Skip to main content

Protection of the Environment, the Biosphere and Biodiversity

  • Reference work entry
  • First Online:

Abstract

What exactly does the environment, the biosphere, and biodiversity entail? To what extent are they in crisis currently, what are the drivers behind this crisis, and why is it important that one should do something about this crisis? What exactly should one focus on when protecting the environment, the biosphere, and biodiversity, and why should one do so? In this chapter, an overview is given of the conceptual, philosophical, and ethical challenges related to finding answers to these questions. The crux of this discussion is devoted to different kinds of values that can be used to justify protection. The most commonly used arguments for the protection of the environment, the biosphere, and biodiversity appeal to their instrumental value. In this context, distinctions are made between the direct use value, indirect use value, amenity value, option value, and existence value that humans can derive from protection of the environment, the biosphere, and biodiversity. While these values can be emphasized in isolation from one another, causing either a destructive overemphasis of use value or a romantic overemphasis of the nonconsumptive (use) value of the environment, the biosphere, and biodiversity, the notion of ecosystem services is discussed as a framework within which these instrumental values can be combined serving as they do as the basis of human well-being. On the other hand, intrinsic value arguments are often emphasized in environmental ethics to counter the reduction of the environment, the biosphere, and biodiversity to mere commodities, or to objects of management at arm’s length from humans and thus at their disposal to use at will. Under the best interpretations of these intrinsic value arguments, the focus falls on a respectful reverence for the environment, the biosphere, and biodiversity, the components that make them up, as well as the ecosystemic and evolutionary processes they entail – conceptualized not as commodities but as prerequisites for the existence, continued evolution, and flourishing of all life on earth. Under this interpretation of intrinsic value, the use of the environment, the biosphere, and biodiversity is not precluded but strongly qualified in that any such use should be careful, considerate, and equitable to enhance and not undermine the conditions under which life (including both human and nonhuman life) can continue to evolve and flourish on earth. In the introductory parts of this chapter, discussion is devoted to issues around definitions of, and conceptual overlaps and differences between environment, the biosphere, and biodiversity, as well as conceptual difficulties that are caused by the vagueness of these terms, efforts to define them objectively, and approaches to them that only emphasize their constituent elements, neglecting a holistic vision that also emphasize the ecosystemic processes they entail and their evolution over time. This chapter concludes with an outlook on the future of the environment, the biosphere, and biodiversity.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   949.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD   549.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

References

  • Afeissa, H. (2009). Intrinsic and instrumental value. In J. B. Callicott & R. Frodeman (Eds.), Encyclopedia of environmental ethics and philosophy (Gale, cengage learning, Vol. 1, pp. 529–531). Detroit: Macmillan Reference USA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Callicott, J. B. (1999). Beyond the land ethic: More essays in environmental philosophy. Albany, NY: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carson, R. (2002). Silent spring. New York: Mariner Books. (1st. Pub. Boston: Houghton Mifflin, 1962).

    Google Scholar 

  • Costanza, R. (1991). Ecological economics: The science and management of sustainability. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davis, M. A. (2009). Invasion biology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ehrenfeld, D. (1988). Why put a value on biodiversity? In E. O. Wilson (Ed.), Biodiversity. Washington, DC: National Academy Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Faith, D. P. (2008). Biodiversity. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2008 Edition). URL: http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2008/entries/biodiversity/

  • Fox, W. (1995). Toward a transpersonal ecology: Developing new foundations for environmentalism. Totnes, Devon: A Resurgence Book.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gardiner, S. M. (2011). A perfect moral storm. The ethical tragedy of climate change. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gaston, K. J. (Ed.). (1996). Biodiversity: A biology of numbers and difference. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hardin, G. (1968). The tragedy of the commons. Science, New Series, 162 (3859), 1243–1248. Also available at: http://www.sciencemag.org/content/162/3859/1243.full

  • Holland, A. (2001). Sustainability. In D. Jamieson (Ed.), A companion to environmental philosophy (pp. 390–401). Malden, MA/Oxford, UK: Blackwell.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Jacobs, M. (1995). Sustainable development, capital substitution and economic humility: A response to Beckerman. Environmental Values, 4, 57–68.

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, D. L., Ambrose, S. H., Bassett, T. J., Bowen, M. L., Crummey, D. E., Isaacson, J. S., Johnson, D. N., Lamb, P., Saul, M., & Winter-Nelson, A. E. (1997). Meanings of environmental terms. Journal of Environmental Quality, 26, 581–589.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kempton, W. M., Boster, J. S., & Hartley, J. A. (1995). Environmental values in American culture. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laurance, W. F. (1999). Reflections on the tropical deforestation crisis. Biological Conservation, 91, 109–117.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Luck, G. W., Daily, G. C., & Ehrlich, P. R. (2003). Population diversity and ecosystem services. Trends in ecology and evolution, 18(7), 331–336.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Meadows, D. H., Meadows, D. l., Randers, J., & Behrens III, W. W. (1972). The limits to growth. A report to the Club of Rome. New York: Universe Books. Also available at: http://www.scribd.com/doc/2682517/Club-of-Rome-Report

  • Millennium Ecosystem Assessment. (2005). Ecosystems and human well-being: Synthesis, p. vi, available at: http://www.maweb.org/documents/document.356.aspx.pdf

  • Morin, E. (1999). Homeland EARTH: A manifesto for the new millennium (Advances in systems theory, complexity and the human sciences). London/England: Hampton Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Næss, A. (1973). The shallow and the deep, long-range ecology movement. Inquiry, 16(1), 95–100.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Norton, B. G. (2003). Searching for sustainability. Interdisciplinary essays in the philosophy of conservation biology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Neill, J., Holland, A., & Light, A. (2008). Environmental values. London/New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pimm, S. L., Russell, G. J., Gittleman, J. L., & Brooks, T. M. (1995). The future of biodiversity. Science, 269, 347–350.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Primack, R. B. (2006). Essentials of conservation biology (4th ed.). Sunderland, MA: Sinauer Associates.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raup, D. M. (1991). Extinction: Bad genes or bad luck? New York: W.W. Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reaka-Kudla, M. L., Wilson, D. E., & Wilson, E. O. (Eds.). (1997). Biodiversity II: Understanding and protecting our biological resources. Washington, DC: Joseph Henry Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rolston, H., III. (2001). Biodiversity. In D. Jamieson (Ed.), A companion to environmental philosophy (pp. 402–415). Malden, MA/Oxford, UK: Blackwell.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Routley, R. (1973). Is there a need for a new, an environmental ethic? In Proceedings of the 15th World Congress of Philosophy (Vol. 1, pp. 205–210). Sophia: Sophia Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Solow, R. M. (1993). Sustainability: An economist’s perspective. In R. Dorfman & N. S. Dorfman (Eds.), Economics of the environment: Selected readings (3rd ed., pp. 178–187). New York: W.W. Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Soulé, M. E., Estes, J. A., Berger, J., & Del Rio, C. M. (2003). Ecological effectiveness: Conservation goals for interactive species. Conservation Biology, 17(5), 1238–1250.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stern, N. (2010). A blueprint for a safer planet: How we can save the world and create prosperity. London: Vintage Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Swilling, M., & Annecke, E. (2012). Just transitions. Explorations of sustainability in an unfair world. Claremont: UCT Press (in South Africa). Tokyo: United Nations University Press (in North America).

    Google Scholar 

  • TEEB. (2010). The economics of ecosystems and biodiversity: Mainstreaming the economics of nature: A synthesis of the approach, conclusions and recommendations of TEEB. The Economics of Ecosystems and Biodiversity. Hosted by UNEP, this report is available at: http://www.teebweb.org/Portals/25/TEEB%20Synthesis/TEEB_SynthReport_09_2010_online.pdf

  • The Ecologist. (1972). A blueprint for survival. The Ecologist, 2 (1). Also available at: http://www.theecologist.info/key27.html

  • The Royal Society. (2012). People and the planet. The Royal Society Science Policy Centre report 01/12. Also available at: http://royalsociety.org/uploadedFiles/Royal_Society_Content/policy/projects/people-planet/2012-04-25-PeoplePlanet.pdf

  • Turner, G. (2008). A comparison of ‘The limits to growth’ with thirty years of reality. Canberra: Commonwealth Scientific and Industrial Research Organisation (CSIRO).

    Google Scholar 

  • WCED. (1987). Our common future. Report of the World Commission on Environment and Development to the United Nations. Available at: http://www.un-documents.net/wced-ocf.htm Known as the Brundtland Report, also published in 1987 at Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Wilson, E. O. (Ed.). (1988). Biodiversity. Washington, DC: National Academy Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, E. O. (1992). The diversity of life. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Johan Hattingh .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2014 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this entry

Cite this entry

Hattingh, J. (2014). Protection of the Environment, the Biosphere and Biodiversity. In: ten Have, H., Gordijn, B. (eds) Handbook of Global Bioethics. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-2512-6_80

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-2512-6_80

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-94-007-2511-9

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-007-2512-6

  • eBook Packages: Humanities, Social Sciences and Law

Publish with us

Policies and ethics