Skip to main content
Log in

On the meaning and the epistemological relevance of the notion of a scientific phenomenon

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this paper I offer an appraisal of James Bogen and James Woodward’s distinction between data and phenomena which pursues two objectives. First, I aim to clarify the notion of a scientific phenomenon. Such a clarification is required because despite its intuitive plausibility it is not exactly clear how Bogen and Woodward’s distinction has to be understood. I reject one common interpretation of the distinction, endorsed for example by James McAllister and Bruce Glymour, which identifies phenomena with patterns in data sets. Furthermore, I point out that other interpretations of Bogen and Woodward’s distinction do not specify the relationship between phenomena and theories in a satisfying manner. In order to avoid this problem I propose a contextual understanding of scientific phenomena according to which phenomena are states of affairs which play specific roles in scientific practice and to which we adopt a special epistemic attitude. Second, I evaluate the epistemological significance of Bogen and Woodward’s distinction with respect to the debate between scientific realists and constructive empiricists. Contrary to what Bogen and Woodward claim, I argue that the distinction does not provide a convincing argument against constructive empiricism.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Achinstein P. (2001) The book of evidence. Oxford University Press., Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Berg-Hildebrand A., Suhm C. (2006) The hardships of an empiricist. In: Berg-Hildebrand A., Suhm C.(eds) Bas C. van Fraassen—The fortunes of empiricism. Ontos., Frankfurt/Main, pp 57–67

    Google Scholar 

  • Bogen J., Woodward J. (1988) Saving the phenomena. The Philosophical Review 97: 303–352

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bogen J., Woodward J. (1992) Observations, theories and the evolution of the human spirit. Philosophy of Science 59: 590–611

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bogen J., Woodward J. (2003) Evading the IRS. Poznan Studies in the Philosophy of Science and the Humanities 20: 223–245

    Google Scholar 

  • Casoli F., Encrenaz T. (2007) The new worlds: Extrasolar planets. Springer, Berlin

    Google Scholar 

  • Castelnovo C., Moessner R., Sondhi S.L. (2008) Magnetic monopoles in spin ice. Nature 451: 42–45

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Duhem P. (1969) To save the phenomena—An essay on the idea of physical theory from Plato to Galileo. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Duric N. (2003) Advanced astrophysics. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Glymour B. (2000) Data and phenomena: A distinction reconsidered. Erkenntnis 52: 29–37

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ladyman J., Douven I., Horsten L., van Fraassen B. C. (1997) A defence of van Fraassen’s critique of abductive inference: Reply to Psillos. The Philosophical Quarterly 47: 305–321

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mayor M., Queloz D. (1995) A Jupiter-mass companion to a solar-type star. Nature 378: 355–359

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McAllister J.W. (1997) Phenomena and patterns in data sets. Erkenntnis 47: 217–228

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mittelstrass J. (1961) Die Rettung der Phänomene—Ursprung und Geschichte eines antiken Forschungsprogramms. Walter de Gruyter & Co, Berlin

    Google Scholar 

  • Monton B., van Fraassen B. (2003) Constructive empiricism and modal nominalism. British Journal for Philosophy of Science 54: 405–422

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Suppes P. (1962) Models of data. In: Nagel E., Suppes P., Tarski A.(eds) Logic, methodology, and philosophy of science—Proceedings of the 1960 international congress. Stanford University Press, Stanford, pp 252–261

    Google Scholar 

  • Tonomura A., Nori F. (2008) Disturbance without the force. Nature 452: 298–299

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Fraassen B. (1980) The scientific image. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • van Fraassen B. (1985) Empiricsm in the philosophy of science. In: Churchland P. M., Hooker C. A.(eds) Images of science. University of Chicago Press, Chicago, pp 245–368

    Google Scholar 

  • Woodward J. (1989) Data and phenomena. Synthese 79: 393–472

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Woodward J. (2000) Data, phenomena, and reliability. Philosophy of Science 67: S163–S179

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Woodward J., Hitchcock C. (2003) Explanatory generalizations, Part I: A counterfactual account. Nous 37: 1–24

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jochen Apel.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Apel, J. On the meaning and the epistemological relevance of the notion of a scientific phenomenon. Synthese 182, 23–38 (2011). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-009-9620-y

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-009-9620-y

Keywords

Navigation