Skip to main content
Log in

Weighted values and the core in NTU games

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
International Journal of Game Theory Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Monderer et al. (Int J Game Theory 21(1):27–39, 1992) proved that the core is included in the set of the weighted Shapley values in TU games. The purpose of this paper is to extend this result to NTU games. We first show that the core is included in the closure of the positively weighted egalitarian solutions introduced by Kalai and Samet (Econometrica 53(2):307–327, 1985). Next, we show that the weighted version of the Shapley NTU value by Shapley (La Decision, aggregation et dynamique des ordres de preference, Editions du Centre National de la Recherche Scientifique, Paris, pp 251–263, 1969) does not always include the core. These results indicate that, in view of the relationship to the core, the egalitarian solution is a more desirable extension of the weighted Shapley value to NTU games. As a byproduct of our approach, we also clarify the relationship between the core and marginal contributions in NTU games. We show that, if the attainable payoff for the grand coalition is represented as a closed-half space, then any element of the core is attainable as the expected value of marginal contributions.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Section 1 of Chang and Chen (2013) discusses this criterion in detail.

  2. Otten et al. (1998) also raised this open question in their concluding remarks.

  3. If we calculate the expected value of marginal contributions by using this probability in TU games, then we obtain the weighted Shapley value; see Kalai and Samet (1987).

  4. We explain the motivation for this function. Our final goal is to find a sequence of weights with which the weighted values converge to x. Suppose that \(\tilde{\varPsi }_i(w)>0\), i.e., \(x_i>\psi ^w(V)\). This means that the value assigned by a given weight vector to player i falls short of i’s payoff in the core outcome x. Then, the function g requires that the weight assigned to i should be increased.

  5. To check this fact, let \(x\in V(S)\) be fixed and let \(\bar{\lambda }\) be the vector such that \(\bar{\lambda }_i=1\) if \(x_i<0\) and \(\bar{\lambda }_i=0\) otherwise. Then, \(x\cdot \bar{\lambda }\le x\cdot \lambda (x^k) \le x^k \cdot \lambda (x^k)\) for all \(k=1,2, \ldots \).

  6. The basic idea of the sequence \(x^m\) is the following: from the vector x, we decrease the payoff of j by m, while increase the payoff of \(i'\) so that the resulting vector is in \(\partial V(S)\). We can show that \(x^m\) always exists by N1 (proper subset), N2 (convex) and N3.

  7. Note that \(T^1\ne \emptyset \), because \(\sum _{i\in N}w^k_i=1\) for all \(k=1, 2, \ldots \).

References

  • Chang C, Chen P (2013) The lambda-nucleolus for non-transferable utility games and Shapley procedure. http://www.saet.uiowa.edu/event-14/

  • Harsanyi JC (1963) A simplified bargaining model for the \(n\)-person cooperative game. Int Econ Rev 4:194–220

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hart S, Mas-Colell A (1989) Potential, value and consistency. Econometrica 57:589–614

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hinojosa MA, Romero E, Zarzuelo JM (2012) Consistency of the Harsanyi NTU configuration value. Games Econ Behav 76(2):665–677

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jehle GA, Reny PJ (2011) Advanced microeconomic theory, 3rd edn. Pearson, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Kalai E, Samet D (1985) Monotonic solutions to general cooperative games. Econometrica 53(2):307–327

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kalai E, Samet D (1987) On weighted Shapley values. Int J Game Theory 16(3):205–222

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maschler M, Owen G (1989) The consistent Shapley value for hyperplane games. Int J Game Theory 18(4):389–407

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maschler M, Owen G (1992) The consistent Shapley value for games without side payments. In: Rational interaction. Springer, Berlin, pp 5–12

  • Masuzawa T (2012) Strong convexity of NTU games. Int J Game Theory 41(3):699–705

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Monderer D, Samet D, Shapley LS (1992) Weighted values and the core. Int J Game Theory 21(1):27–39

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Otten GJ, Borm P, Peleg B, Tijs S (1998) The MC-value for monotonic NTU-games. Int J Game Theory 27(1):37–47

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peleg B, Sudhöter P (2007) Introduction to the theory of cooperative games, 2nd edn. Springer, Berlin

    Google Scholar 

  • Pérez-Castrillo D, Wettstein D (2006) An ordinal Shapley value for economic environments. J Econ Theory 127(1):296–308

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shapley LS (1953) A value for n-person games. In: Roth AE (ed) The Shapley value. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 41–48

    Google Scholar 

  • Shapley LS (1969) Utility comparison and the theory of games. In: La Decision, aggregation et dynamique des ordres de preference, Editions du Centre National de la Recherche Scientifique, Paris, pp 251–263

  • Sharkey WW (1981) Convex games without side payments. Int J Game Theory 10(2):101–106

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vilkov VB (1977) Convex games without side payments. Vestnik Leningradskiva Universitata 7:2124 (in Russian)

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Koji Yokote.

Additional information

K. Yokote thanks Yukihiko Funaki, Yasushi Agatsuma and two anonymous referees for their valuable comments. The author would like to acknowledge the financial support provided by the Japan Society for the Promotion of Science (JSPS).

Appendix

Appendix

Proof of Claim 1

Let \(V\in \mathcal {G}\), \(S\subseteq N\), \(|S|\ge 2\), \(j\in S\) and \(z\in \mathbb {R}^{S\backslash \{j\}}\). We define \(Y\subseteq \mathbb {R}\) by

$$\begin{aligned} Y=\left\{ r\in \mathbb {R}: \left( (z_k)_{k\in S\backslash \{j\}}, r\right) \in V(S)\right\} \end{aligned}$$

By N2 (closed), Y is closed. Thus, to prove Claim 1, it suffices to prove that Y is bounded from above and non-empty.

Let \(x\in \partial V(S)\). By N2 (convex), there exists a normal vector \(\lambda \) such that

$$\begin{aligned} V(S)\subseteq \{y\in \mathbb {R}^S: y\cdot \lambda \le x\cdot \lambda \}. \end{aligned}$$

Moreover, by N3, there exists \(\delta >0\) such that \(\lambda _j\ge \delta \). It follows that Y is bounded from above.

We prove \(Y\ne \emptyset \), i.e., there exists \(r \in \mathbb {R}\) such that \(\left( (z_k)_{k\in S\backslash \{j\}}, r\right) \in V(S)\). Assume, by way of contradiction, that for any \(r\in \mathbb {R}\), \(\left( (z_k)_{k\in S\backslash \{j\}}, r\right) \notin V(S)\). We define \(Z\subseteq \mathbb {R}^S\) by

$$\begin{aligned} Z=\left\{ \left( (z_k)_{k\in S\backslash \{j\}}, r\right) : r\in \mathbb {R}\right\} . \end{aligned}$$

The two sets V(S) and Z are convex, and the intersection between the two sets is empty. By the separation theorem, there exists \(p\in \mathbb {R}^S\), \(p\ne \mathbf {0}\), such that

$$\begin{aligned} p\cdot x \le p\cdot y \quad \text {for all } x\in V(S), y\in Z. \end{aligned}$$
(16)

Suppose that \(p_j>0\). Then, by taking an arbitrary sequence \(\{y^k\}_{k=1}^\infty \subseteq Z\) such that \(y_j^k \rightarrow -\infty \), we have \(p\cdot y^k\rightarrow -\infty \), which contradicts Eq. (16). Similarly, if we suppose that \(p_j<0\), we have a contradiction with Eq. (16). As a result, \(p_j=0\).

Suppose to the contrary that \(p_i<0\) for some \(i\in S\backslash \{j\}\). Consider the sequence \(\{x^l\}_{l=1}^\infty \subseteq V(S)\) such that \(x_i^l\rightarrow -\infty \) and \(x_h^l=x_h^{l+1}\) for all \(h\in S\), \(h\ne i\), \(l=1,2,\ldots \). By N2 (comprehensive), such a sequence always exists. Then, \(p\cdot x^l\rightarrow +\infty \), which contradicts Eq. (16). It follows that \(p\ge \mathbf {0}\). Since \(p\ne \mathbf {0}\), there exists a player \(i'\in S\backslash \{j\}\) such that \(p_{i'}>0\).

Let \(x\in \partial V(S)\) be arbitrarily given. For any \(m \in \mathbb {N}\), let \(\tilde{x}^m\) denote the following vector:

$$\begin{aligned} \tilde{x}^m_j=x_j-m, \tilde{x}^m_i=x_i \quad \text {for all } i\in S\backslash \{j\}. \end{aligned}$$

By N2 (comprehensive), \(\tilde{x}^m \in V(S)\). Then, for any \(m\in \mathbb {N}\), there exists \(x^m\) such thatFootnote 6

$$\begin{aligned} x^m_j&=\tilde{x}_j^m, \\ x^m_h&=x_h \quad \text {for all } h\in S, h\ne i', h\ne j, \\ x^m&\in \partial V(S). \end{aligned}$$

Consider the sequence \(\{x^m\}_{m=1}^\infty \subseteq \partial V(S)\). Since \(x^m_j\rightarrow -\infty \), by N4, we have \(x^m_{i'} \rightarrow +\infty \). Since \(p_j=0\) and \(p_{i'}>0\), we have \(p\cdot x^m\rightarrow +\infty \), which contradicts Eq. (16). \(\square \)

Proof of Claim 2

The proof of \(\Omega (v)\subseteq cl \mathcal {W}(v)\) is given by Theorem 4 of Kalai and Samet (1987). We prove the converse set-inclusion. Let \(x\in cl \mathcal {W}(v)\). Then, there exists a sequence \(\{w^k\}_{k=1}^\infty \subseteq \varDelta ^N_{++}\) such that

$$\begin{aligned} x=\lim _{k\rightarrow \infty }\phi ^{w^k}(v). \end{aligned}$$

Since \(\{w^k\}_{k=1}^\infty \subseteq \varDelta ^N_{++}\) is a bounded sequence, there exists a convergent subsequence. Assume, for notational simplicity, that \(\{w^k\}_{k=1}^\infty \) itself converges. Let \(w^*\) denote the limit point.

Suppose that \(w^*_i>0\) for all \(i\in N\). Then, by letting \(\omega =(\{N\}, w^*)\), we have

$$\begin{aligned} \lim _{k\rightarrow \infty }\phi ^{w^k}(v)=\phi ^\omega (v), \end{aligned}$$

which implies that \(x\in \Omega (v)\).

Suppose that \(w^*_i=0\) for some \(i\in N\). We define the ordered partition \(\{T^r, T^{r-1}, \ldots , T^1\}\) of N inductively as follows:Footnote 7

$$\begin{aligned} T^1=\{i\in N: \lim _{k\rightarrow \infty }w^k_i>0\}, \end{aligned}$$

and, for each \(q=2, \ldots , r\), given that \(T^s\), \(1\le s\le q-1\), is determined, we define

$$\begin{aligned} T^q=\left\{ i\in N\backslash \cup _{s=1}^{q-1} T^s: \lim _{k\rightarrow \infty } \frac{w_i^k}{\sum _{j\in N\backslash \cup _{s=1}^{q-1} T^s}w_j^k}>0\right\} . \end{aligned}$$

We remark that, for each \(q=2, \ldots , r\), and \(i\in N\backslash \cup _{s=1}^{q-1} T^s\), the sequence

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{w_i^k}{\sum _{j\in N\backslash \cup _{s=1}^{q-1} T^s}w_j^k}, \text { } k=1, 2, \ldots , \end{aligned}$$

is bounded. So, if the above sequence does not converge, we can choose a convergent subsequence. For simplicity we assume that the above sequence always converges. Since N and r are finite, the above inductive definition is well-defined. For each \(q=1, \ldots , r\), we define \(w^{T^q}\in \varDelta ^{T^q}_{++}\) by

$$\begin{aligned} w^{T^q}_i=\lim _{k\rightarrow \infty } \frac{w_i^k}{\sum _{j\in N\backslash \cup _{s=1}^{q-1} T^s}w_j^k} \quad \text {for all } i\in T^q. \end{aligned}$$

We define the generalized weight vector \(\omega \) by

$$\begin{aligned} \omega =(T^r, \ldots , T^1, w^{T^r}, \ldots , w^{T^1}). \end{aligned}$$

We prove that, for any \(i\in T^q\), \(q=1, \ldots , r\),

$$\begin{aligned} \lim _{k\rightarrow \infty }\phi ^{w^k}_i(v)=\phi ^\omega _i(v). \end{aligned}$$

Choose an arbitrary \(q\in \{1, \ldots , r\}\) and \(i\in T^q\). Let \(S\subseteq N\), \(S\ne \emptyset \). If \(i\notin S\), then \(\lim _{k\rightarrow \infty }\phi ^{w^k}_i(u_S)=0\). If \(i\in S\), set

$$\begin{aligned} q'=\min \left\{ s\in \{1, \ldots , q\}: T^s\cap S\ne \emptyset \right\} . \end{aligned}$$

If \(q'<q\), then

$$\begin{aligned} \lim _{k\rightarrow \infty }\phi ^{w^k}_i(u_S)=\lim _{k\rightarrow \infty } \frac{\frac{w^k_i}{\sum _{j\in \cup _{s=q'}^{r} T^s}w^k_j}}{\frac{\sum _{j\in S}w^k_j}{\sum _{j\in \cup _{s=q'}^{r} T^s}w^k_j}}=0. \end{aligned}$$

On the other hand, if \(q'=q\), then

$$\begin{aligned} \lim _{k\rightarrow \infty }\phi ^{w^k}_i(u_S)=\lim _{k\rightarrow \infty } \frac{\frac{w^k_i}{\sum _{j\in \cup _{s=q'}^{r} T^s}w^k_j}}{\frac{\sum _{j\in S}w^k_j}{\sum _{j\in \cup _{s=q'}^{r} T^s}w^k_j}}=\frac{w^{T^q}_i}{\sum _{j\in S\cap T^q}w^{T^q}_j}. \end{aligned}$$

Since S is arbitrarily chosen, together with the facts that the set of the unanimity games forms a basis of the set of TU games and \(\phi ^w\), \(\phi ^\omega \) are linear, we obtain

$$\begin{aligned} \lim _{k\rightarrow \infty }\phi ^{w^k}_i(v)=\phi ^\omega _i(v). \end{aligned}$$

Since q and \(i\in T^q\) are arbitrarily chosen, the proof completes. \(\square \)

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Yokote, K. Weighted values and the core in NTU games. Int J Game Theory 46, 631–654 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s00182-016-0550-x

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s00182-016-0550-x

Keywords

Navigation