Skip to main content
Log in

Population thinking as trope nominalism

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The concept of population thinking was introduced by Ernst Mayr as the right way of thinking about the biological domain, but it is difficult to find an interpretation of this notion that is both unproblematic and does the theoretical work it was intended to do. I argue that, properly conceived, Mayr’s population thinking is a version of trope nominalism: the view that biological property-types do not exist or at least they play no explanatory role. Further, although population thinking has been traditionally used to argue against essentialism about biological kinds, recently it has been suggested that it may be consistent with at least some forms of essentialism—ones that construe essential properties as relational. I argue that if population thinking is a version of trope nominalism, then, as Mayr originally claimed, it rules out any version of essentialism about biological kinds.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Ariew A. (2008) Population thinking. In: Ruse M. (eds) Oxford handbook of philosophy of biology. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 64–86

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Ariew A., Lewontin R. (2004) The confusions of fitness. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 55: 347–363

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bouchard F., Rosenberg A. (2004) Fitness, probability and the principles of natural selection. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 55: 693–712

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boyd R. (1999) Homeostasis, species and higher taxa. In: Wilson R. (eds) Species: New interdisciplinary essays. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA, pp 141–186

    Google Scholar 

  • Brandon R. N. (2006) The principle of drift: Biology’s first law. Journal of Philosophy 102: 319–335

    Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, K. (1981). The metaphysics of abstract particulars. Midwest studies in philosophy, 6, 477–488. Reprinted in D. H. Mellor & A. Oliver (Eds.), Properties (pp. 125–139). Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1997.

  • Campbell K. (1990) Abstract particulars. Blackwell, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Cummins R. (1975) Functional analysis. Journal of Philosophy 72: 741–765

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Daly C. (1997) Tropes. In: Mellor D. H., Oliver A. (eds) Properties. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 140–159

    Google Scholar 

  • Dawkins R. (1982) The extended phenotype. W. H. Freeman, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Dretske F. (1988) Explaining behavior. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Dretske F. (1990) Reply to reviewers. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 50: 819–839

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dupré J. (1993) The disunity of science: Metaphysical foundation of the disunity of science. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Dupré J. (2002) Humans and other animals. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Elder C. L. (1995) A different kind of natural kind. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 73: 516–531

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ellis B. (2001) Scientific essentialism. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Ereshefsky, M. (2008). Species. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Fall 2008 edition).

  • Ereshefsky, M. (forthcoming). Natural kinds in biology. In Routledge encyclopedia of philosophy.

  • Ghiselin M. T. (1974) A radical solution to the species problem. Systematic Zoology 23: 536–544

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith P. (2009) Darwinian populations and natural selection. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths P. (1999) Squaring the circle: Natural kinds with historical essences. In: Wilson R. (eds) Species: New interdisciplinary essays. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA, pp 209–228

    Google Scholar 

  • Hacking, I. (2007). Natural kinds: Rosy Dawn, scholastic twilight. In A. O’Hear (Ed.), The philosophy of science (pp. 203–239) (Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplements Volume 61). Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.

  • Hawthorne J., Gendler T. S. (2000) Origin essentialism: The arguments reconsidered. Mind 109: 285–298

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hull, D. (1965). The effect of essentialism on taxonomy: 2000 years of stasis. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 15, 314–326; 16, 1–18.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hull D. (1978) A matter of individuality. Philosophy of Science 45: 335–360

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hull D. (1980) Individuality and selection. Annual Review of Ecology and Systematics 11: 311–332

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hull D. (1986) On human nature. PSA: Proceedings of the Biannual Meetings of the Philosophy of Science Association 2: 3–13

    Google Scholar 

  • Hull, D. (1994). Contemporary systematic philosophies. In E. Sober (Ed.), Conceptual issues in evolutionary biology (2nd ed., pp. 295–330). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

  • Kitcher P. (2007) Does ‘race’ have a future? Philosophy and Public Affairs 35: 293–317

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kripke S. (1980) Naming and necessity. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • LaPorte J. (2004) Natural kinds and conceptual change. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewens T. (2001) Sex and selection: Reply to Matthen. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 52: 589–598

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Matthen M. (1998) Biological universals and the nature of fear. Journal of Philosophy 95: 105–132

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Matthen M. (1999) Evolution, Wisconsin style: Selection and the explanation of individual traits. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 50: 143–150

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Matthen M. (2003) Is sex really necessary? And other questions for Lewens. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 54: 297–308

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Matthen M., Ariew A. (2002) Two ways of thinking about fitness and natural selection. Journal of Philosophy 49: 53–83

    Google Scholar 

  • Mayr E. (1942) Systematics and the origin of species. Columbia University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Mayr, E. (1959/1994). Typological versus population thinking. In B. J. Meggers (Ed.), Evolution and anthropology (pp. 409–412). Washington: The Anthropological Society of America. Reprinted in E. Sober (Ed.), Conceptual issues in evolutionary biology (pp. 325–328). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1994.

  • Mayr E. (1963) Animal species and evolution. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Mayr, E. (1969/1976). The biological meaning of species. Biological Journal of the Linnean Society, 1, 311–320. Reprinted in E. Mayr (Ed.), Evolution and the diversity of life (pp. 515–525). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

  • Mayr E. (1982) The growth of biological thought. Diversity, evolution, and inheritance. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Mayr E. (1988) The ontology of the species taxon. In: Mayr E. (eds) Towards a new philosophy of biology. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA, pp 335–358

    Google Scholar 

  • Mayr E. (1996) What is a species, and what is not? Philosophy of Science 63: 262–277

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Millikan R. G. (1990) Seismograph readings for “explaining behavior”. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 50: 819–839

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Millikan R. G. (1999) Historical kinds and the “special sciences”. Philosophical Studies 95: 45–65

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Millstein R. (2006) Natural selection as a population-level causal process. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 57: 627–653

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nanay B. (2005) Can cumulative selection explain adaptation? Philosophy of Science 72: 1099–1112

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nanay B. (2009) The properties of singular causation. The Monist 92: 112–132

    Google Scholar 

  • Nanay, B. (forthcoming). Three ways of resisting essentialism about natural kinds. In J. K. Campbell & M. H. Slater (Eds.), Carving nature at its joints. Topics in contemporary philosophy (Vol. 8). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

  • Nanay, B. (ms). Type selection versus token selection.

  • Neander K. (1995a) Pruning the tree of life. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 46: 59–80

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Neander K. (1995b) Explaining complex adaptations. A reply to Sober’s ‘reply to Neander’. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 46: 583–587

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Okasha S. (2002) Darwinian metaphysics: Species and the question of essentialism. Synthese 131: 191–213

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Platts M. (1983) Explanatory kinds. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 34: 133–148

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pust J. (2001) Natural selection explanation and origin essentialism. Canadian Journal of Philosophy 31: 201–220

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam H. (1975) Mind, language and reality. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Robertson T. (1998) Possibilities and the arguments for origin essentialism. Mind 107: 729–749

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rosenberg A. (1983) Coefficients, effects and genic selection. Philosophy of Science 50: 332–338

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rosenberg A., Bouchard F. (2005) Matthen and Ariew’s obituary to fitness: Reports of its death have been greatly exaggerated. Biology and Philosophy 20: 343–353

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sanford, D. H. (ms). Tropiary for beginners. Commentary on Peter Simons’s ‘Particulars in particular clothing’.

  • Schaffer J. (2001) The individuation of tropes. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 79: 247–257

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Simons P. (1994) Particulars in particular clothing. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 54: 553–575

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith B., Varzi A. C. (2001) Environmental metaphysics. In: Meixner U. (eds) Metaphysics in the post-metaphysical age. Hölder-Pichler-Tempsky, Vienna, pp 231–239

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith B., Varzi A. C. (2002) Surrounding space. On the ontology of organism-environment relations. Theory in Biosciences 120: 139–162

    Google Scholar 

  • Sober E. (1980) Evolution, population thinking, and essentialism. Philosophy of Science 47: 350–383

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sober E. (1981) Evolutionary theory and the ontological status of properties. Philosophical Studies 40: 147–176

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sober E. (1984) The nature of selection. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Sober E. (1995) Natural selection and distributive explanation. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 46: 384–397

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sober E., Lewontin R. (1982) Artifact, cause and genic selection. Philosophy of Science 49: 157–180

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sober E., Lewontin R. (1983) Reply to Rosenberg on genic selection. Philosophy of Science 50: 648–650

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stephens C. (2004) Selection, drift, and the “forces” of evolution. Philosophy of Science 71: 550–570

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Fraassen B. (1980) The scientific image. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Walsh D. M. (1998) The scope of selection: Sober and Neander on what natural selection explains. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 76: 250–264

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Walsh D. M. (2006) Evolutionary essentialism. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 57: 425–448

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Walsh D. M., Lewens T., Ariew A. (2002) The trials of life: Natural selection and random drift. Philosophy of Science 69: 429–446

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilkerson T. E. (1995) Natural kinds. Avebury, Aldershot

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams, D. C. (1953). On the elements of being. Review of Metaphysics, 7, 3–18; 171–192.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, R. A., Barker, M. J., & Brigandt, I. (forthcoming). When traditional essentialism fails: Biological natural kinds. Philosophical Topics.

  • Wimsatt W. C. (1980) Units of selection and the structure of the multi-level genome. Philosophy of Science Association 2: 122–193

    Google Scholar 

  • Wolterstorff N. (1973) On universals. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Bence Nanay.

Additional information

I am grateful for comments by Peter Godfrey-Smith, Karen Neander, David Sanford, Marc Lange, David Papineau, Roberta Balarin, Jason Rhein, Kris McDaniels, Ben Bradley, Kevan Edwards and James Young on an earlier version of this paper.

I presented this paper at the Inland Northwest Philosophy Conference, at the British Columbia Philosophy Conference and at the SPDMBABWS group at Syracuse University. I am grateful for my commentators as well as the audiences. This paper grew out of the discussion at my PhD seminar on natural kinds at Syracuse University. I am also grateful for detailed comments from two referees at Synthese.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Nanay, B. Population thinking as trope nominalism. Synthese 177, 91–109 (2010). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-009-9641-6

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-009-9641-6

Keywords

Navigation