Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Comment on Andreas von Hirsch: The Roles of Harm and Wrongdoing in Criminalisation Theory

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Criminal Law and Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Whereas liberals tend to emphasize harm as the decisive criterion for legitimizing criminalisation, moralists take a qualified notion of wrongfulness as sufficient even when no harm is at hand. This comment takes up Andreas von Hirsch’s “dual element approach” requiring both harm and wrongfulness as necessary conditions for criminalisation and argues that Joel Feinberg’s account of harming as violation of moral rights is perfectly compatible with it. Subsequently, two issues from the liberalism-moralism debate on criminalisation are examined: The difficulty of how to determine wrongfulness beyond the scope of harming, and the so far disregarded question of whether the democratic legislator is free within the framework of constitution to criminalise whatever conduct he wants to prevent irrespective of philosophical constraints.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. S. von Hirsch (2013), Harms and Wrongs doing as Reciprocal Constraints.

  2. von Hirsch (2013), Introduction.

  3. von Hirsch (2013), Introduction.

  4. von Hirsch (2013), text at fn. 19.

  5. von Hirsch (2013), Harm and ‘Resources’.

  6. von Hirsch (2013), Harm and Wrong doing as Reciprocal Constraints.

  7. I shall focus on this point below.

  8. von Hirsch (2013), Introduction.

  9. In German criminal law, this problem is discussed under the label of “Taeter hinter demTaeter” (perpetrator behind the perpetrator). To be held criminally responsible, the indirect originator of a harmful act can be treated as perpetrator only if he somehow dominated the immediate actor.

  10. In Harm to Others, Feinberg includes a chapter on “Fairly Imputing Harms” (Feinberg [1984], 218 ff.), but it only comprehends sketches concerning special cases of harming.

  11. Feinberg (1984), 36.

  12. Feinberg (1984), 9.

  13. Feinberg (1984), 110 f.

  14. Feinberg (1990a, 1990b and 1990c).

  15. von Hirsch (2013), Introduction.

  16. Cf. Feinberg (1984), 9.

  17. S. Simester/von Hirsch (2011), and von Hirsch (2013), Wrongfulness Judgements in Criminalisation Theory.

  18. See von Hirsch (2013): “Harm and wrongdoing as reciprocal constraints“. Cf. also Duff (2007), 83 f., where he interprets the wrongfulness criterion in Feinberg’s harm principle as a “side constraint of justice”.

  19. Paradigmatic Moore’s confidence in emotions as reliable indicators for the objective immorality of an act: See Moore (1997), 183.

  20. Concerning the notion of pure moralism see Feinberg (1988), 8.

  21. See Moore (1997), 127-138, 183.

  22. Regarding the mentioned three groups of wrongful actions see Duff (2013), Criminalisation and Wrong doing.

  23. Duff (2013), text at fn. 38.

  24. Duff (2013), Concluding Comments.

  25. Duff (2013), Concluding Comments.

  26. Cf. Duff (2007), 88.

  27. Duff (2013), Concluding Comments.

  28. von Hirsch (2013), Legal Moralism and Public Discourse; Duff (2013), Concluding Comments.

  29. Here it must be added that the German legislator is meant to be free in deciding what is a Rechtsgut.

  30. Bundesverfassungsgericht, Entscheidungen, vol. 120, p. 224 ff., Rn. 35. This is the incest-decision already mentioned by von Hirsch.

  31. BVerfGE 120, 224 ff., Rn. 38 f.

  32. Gaerditz (2010), 362.

  33. At least if the respective legislation complies with the principle of proportionality—a condition the Bundesverfassungsgericht set up for the legitimacy of any state act, but never used to declare a criminal provision unconstitutional.

References

  • Duff, R.A. (2007). Answering for Crime. Responsibility and Liability in the Criminal Law. Oxford and Portland/Oregon: Hart Publishing.

  • Duff, R.A. (2013).Towards a Modest Legal Moralism. doi:10.1007/s11572-012-9191-8.

  • Feinberg, J. (1984). Harm to Others. The Moral Limits of the Criminal Law, vol. 1. New York/Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Feinberg, J. (1988). Harmless Wrongdoing. The Moral Limits of the Criminal Law, vol 4. New York, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Feinberg, J. (1990a). In Defense of Moral Rights: Their bare Existence. In Freedom & Fulfillment. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

  • Feinberg, J. (1990b). In Defense of Moral Rights: Their Social Importance. In Freedom & Fulfillment. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

  • Feinberg, J. (1990c). In Defense of Moral Rights: Their Constitutional Relevance. In Freedom & Fulfillment. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

  • Gaerditz, K.F. (2010). Strafbegründung und Demokratieprinzip. Der Staat 49, p. 331–367.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moore, M. (1997). Placing Blame. A General Theory of the Criminal Law. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • von Hirsch, A. (2013). Harm and Wrongdoing in Criminalisation Theory. doi:10.1007/s11572-012-9192-7.

  • Simester, A. and von Hirsch, A. (2011). Crimes, Harms, and Wrongs. On the Principles of Criminalisation. Oxford: Hart Publishing.

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Gerhard Seher.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Seher, G. Comment on Andreas von Hirsch: The Roles of Harm and Wrongdoing in Criminalisation Theory. Criminal Law, Philosophy 8, 257–264 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11572-013-9205-1

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11572-013-9205-1

Keywords

Navigation