Rini, R.A. (2015). Psychology and the Aims of Normative Ethics. In: Clausen, J., Levy, N. (eds) Handbook of Neuroethics. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-4707-4_162

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-4707-4_162

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-94-007-4706-7

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-007-4707-4

  • eBook Packages: Humanities, Social Sciences and Law

Publish with us

Policies and ethics