Skip to main content
Log in

Discount-neutral utility models for denumerable time streams

  • Published:
Theory and Decision Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper formulates and axiomatizes utility models for denumerable time streams that make no commitment in regard to discounting future outcomes. The models address decision under certainty and decision under risk. Independence assumptions in both contexts lead to additive or multiplicative utilities over time periods that allow unambiguous comparisons of the relative importance of different periods. The models accommodate all patterns of future valuation. This discount-neutral feature is attained by restricting preference comparisons to outcome streams or probability distributions on outcome streams that differ in at most a finite number of periods.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

REFERENCES

  • Algoet, P.H.: 1994, ‘The strong law of large numbers for sequential decisions under uncertainty’, IEEE Transactions on Information Theory 40, 609–633.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bailey, S.: 1825, A Critical Dissertation on the Nature, Measure, and Causes of Value, New York: Augustus M. Kelly (1967).

    Google Scholar 

  • Balintfy, J.L., Duffy, W.J. and Sinha, P.: 1974, ‘Modeling food preferences over time’, Operations Research 22, 711–727.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baumol, W.J.: 1958, ‘On the social rate of discount’, American Economic Review 58, 788–802.

    Google Scholar 

  • Becker, R.A., Boyd, J.H. and Sung, B.Y.: 1989, ‘Recursive utility and optimal capital accumulation. I. Existence’, Journal of Economic Theory 47, 76–100.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bernoulli, D.: 1738, ‘Specimen theoriae novae de mensura sortis’, Commentarii Academiae Scientiarum Imperialis Petropolitanae 5, 175–192. Translated by L. Sommer: 1954, ‘Exposition of a new theory on the measurement of risk’, Econometrica 22, 23–36.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blackwell, D.: 1965, ‘Discounted dynamic programming’, Annals of Mathematical Statistics 36, 226–235.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blackwell, D. and Girshick, M.A.: 1954, Theory of Games and Statistical Decisions, New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bleichrodt, H. and Gafni, A.: 1994, ‘Time preference, the discounted utility model and health’, preprint.

  • Böhm-Bawerk, E. von: 1889, Positive Theorie des Kapitals, Vol. II, 4th edn., translated by I.D. Huncke: 1959, Capital and Interest, Vol. II, Positive Theory of Capital, Book IV, Section I, pp. 257–289, South Holland, IL: Libertarian Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brown, D.J. and Lewis, L.M.: 1981, ‘Myopic economic agents’, Econometrica 49, 359–368.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chow, Y.S. and Robbins, H.: 1963, ‘On optimal stopping rules’, Zeitschrift für Wahrscheinlichkeitstheorie und verwandte Gebiete 2, 33–49.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cowen, T. and High J.: 1988, ‘Time, bounded utility, and the St. Petersburg paradox’, Theory and Decision 25, 219–223.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dana, R.A. and Le Van, C.: 1991, ‘Equilibria of a stationary economy with recursive preferences’, Journal of Optimization Theory and Applications 71, 289–313.

    Google Scholar 

  • Debreu, G.: 1960, ‘Topological methods in cardinal utility theory’, in Mathematical Methods in the Social Sciences, 1959, K.J. Arrow, S. Karlin and P. Suppes, (ed.) pp. 16–26, Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Diamond, P.A.: 1965, ‘The evaluation of infinite utilitystreams’, Econometrica 33, 170–177.

    Google Scholar 

  • Duffie, D., Epstein, L.G. and Skiadas, C.: 1992, ‘Stochastic differential utility’, Econometrica 60, 353–394.

    Google Scholar 

  • Epstein, L.G. and Wang, T.: 1994, ‘Intertemporal asset pricing under Knightian uncertainty’, Econometrica 62, 283–322.

    Google Scholar 

  • Epstein, L. and Zin, S.: 1989, ‘Substitution, risk aversion and the temporal behavior of consumption and asset returns: A theoretical framework’, Econometrica 57, 937–969.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fetter, F.A.: 1915, Economic Principles, Vol. I, New York: The Century Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fetter, F.A.: 1977, Capital, Interest, and Rent: Essays in the Theory of Distribution, ed. by M. Rothbard, Kansas City: Sheed Andrews and McMeel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fishburn, P.C.: 1965a, ‘Independence in utility theory with whole product sets’, Operations Research 13, 28–45.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fishburn, P.C.: 1965b, ‘Markovian dependence in utility theory with whole product sets’, Operations Research 13, 238–257.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fishburn, P.C.: 1966, ‘Additivity in utility theory with denumerable product sets’, Econometrica 34, 500–503.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fishburn, P.C.: 1970, Utility Theory for Decision Making, New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fishburn, P.C.: 1990, ‘Continuous nontransitive additive conjoint measurement’, Mathematical Social Sciences 20, 165–193.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fisher, I.: 1892, ‘Mathematical investigations in the theory of values and prices’, Transactions of the Connecticut Academy of Arts and Sciences 9, 1–124.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fisher, I.: 1930, The Theory of Interest, New York: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilboa, I.: 1989, ‘Expectation and variation in multi-period decisions’, Econometrica 57, 1153–1169.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gordon, B.: 1975, Economic Analysis Before Adam Smith: Hesiod to Lessius, New York: Barnes and Noble.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hammond, P.J.: 1976, ‘Changing tastes and coherent dynamic choice’, Review of Economic Studies 43, 159–173.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harvey, C.M.: 1988, ‘Utility functions for infinite-period planning’, Management Science 34, 645–665.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harvey, C.M.: 1994, ‘The reasonableness of non-constant discounting’, Journal of Public Economics 53, 31–51.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harvey, C.M.: 1995, ‘Proportional discounting of future costs and benefits’, Mathematics of Operations Research 20, 381–399.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jensen, N.E.: 1967, ‘An introduction to Bernoullian utility theorem. I. Utility functions’, Swedish Journal of Economics 69, 163–183.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kauder, E.: 1965, A History of Marginal Utility Theory, Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Keeney, R.L.: 1968, ‘Quasi-separable utility functions’, Naval Research Logistics Quarterly 15, 551–565.

    Google Scholar 

  • Keeney, R.L. and Raiffa, H.: 1976, Decisions with Multiple Objectives: Preferences and Value Tradeoffs, New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kohn, M.G. and Shavell, S.: 1974, ‘The theory of search’, Journal of Economic Theory 9, 93–123.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koopmans, T.C.: 1960, ‘Stationary ordinal utility and impatience’, Econometrica 28, 287–309.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koopmans, T.C.: 1972, ‘Representation of preference orderings over time’, in Decision and Organization, ed. by C.B. McGuire and R. Radner, pp. 79–100, Amsterdam: North-Holland.

    Google Scholar 

  • Krantz, D.H., Luce, R.D., Suppes, P. and Tversky, A.: 1971, Foundations of Measurement, Vol. I, New York: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kreps, D.M. and Porteus, E.L.: 1977, ‘On the optimality of structured policies in countable stage decision processes. II: Positive and negative problems’, SIAM Journal on Applied Mathematics 32, 457–466.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kreps, D.M. and Porteus, E.L.: 1978, ‘Temporal resolution of uncertainty and dynamic choice theory’, Econometrica 46, 185–200.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kreps, D.M. and Porteus, E.L.: 1979, ‘Dynamic choice theory and dynamic programming’, Econometrica 47, 91–100.

    Google Scholar 

  • Loewenstein, G.: 1987, ‘Anticipation and the valuation of delayed consumption’, Economic Journal 97, 666–684.

    Google Scholar 

  • Loewenstein, G. and Elster, J.: 1992, Choice over Time, New York: Russell Sage Foundation.

    Google Scholar 

  • Loewenstein, G. and Prelec, D.: 1991, ‘Negative time preference’, AEA Papers and Proceedings 81, 347–352.

    Google Scholar 

  • Loewenstein, G. and Thaler, R.: 1989, ‘Anomalies: Intertemporal choice’, Journal of Economic Perspectives 3, 181–193.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lucas, R. and Stokey, N.: 1984, ‘Optimal growth with many consumers’, Journal of Economic Theory 32, 139–171.

    Google Scholar 

  • Menger, K.: 1934, ‘Das Unsicherheitsmoment in der Wertlehre’, Zeitschrift für Nationaloekonomie 5, 459–485. Translated by W. Schoellkopf: 1967, ‘The role of uncertainty in economics’, in Essays in Mathematical Economics, ed. M. Shubik, pp. 211–231, Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nairay, A.: 1984, ‘Asymptotic behavior and optimal properties of a consumptioninvestment model with variable time preference’, Journal of Economics and Dynamic Control 7, 283–313.

    Google Scholar 

  • Olson, M. and Bailey, M.J.: 1981, ‘Positive time preference’, Journal of Political Economy 89, 1–25.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pauly, M.V.: 1970, ‘Risk and the social rate of discount’, American Economic Review 60, 195–198.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peleg, B. and Yaari, M.E.: 1973, ‘On the existence of a consistent course of action when tastes are changing’, Review of Economic Studies 40, 391–401.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pollak, R.A.: 1967, ‘Additive von Neumann-Morgenstern utility functions’, Econometrica 35, 485–494.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ramsey, F.P.: 1928, ‘A mathematical theory of saving’, Economic Journal 38, 543–559.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rothbard, M.N.: 1990, ‘Time preference’, in The New Palgrave: Utility and Probability, ed. by J. Eatwell, M. Milgate and P. Newman, pp. 270–275, London: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Samuelson, P.A.: 1977, ‘St. Petersburg paradoxes: Defanged, dissected, and historically described’, Journal of Economic Literature 15, 24–55.

    Google Scholar 

  • Savage, L.J.: 1954, The Foundations of Statistics, New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shafer, G.: 1988, ‘The St. Petersburg paradox’, in Encyclopedia of Statistical Sciences, Vol. 8, ed. by S. Kotz and N.L. Johnson, pp. 865–870, New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Streufert, P.A.: 1993, ‘Abstract recursive utility’, Journal of Mathematical Analysis and Applications 175, 169–185.

    Google Scholar 

  • Suppes, P. and Zinnes, J.L.: 1963, ‘Basic measurement theory’, in Handbook of Mathematical Psychology, I, ed. by R.D. Luce, R.R. Bush, and E. Galanter, New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Toulet, C.: 1986, ‘An axiomatic model of unbounded utility functions’, Mathematics of Operations Research 11, 81–94.

    Google Scholar 

  • Uzawa, H.: 1968, ‘Time preference, the consumption function, and optimum asset holdings’, in Value, Capital and Growth: Papers in Honour of Sir John Hicks, ed. by J.N. Wolfe, Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Mises, L.: 1949, Human Action: A Treatise on Economics, third revised edn. (1966), Chicago: Regnery.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wakker, P.P.: 1989, Additive Representations of Preferences, Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wakker, P.P.: 1993, ‘Unbounded utility for Savage's ‘Foundations of Statistics’ and other models’, Mathematics of Operations Research 18, 446–485.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weibull, J.W.: 1985, ‘Discounted-value representationsof temporal preferences’, Mathematics of Operations Research 10, 244–250.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yahav, J.A.: 1966, ‘On optimal stopping’, Annals of Mathematical Statistics 37, 30–35.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Fishburn, P., Edwards, W. Discount-neutral utility models for denumerable time streams. Theory and Decision 43, 139–166 (1997). https://doi.org/10.1023/A:1004943925179

Download citation

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1023/A:1004943925179

Navigation