Skip to main content
Log in

Lexicalisation and the Origin of the Human Mind

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Biosemiotics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper will discuss the origin of the human mind, and the qualitative discontinuity between human and animal cognition. We locate the source of this discontinuity within the language faculty, and thus take the origin of the mind to depend on the origin of the language faculty. We will look at one such proposal put forward by Hauser et al. (Science 298:1569-1579, 2002), which takes the evolution of a Merge trait (recursion) to solely explain the differences between human and animal cognition. We argue that the Merge-only hypothesis fails to account for various aspects of the human mind. Instead we propose that the process of lexicalisation is also unique to humans, and that this process is key to explaining the vast qualitative differences. We will argue that lexicalisation is a process through which concepts are reformatted to be able to take on semantic features and to take part in grammatical relations. These are both necessary conditions for a grammatical mind and the increased ability to express conceptual content. We therefore propose a possible explanans for the discontinuity between humans and animals, namely that merge with lexicalisation (and consequently semantic features and grammatical relations) is a minimal requirement for the human mind.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See Spelke (2003); Chomsky (2005); Carruthers (2006) and Hinzen (2006) for varying views on this relationship.

  2. Some philosophers have taken the presence of inferential abilities to be the mark of possessing concepts (see Crane 1992 and Burge 2010). Though the precise nature of the inferential abilities of animals is debated (see Beck 2012 for a review of the positions in the literature), we take their limited inferential abilities to indicate a limited form of concept possession.

  3. Note that a continuity theorist can accept the existence of a shared core cognition system without contradicting their position. The continuity theorist can posit entirely new forms of representations as the thesis concerns the source of their development, not their existence.

  4. Following Carey (2009) we take this bootstrapping to be similar to the way in which Quine (1960, 1969) envisaged for a child acquiring ontological commitments. This is a different form of bootstrapping than is discussed in the language acquisition literature, which concerns a mapping problem of lexical items onto syntactic categories.

  5. The pyow-hack noises made by Putty-nosed monkeys that exist to warn of predators have been taken by some authors to constitute semantic combinatorics (see Arnold and Zuberbühler 2008); whilst the calls of Campbell’s monkeys have been taken to exhibit combinatorial organisation akin to a ‘proto-syntax’ (Ouattara et al. 2009). The following paper takes such semantic content to be qualitatively different from that of human semantics, this distinction is born out of having a grammatical mind with lexicalisation that affords new ways of using symbolic representations.

  6. For a discussion on FOXP2, a gene involved in speech production, see Lai et al. 2001; Enard et al. 2002; for other possible genetic mutations see Crow 2008. For a negative perspective on the role of FOXP2 in language evolution see Berwick 2011.

  7. The extent to which these approaches vary can be seen in the edited volumes Language Evolution (Christiansen and Kirby 2003a), The Biolinguistic Enterprise: New Perspectives on the Evolution and Nature of the Human Language Faculty (Di Sciullo and Boeckx 2011), and The Oxford Handbook of Language Evolution (Tallerman and Gibson 2012).

  8. Some authors argue that the imperfections in language can be reduced to conflicting interface conditions, and hence the imperfections become epiphenomenal, see Zeijlstra 2009 for discussion.

  9. Sound includes all articulatory modes for language expression, including signing or other non-vocal modes.

  10. This is not to claim that all concepts in adult cognition have their source in core-cognition. Once the system outlined in this paper is in place concepts can be formed independently of core-cognition systems.

  11. Note though that although we have endorsed a discontinuity thesis between core cognitive systems and later adult cognition, we do not wish to rule out the idea that the two cognitive systems are commensurable.

  12. For alternative views on lexicalisation see Pietroski (2005).

  13. Phi features are a subset of the universal feature set and are typically understood to be person, number, and gender features.

References

  • Arnold, K., & Zuberbühler, K. (2008). Meaningful call combinations in a non-human primate. Current Biology, 18(5), R202–R203.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Barth, H., Kanwisher, N., & Spelke, E. S. (2003). The construction of large number representations in adults. Cognition, 86, 201–221.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Beck, J. (2012). Do animals engage in conceptual thought? Philosophy Compass, 7, 218–229.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berwick, R. (2011). All you need is merge: Biology, computation, and language from the bottom up. In A. M. Di Sciullo & C. Boeckx (Eds.), The biolinguistic enterprise: New perspectives on the evolution and nature of the human language faculty (pp. 461–492). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berwick, R., & Chomsky, N. (2011). The biolinguistic program: The current state of its development. In A. M. Di Sciullo & C. Boeckx (Eds.), The biolinguistic enterprise: New perspectives on the evolution and nature of the human language faculty (pp. 19–41). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bloomfield, T. C., Gentner, T. Q., & Margoliash, D. (2011). What birds have to say about language? Nature Neuroscience, 14(8), 947–948.

    Article  CAS  PubMed Central  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Boeckx, C. (2008). Bare syntax. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boeckx, C. (2009). The nature of merge: Consequences for mind, language, and biology. In M. Piattelli-Palmarini, J. Uriagereka, & P. Salaburu (Eds.), Of minds and language: A dialogue with Noam Chomsky in the Basque Country (pp. 44–57). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boghossian, P. A. (1995). Content. In J. Kim & E. Sosa (Eds.), A companion to metaphysics (pp. 94–96). Oxford: Blackwell Publishers Ltd.

    Google Scholar 

  • Borer, H. (2005). Structuring sense (Vol. 2). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Burge, T. (2010). Origins of objectivity. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Byrne, R. W. (1995). The thinking ape. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carey, S. (2009). The origin of concepts. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Carruthers, P. (2006). The architecture of the mind. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Carruthers, P. (2011). Language in cognition. In E. Margolis, R. Samuels, & S. Stich (Eds.), The oxford handbook of philosophy of cognitive science (pp. 382–401). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, N. (1995). The minimalist program. Cambridge: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, N. (2005). Three factors in language design. Linguistic Inquiry, 36(1), 1–22.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, N. (2007). Approaching UG from below. In U. Sauerland & H. M. Gartner (Eds.), Interfaces + recursion = language?: Chomsky’s minimalism and the view from syntax-semantics (pp. 1–29). Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, N. (2008). On phases. In R. Freidin, C. Otero, & M. L. Zubzarreta (Eds.), Foundational issues in linguistic theory: Essays in honor of jean-roger vergnaud (pp. 133–166). Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Christiansen, M. H., & Kirby, S. (Eds.). (2003a). Language evolution. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Christiansen, M. H., & Kirby, S. (2003b). Language evolution: The hardest problem in science? In M. H. Christiansen & S. Kirby (Eds.), Language evolution (pp. 1–15). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Cinque, G. (1999). Adverbs and functional heads: A cross-linguistic perspective. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Crane, T. (1992). The nonconceptual content of experience. In T. Crane (Ed.), The contents of experience (pp. 136–157). New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Crow, T. J. (2008). The ‘big bang’ theory of the origin of psychosis and the faculty of language. Schizophrenia Research, 101, 31–52.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Di Sciullo, A. M., & Boeckx, C. (Eds.). (2011). The biolinguistic enterprise: New perspectives on the evolution and nature of the human language faculty. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dummett, M. (1994). Origins of analytical philosophy. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Enard, W., Przeworski, M., Fisher, S. E., Lai, C. S. L., Wiebe, V., Kitano, T., Monaco, A. P., & Pääbo, S. (2002). Molecular evolution of FOXP2, a gene involved in speech and language. Nature, 418, 869–872.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. A. (1975). The language of thought. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. A. (1980). On the Impossibility of acquiring “more powerful” structures: Fixation of belief and concept acquisition. In Piatelli-Palmerini (Ed.), Language and learning (pp. 142–162). Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gould, S. J., & Eldredge, N. (1977). Punctuated equilibria: the tempo and mode of evolution reconsidered. Paleobiology, 3(2), 115–151.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gould, S. J., & Lewontin, R. C. (1979). The spandrels of San Marco and the Panglossian paradigm: a critique of the adaptationist programme. Proceedings of the Royal Society. Biological Sciences, 205, 581–598.

    Article  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Hauser, M. D., & Carey, S. (2003). Spontaneous representations of small numbers of objects by rhesus macaques: examinations of content and format. Cognitive Psychology, 47(4), 367–401.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Hauser, M. D., Chomsky, N., & Fitch, W. T. (2002). The faculty of language; What is it, Who has it, and How did it evolve? Science, 298, 1569–1579.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Hauser, M. D., Tsao, F., Garcia, P., & Spelke, E. S. (2003). Evolutionary foundations of number: spontaneous representation of numerical magnitudes by cotton-top tamarins. Proceedings of the Royal Society, London, B, 270, 1441–1446.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hinzen, W. (2006). Mind design and minimal syntax. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Jackendoff, R., & Pinker, S. (2005). The nature of the language faculty and its implications for evolution of language (Reply to Fitch, Hauser, and Chomsky). Cognition, 97, 211–225.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, M. H., Bolhuis, J. J., & Horn, G. (1985). Interaction between acquired preferences and developing predispositions during imprinting. Animal Behaviour, 33, 1000–1006.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kayne, R. (1994). The antisymmetry of syntax. Cambridge: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lai, C. S. L., Fisher, S. E., Hurst, J. A., Vargha-Khadem, F., & Monaco, A. P. (2001). A forkhead-domain gene is mutated in a severe speech and language disorder. Nature, 413, 519–523.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Lieberman, P. (1968). Primate vocalizations and human linguistic ability. Journal of the Acoustical Society of American, 44, 1574–1584.

    Article  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Lieberman, P. (2003). Motor control, speech, and the evolution of human language. In M. Christiansen & S. Kirby (Eds.), Language evolution (pp. 255–271). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Macnamara, J. (1986). Border dispute: The place of logic in psychology. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marantz, A. (2000). Words. Ms., MIT.

  • Morton, J., Johnson, M. H., & Maurer, D. (1990). On the reasons for newborns’ responses to faces. Infant Behavior & Development, 13, 99–103.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ouattara, K., Lemasson, A., & Zuberbühler, K. (2009). Campbell’s monkeys concatenate vocalizations into context-specific call sequences. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 106(51), 22026–22031.

    Article  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Piaget, J. (1980). Language within cognition: Schemes of action and language learning. In M. Piatelli-Palmerini (Ed.), Language and learning (pp. 163–183). Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pietroski, P. M. (2005). Events and semantic architecture. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pinker, S. (2003). Language as an adaptation to the cognitive niche. In M. Christiansen & S. Kirby (Eds.), Language evolution (pp. 16–37). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Pinker, S., & Jackendoff, R. (2005). The faculty of language: What’s special about it? Cognition, 95, 201–236.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. O. (1960). Word and object. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. O. (1969). Ontological relativity and other essays. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Santos, L. (2004). Core Knowledges: a dissociation between spatiotemporal knowledge and contact-mechanics in a non-human primate? Developmental Science, 7, 167–174.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Sanz, C., Morgan, D., & Gulick, S. (2004). New insights into chimpanzees, tools, and termites from the Congo Basin. The American Naturalist, 164, 567–581.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Sigurðsson, H. Á. (2004). Meaningful silence, meaningless sounds. Linguistic Variation Yearbook, 4, 235–259.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Spelke, E. S. (2000). Core knowledge. American Psychologist, 55, 1233–1243.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Spelke, E. S. (2003). What makes humans smart? Core knowledge and natural language. In D. Gentner & S. Goldin-Meadow (Eds.), Language in mind (pp. 277–311). Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spelke, E. S., & Kinzler, K. D. (2007a). Core knowledge. Developmental Science, 10(1), 89–96.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Spelke, E. S., & Kinzler, K. D. (2007b). Core systems in human cognition. Progress in Brain Research, 164, 257–264.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Tallerman, M. (2007). Did our ancestors speak a holistic protolanguage? Lingua, 117(3), 579–604.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tallerman, M., & Gibson, K. R. (Eds.). (2012). The oxford handbook of language evolution. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tattersall, I. (2004). What happened in the origin of human consciousness. The Anatomical Record, Part B New Anatomy, 276B, 19–26.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Xu, F., & Spelke, E. (2000). Large number discrimination in 6-month-year-old infants. Cognition, 74, B1–B11.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Xu, F., Spelke, E., & Goddard, S. (2005). Number sense in human infants. Developmental Science, 8, 88–101.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Zeijlstra, H. (2009). Dislocation effects, uninterpretable features, functional heads, and parametric variation: consequences of conflicting interface conditions. In K. K. Grohmann (Ed.), InterPhases: Phase-theoretic investigations of linguistic interfaces (pp. 82–113). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Thomas J. Hughes.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Hughes, T.J., Miller, J.T.M. Lexicalisation and the Origin of the Human Mind. Biosemiotics 7, 11–27 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s12304-013-9189-1

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s12304-013-9189-1

Keywords

Navigation