Skip to main content
Log in

Robots and reality: a reply to Robert Sparrow

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Ethics and Information Technology Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

We commonly identify something seriously defective in a human life that is lived in ignorance of important but unpalatable truths. At the same time, some degree of misapprehension of reality may be necessary for individual health and success. Morally speaking, it is unclear just how insistent we should be about seeking the truth. Robert Sparrow has considered such issues in discussing the manufacture and marketing of robot ‘pets’, such as Sony’s doglike ‘AIBO’ toy and whatever more advanced devices may supersede it. Though it is not his only concern, Sparrow particularly criticizes such robot pets for their illusory appearance of being living things. He fears that some individuals will subconsciously buy into the illusion, and come to sentimentalize interactions that fail to constitute genuine relationships. In replying to Sparrow, I emphasize that this would be continuous with much of the minor sentimentality that we already indulge in from day to day. Although a disposition to seek the truth is morally virtuous, the virtue concerned must allow for at least some categories of exceptions. Despite Sparrow’s concerns about robot pets (and robotics more generally), we should be lenient about familiar, relatively benign, kinds of self-indulgence in forming beliefs about reality. Sentimentality about robot pets seems to fall within these categories. Such limited self-indulgence can co-exist with ordinary honesty and commitment to truth.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Sparrow (2002).

  2. Sparrow, Robot Dogs, p. 308.

  3. Sparrow, Robot Dogs, p. 316.

  4. Sparrow and Sparrow (2006).

  5. Most recently: Sparrow (2009).

  6. Sparrow, Robot Dogs, pp. 308–309.

  7. Sparrow and Sparrow, In the Hands of Machines, pp. 151–153.

  8. Sparrow, Robot Dogs, pp. 316–317.

  9. Levy (2007).

  10. Sparrow, Robot Dogs, pp. 309–312.

  11. Sparrow, Robot Dogs, pp. 313–314.

  12. Sparrow, Robot Dogs, pp. 315.

  13. For the complexities of any concept of self-deception and the difficulties of holding agents responsible for being self-deceived, see Levy (2004).

  14. Sparrow, Robot Dogs, pp. 315.

  15. Sparrow, Robot Dogs, pp 315.

  16. Again, I don't suggest that this is the only argument available to Sparrow, or the only argument that he relies upon. It is, however, a central argument, and its acceptance would commit us to the kind of puritanism about truth that I am attempting to identify and criticize.

  17. Hofstadter (1995), p. 157.

  18. Sparrow, Robot Dogs: 315. See also Sparrow and Sparrow, In the Hands of Machines, p. 155.

  19. See, e.g., Taylor and Brown (1988), p. 196.

  20. Taylor and Brown (1988); Snyder and Higgins (1988).

  21. Taylor and Brown (1988), pp. 194, 197–199.

  22. Snyder and Higgins, Excuses: 32 (emphasis in the text).

  23. Sparrow, Robot Dogs, p. 315.

  24. Kant (1948).

  25. Compare the discussion of fictive judgments and critical contexts in Joyce (2001), pp. 190–194.

  26. Levy, Self-Deception, pp. 297–98.

  27. Nozick (1974).

  28. Nozick, Anarchy, State, and Utopia, p. 45.

  29. The Matrix Reloaded (2003) and The Matrix Revolutions (2003).

  30. This is surveyed in Blackford (2004).

  31. McMahon (2002), p. 177.

  32. Similar misfortunes are discussed in another context by Nagel (1979), p. 4–6.

  33. Benson and Stangroom (2006), pp. 179–80.

  34. E.g., Taylor and Brown, Illusion and Well-Being, p. 195.

  35. Compare Joyce's discussion of the instrumental value of truth Joyce (2001), pp. 178–179.

  36. Clifford (1999), pp. 70–71.

  37. Clifford (1999), pp. 70–71.

  38. Clifford (1999), pp. 73–74. Compare Joyce (2001), p. 179.

  39. These examples are mentioned by Sparrow, Robot Dogs, p. 312.

  40. Benson and Stangroom (2006)

  41. Glover (2001).

  42. Mackie (1977).

  43. See generally Hofstadter, The Ineradicable Eliza Effect and Its Dangers.

References

  • Benson, O., & Stangroom, J. (2006). Why truth matters (pp. 164–165). London and New York: Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blackford, R. (2004). Try the Blue Pill: What’s wrong with life in a simulation? In M. Kapell & W. G. Doty (Eds.), Jacking into the matrix Franchise: Cultural reception and interpretation (pp. 169–182). New York: Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clifford, W. K. (1999) The ethics of belief. First published 1876. In The ethics of belief and other essays (pp. 70–96). Amherst: Prometheus Books.

  • Glover, J. (2001). Humanity: A moral history of the twentieth century. First published 1999 (pp. 362–363). London: Pimlico.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hofstadter, D. (1995). Preface 4: The ineradicable Eliza effect and its dangers. In D. Hofstadter & The Fluid Analogies Research Group, (Eds.), Fluid concepts and creative analogies: Computer models of the fundamental mechanisms of thought (pp. 155–168). New York: BasicBooks.

  • Joyce, R. (2001). The myth of morality (pp. 190–194). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (1948) Groundwork of the metaphysic of morals. First published 1785 (H. J. Paton, Trans.). London: Routledge.

  • Levy, N. (2004). Self-deception and moral responsibility. Ratio XVII: 294–311.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levy, D. (2007). Love and sex with robots: The evolution of human-robot relationships. New York: HarperCollins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mackie, J. L. (1977). Ethics: Inventing right and wrong. London: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • McMahon, J. L. (2002). Popping a bitter pill: Existential authenticity in The Matrix and Nausea. In W. Irwin (Ed.), The matrix and philosophy: Welcome to the desert of the real (pp. 166–177). Chicago: Open Court.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, T. (1979). Death. In Mortal Questions (pp. 1–10). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Nozick, R. (1974). Anarchy, state, and utopia (pp. 42–45). New York: Basic Books.

  • Snyder, C. R., & Higgins, R. L. (1988). Excuses: Their effective role in the negotiation of reality. Psychological Bulletin, 104, 23–35.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sparrow, R. (2002). The March of the robot dogs. Ethics and Information Technology, 4, 305–318.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sparrow, R. (2009). Predators or plowshares? Time to consider arms control of robotic weapons. IEEE Technology and Society, 28, 25–29.

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Sparrow, R., & Sparrow, L. (2006). In the hands of machines? The future of aged care. Minds and Machines, 16, 141–161.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, S. E., & Brown, J. D. (1988). Illusion and well-being: A social psychological perspective on mental health. Psychological Bulletin, 103, 193–210.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I wish to thank Rob Sparrow for his encouragement and assistance in personal communications regarding the subject matter of this paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Russell Blackford.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Blackford, R. Robots and reality: a reply to Robert Sparrow. Ethics Inf Technol 14, 41–51 (2012). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10676-011-9266-6

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10676-011-9266-6

Keywords

Navigation