Skip to main content
Log in

Truth promoting non-evidential reasons for belief

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Sometimes a belief that p promotes having true beliefs, whether or not p is true. This gives reasons to believe that p, but most epistemologists would deny that it gives epistemic reasons, or that these reasons can epistemically justify the belief that p. Call these reasons to believe “truth promoting non-evidential reasons for belief.” This paper argues that three common views in epistemology, taken together, entail that reasons of this sort can epistemically justify beliefs. These three claims are: epistemic oughts are normative, epistemic oughts have a source, and the source of epistemic oughts is an end that has true belief as a necessary component. These claims would be hard for many epistemologists to deny, but accepting them, and thus accepting that truth promoting non-evidential reasons can justify beliefs, has significant consequences for epistemology. The paper considers accounts of epistemic oughts that endorse these claims but might seem to avoid the consequence that truth promoting non-evidential reasons generate real epistemic oughts, and shows that none do.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. There are also reasons against belief analogous to TPR. One has such reasons against believing p when the belief that p promotes believing what is false. I won’t discuss these, although I do think they will generate epistemic oughts in much the same way TPR do.

  2. I’m not the first to note that certain epistemic ends would generate TPR. This comes up, for example, in papers by Richard Fumerton (2001) and Marian David (2001); Fumerton’s paper in fact is the source of one of the examples I use below (noted in a footnote). However, previous work on the topic considers a narrower range of epistemic ends than this paper, and doesn’t really engage with the questions of whether TPR can generate oughts or if these could be epistemic. Further, this previous work tends to be dismissive of the possibility that we ought to believe on our TPR, being more interested in epistemic oughts that are intuitive. This paper, on the other hand, is less concerned with intuitions about epistemic oughts and more with what oughts have normative force and why.

  3. Some readers have indicated that they find these objections distracting, that one or another of them seems to make my argument a non-starter. If you feel similarly, I suggest skipping ahead now to the section where I respond to the relevant objection and then returning here. Most of my responses to objections don’t rely on the points I make between here and there.

  4. This argument comes from Fumerton (2001). Interestingly, Foley, who seems to assume that synchronic epistemic ends cannot generate TPR, does say that synchronic epistemic ends can give one epistemic reasons that are not evidence. He says that one has epistemic reasons but not evidence to believe p in a situation where, were one to believe p, p would likely be true, and were one to not believe p, p would likely be false (Foley 1992, pp. 29–30). These reasons aren’t TPR because they don’t arise from p’s promoting other true beliefs, but allowing for these reasons does suggest that, if Foley had considered the possibility of dependence relations between beliefs, he would agree that synchronic epistemic ends generate TPR.

  5. One might have a parallel view according to which beliefs aim at knowledge.

  6. This is perhaps metaphorical. Wedgwood says that believers take themselves to be committed to this goal, so perhaps this is not an aim of belief but of believers. On the other hand, Wedgwood talks about correctness standards that are built into belief itself, which function like epistemic aims of belief. My argument works if we substitute either of these in where I talk about the aim of belief or epistemic ends.

  7. I’ll address later in the paper the special case where TPR make it so that we ought to believe some claim that we have conclusive evidence against.

  8. For those familiar with Wedgwood’s paper, Wedgwood might describe the e-pistemic ought as an ought that applies to a belief and arises out of the correctness standard for that belief alone.

  9. Thank you to Julia Staffel for pointing out this objection.

  10. See Turri (2009) for a very clear example. I could just as well cite a tedious number of other articles.

  11. The claim about the connection between knowledge and justification is not completely uncontroversial; see, e.g. Kornblith (2008).

  12. When an agent luckily believes a truth, what’s accidental or out of an agent’s control is not the truth of the proposition that the agent believed, but rather that the agent ended up believing a proposition that is true.

  13. Pritchard and some others advocate an alternate view of luck. On this view, an event’s being lucky has to do with the fact that the event doesn’t occur in most nearby possible worlds (Pritchard 2004). I think this account is problematic, because I have a hard time seeing why it matters that one is lucky in this way (as long as such luck doesn’t eliminate one’s justification). That said, I suspect that, given a plausible understanding of what possible worlds are nearby, t-pistemically justified beliefs that turn out true will also be lucky in this modal sense. However, I’m uncomfortable making arguments based on a particular view of the ordering of possible worlds, and so I will refer readers who agree with Pritchard to my trump argument at the end of this section. (Note that discussions of the ordering of possible worlds also pose a problem for those defending a modal view of luck and knowledge like Pritchard’s; see e.g. Baumann 2008).

  14. My thanks to an anonymous referee for making this worry salient for me.

  15. One may be able to generate cases for other sorts of beings—beings with almost no beliefs, for example—where their beliefs against conclusive evidence are justified by fewer epistemic benefits. But these won’t present compelling objections to my arguments.

  16. I’ve been asked if this doesn’t render my findings in this paper uninteresting, as TPR can generate oughts only in very rare circumstances. However, remember that TPR can also make it the case that we ought to believe propositions for which we have insufficient evidence. Cases in which such beliefs are justified by TPR may be much more common.

  17. This is a view sometimes called “threshold deontology” or “moderate deontology” (Alexander 2000), and I’m assured that it is the majority, although not consensus, view among deontologists (White 2009). Moore (1989), Nagel (1979), and Nozick (1974) are supposed to have held such a view (Alexander 2000).

  18. One additional worry would be that, if TPR were epistemic reasons, then it turns out that Pascal’s Wager might show that we have epistemic reasons to believe in God: perhaps we can expect that God will reward believers, but not unbelievers, with infinite true beliefs in the afterlife. (Thanks to an anonymous referee for raising this issue) This would be a surprising consequence, since Pascal’s Wager is traditionally taken to be an argument for theistic belief based in practical, not epistemic, reasons. However, I don’t think anyone should find this consequence to be unacceptable. There is a large literature on Pascal’s Wager which shows that the Wager does not justify belief in God in the practical sense; for example, it is often argued that the balance of our reasons doesn’t favor belief in God over alternate deities. The arguments in this literature will generally be able to be adapted to show that the Wager does not justify belief in God in the epistemic sense as well, even if TPR can justify beliefs.

  19. We can imagine cases in which one has practical reasons to follow one’s epistemic oughts; e.g. if one were paid to do so.

  20. They either deny doxastic involuntarism, or think that it is irrelevant to whether or not we have reasons to believe. I won’t address involuntarism because of this.

References

  • Adler, J. E. (2002). Belief’s own ethics. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alexander, L. (2000). Deontology at the threshold. San Diego Law Review, 37, 893–912.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alston, W. P. (1989). Epistemic justification: Essays in the theory of knowledge. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alston, W. P. (2005). Beyond “justification:” Dimensions of epistemic evaluation. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baumann, P. (2008). Is knowledge safe? American Philosophical Quarterly, 45, 19–30.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bishop, M. A., & Trout, J. D. (2005). Epistemology and psychology of human judgment. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Brady, M. S. (2009). Curiosity and the value of truth. In A. Haddock, et al. (Eds.), Epistemic value. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Conee, E. (1992). The truth connection. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 62, 657–669.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Conee, E., & Feldman, R. (1985). Evidentialism. Philosophical Studies, 48, 15–34.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • David, M. (2001). Truth as the epistemic goal. In M. Steup (Ed.), Knowledge, truth, and duty. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elgin, C. C. (2009). Is understanding factive? In A. Haddock, et al. (Eds.), Epistemic value. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feldman, R. (2000). The ethics of belief. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 60, 667–695.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Foley, R. (1987). The theory of epistemic rationality. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Foley, R. (1992). Working without a net. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fumerton, R. (2001). Epistemic justification and normativity. In M. Steup (Ed.), Knowledge, truth, and duty: Essays on epistemic justification, responsibility, and virtue. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. I. (1979). What is justified belief? In G. Pappas (Ed.), Justification and knowledge. Dordrecht: Riedel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. (2002). The unity of the epistemic virtues, in his pathways to knowledge. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Grimm, S. R. (2009). Epistemic normativity. In A. Haddock, et al. (Eds.), Epistemic value. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jones, W. E. (2009). The goods and the motivation of believing. In A. Haddock, et al. (Eds.), Epistemic value. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelly, T. (2003). Epistemic rationality as instrumental rationality. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 76, 612–640.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kornblith, H. (2008). Knowledge needs no justification. In Q. Smith (Ed.), Epistemology: New essays. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kvanvig, J. L. (2003). The value of knowledge the pursuit of understanding. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kvanvig, J. L. (2005). Truth and the epistemic goal. In Matthias. Steup & Ernest. Sosa (Eds.), Contemporary debates in epistemology. Malden: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lynch, M. P. (2004). True to life: Why truth matters. Cambridge: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moore, M. S. (1989). Torture and the balance of evils. Israel Law Review, 23, 297–334.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moran, R. (2001). Authority and estrangement. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, T. (1979). Mortal questions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nozick, R. (1974). Anarchy, state, and Utopia. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oddie, G. (1997). Conditionalization, cogency, and cognitive value. British Journal of the Philosophy of Science, 48, 533–541.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pritchard, D. (2004). Epistemic luck. Journal of Philosophical Research, 29, 193–222.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pritchard, D. (2009). Knowledge, understanding, and epistemic value. Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement, 64, 19–43.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Riggs, W. D. (2002). Reliability and the value of knowledge. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 64, 79–96.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shah, N. (2003). How truth governs belief. Philosophical Review, 112, 447–482.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shah, N. (2006). A new argument for evidentialism. The Philosophical Quarterly, 56, 481–498.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sosa, E. (2007). A virtue epistemology: Apt belief and reflective knowledge. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, S. E., & Brown, J. D. (1988). Illusion and well-being: A social perspective on mental health. Psychological Bulletin, 103, 193–210.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Turri, J. (2009). The ontology of epistemic reasons. Nous, 43, 490–512.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Velleman, J. D. (2000). The possibility of practical reason. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wedgwood, R. (2002). The aim of belief. Philosophical Perspectives, 16, 267–297.

    Google Scholar 

  • White, M. D. (2009). Deontology. In J. Pell & I. van Staveren (Eds.), Handbook of economics and ethics. Cheltenham: Edward Elgar.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zagzebski, L. (2003). The search for the source of epistemic good. Metaphilosophy, 34, 12–28.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I would like to thank Julia Staffel, Dom Bailey, Justin Snedegar, Chris Heathwood, Eric Chwang, Graham Oddie, Michael Tooley, and a number of conference participants whose names I don’t know for their comments on drafts or presentations of this paper. I’d also like to thank all the participants in my 2011 epistemology seminar for inspiring me to think through these issues.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Brian Talbot.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Talbot, B. Truth promoting non-evidential reasons for belief. Philos Stud 168, 599–618 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-013-0139-1

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-013-0139-1

Keywords

Navigation