Skip to main content
Log in

Underdetermination, realism and empirical equivalence

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Are theories ‘underdetermined by the evidence’ in any way that should worry the scientific realist? I argue that no convincing reason has been given for thinking so. A crucial distinction is drawn between data equivalence and empirical equivalence. Duhem showed that it is always possible to produce a data equivalent rival to any accepted scientific theory. But there is no reason to regard such a rival as equally well empirically supported and hence no threat to realism. Two theories are empirically equivalent if they share all consequences expressed in purely observational vocabulary. This is a much stronger requirement than has hitherto been recognised—two such ‘rival’ theories must in fact agree on many claims that are clearly theoretical in nature. Given this, it is unclear how much of an impact on realism a demonstration that there is always an empirically equivalent ‘rival’ to any accepted theory would have—even if such a demonstration could be produced. Certainly in the case of the version of realism that I defend—structural realism—such a demonstration would have precisely no impact: two empirically equivalent theories are, according to structural realism, cognitively indistinguishable.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Duhem P. (1906/1954) The aim and structure of physical theory. Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ

    Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, C. G. (1958/1965). The theoretician’s Dilemma: A study in the logic of theory construction. In Aspects of scientific explanation (pp. 173–228). New York: The Free Press.

  • Kitcher P. (1993) The advancement of science. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn T. S. (1957/1985) The Copernican revolution: Planetary astronomy in the development of western thought. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Laudan L. (1981) A confutation of convergent realism. Philosophy of Science 48(1): 19–49

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laudan L., Leplin J. (1991) Empirical equivalence and underdetermination. The Journal of Philosophy 88: 449–472

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lakatos I. (1970) Falsification and the methodology of scientific research programmes. In: Lakatos I., Musgrave A.E. (eds) Criticism and the growth of knowledge. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Lakatos I., Zahar E. (1976) Why did Copernicus’ research program Supersede Ptolemy’s?. In: Westman R. S. (eds) The Copernican achievement. UCLA Center for Medieval and Renaissance Studies Contributions Vol. VII. University of California Press, Berkeley, CA, p 354

    Google Scholar 

  • Lipton, P. (2000). Tracking track records I. In Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, (Supplementary Vols. 74, pp. 179–205).

  • Okasha S. (1997) Laudan and Leplin on empirical equivalence. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 48: 251–256

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Poincaré H. (1905/1952) Science and hypothesis. Dover Publications, Inc, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Psillos S. (1999) Scientific realism: How science tracks truth. Routledge, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Psillos S. (2004) Tracking the real: Through thick and thin. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 55: 393–409

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. O. (1961). On what there is. In From a logical point of view: 9 Logico-philosophical essays (pp. 1–19). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

  • van Fraassen B. (1980) The scientific image. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Votsis I. (2005) The upward path to structural realism. Philosophy of Science 72(5): 1361–1372

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Worrall J. (1989) Structural realism: The best of both worlds. Dialectica 43(1–2): 99–124

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Worrall, J. (2000). Tracking track records II. In Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, (Supplementary Vols. 74, pp. 207–235).

  • Worrall J. (2001) The scope, limits, and distinctiveness of the method of ‘deduction from the phenomena’: Some lessons from Newton’s ‘demonstrations’ in optics. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 51: 45–80

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Worrall J. (2003) Normal science and Dogmatism, Paradigms and Progress: Kuhn ‘versus’ Popper and Lakatos. In: Nickles T. (eds) Thomas Kuhn. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, MA, pp 65–100

    Google Scholar 

  • Worrall J. (2006) Theory-confirmation and history. In: Cheyne C., Worrall J., Musgrave A. (eds) Rationality and reality: Conversations with Alan Musgrave. Springer, Dordrecht, pp 31–62

    Google Scholar 

  • Worrall, J. (forthcoming). Defending structural realism; or: The ‘Newman objection’ what objection?

  • Worrall J., Zahar E. (2001) Appendix IV: Ramseyfication and structural realism. In: Zahar E. (eds) Poincaré’s philosophy: From conventionalism to phenomenology. Open Court, Chicago, pp 236–251

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to John Worrall.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Worrall, J. Underdetermination, realism and empirical equivalence. Synthese 180, 157–172 (2011). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-009-9599-4

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Revised:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-009-9599-4

Keywords

Navigation