Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Abstract

Rawls says that public reason is the reason of the citizens of a democratic state and takes the Supreme Court in the USA as the exemplar of public reason. It differs from non public reason, which is used e.g., in universities and academic institutions. Rawls contrasts with Kant, which opposes the public reason of the scholar—or the philosopher—, who speaks before the world, to the private reason of state or church officials. The later, once they accept an authority, cannot think by themselves (selbst denken). A closer examination shows that Rawls is not so far from Kant as it seems, because he takes the constitutional judges not as they are, but as they should be. However Rawls still apparently refuses Kant’s unity of reason. Further investigation of the relations between ethical reason, democratic reason and legal reason is needed. Democratic reason is tantamount both to public reason and to legal reason in a modern constitutional state. It is a requirement of ethics but still not identical with ethical reason, since it is possible to accept democratic reason and to argue against it from an ethical point of view. There is just one good way of reasoning, in spite of the constraints that the sources of law and the rules of procedure impose on legal reasoning, compared with ethics. Such constraints are based on the democratic principle, which is again based on ethical reason, which at last both grounds and limits the constraints that law imposes on reason.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Rawls returned to the same topic in “The Idea of Public Reason Revisited” in Rawls [11, pp. 129–180] and again in Rawls [12, pp. 26–29, 89–94].

  2. On public reason in Kant, see Onora O'Neil [8, chap. 2; 9, pp. 282ff.].

  3. See the commentary of Ernst Tugenhat [13, p. 144].

References

  1. Dahl, Robert. 1989. Democracy and its critics. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Kant. 1902. Kant’s gesammelten Schriften [Akademie-Ausgabe]. Berlin: Reimer, later: de Gruyter.

  3. Kant. 1784. Beantwortung der Frage: Was ist Auflärung? [A]. In Kant 2, VIII, 33–42.

  4. Kant. 1786. Was heißt: sich im Denken orientieren? [A]. In Kant 2, VIII, 131–47.

  5. Kant. 1785. Grundlegung zur Methaphysik der Sitten [A, B 1786]. In Kant 2, IV, 385–463].

  6. Kant. 1795. Zum ewigen Frieden [A, B 1796]. In Kant 2, VIII, 341–386.

  7. Kant. 1798 Der Streit der Fakultäten [A]. In Kant 2, VII, 1–116.

  8. O’Neil, Onora. 1989. Constructions of reason. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  9. O’Neil, Onora. 1989. Reason and autonomy in Grundlegung iii. In Grundlegung zur Methaphysik der Sitten. Ein kooperativer Kommentar, ed. Höffe, Otfried, Frankfurt am Main: Klostermann.

  10. Rawls, John. 1993. Political liberalism. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Rawls, John. 1999. The law of peoples. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Rawls, John. 2001. Justice as fairness. In A restatement, ed. Erin Kelly. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Belknap.

  13. Tugenhat, Ernst. 1993. Vorlesung über ethik. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to José de Sousa e Brito.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

de Sousa e Brito, J. Public Reason Between Ethics and Law. Int J Semiot Law 25, 465–472 (2012). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11196-011-9235-8

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11196-011-9235-8

Keywords

Navigation