Skip to main content

Ontology and Methodology in Analytic Philosophy

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Book cover Theory and Applications of Ontology: Philosophical Perspectives

Abstract

This chapter provides a survey of ontology in the analytic tradition with a special focus on the reasons for the reemergence of ontology in the 1970s. Beginning with the ontological views of Frege and Russell, the chapter discusses the origin of some central methodological tendencies in the tradition. The interplay between logical considerations and intuitive or common sense reasoning are discussed in detail. Some discussion of the anti-metaphysical views which figure prominently in the tradition are discussed. The chapter concludes by examining some recent developments.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    The development of analytic ontology over the past three decades deserves extended discussion. There are a number of introductory anthologies which cast a broad net, including Barry Smith and Hans Burkhardt (1991) and Roberto Poli, and Peter Simons (1996). Two examples of recent work in analytic ontology which provide a solid introduction to the contemporary debates are Trenton Merricks (2007) and Theodore Sider, (2003). Dale Jacquette makes a case for the importance of logic in ontology in his (2002).

  2. 2.

    Scott Soames (2005) has argued persuasively for the centrality of Kripke’s work in the revival of metaphysics.

  3. 3.

    While this essay will not discuss Bergmann’s ideas, his struggle to reconcile positivism and ontology is a fascinating example of the more general problem, in analytic ontology of reconciling common sense presuppositions with formal and scientific insights. Herbert Hochberg provides a very informative discussion of Bergmann’s views in his (1994).

  4. 4.

    Two books which examine the ontological views of early analytic philosophers are Jan Dejnozka (1996) and Gideon Makin (2001)

  5. 5.

    Most recently, in his Ethics Without Ontology Hilary Putnam argues that ontology has had disastrous consequences for philosophy of mathematics and moral philosophy. Like Carnap, he argues that moral and mathematical reasoning can be conducted apart from debates concerning the foundations of these endeavors, arguing in effect, that ontology factors out of our moral and mathematical reasoning. Given his earlier criticisms of logical positivism, it is striking that Putnam comes so close to the anti-ontological arguments which we find in the Aufbau and in Pseudoproblems of Philosophy.

  6. 6.

    By way of examples, the see the papers collected in Szabo Gendler and Hawthorne (2002) and Vincent Hendricks’ Mainstream and Formal Epistemology.

  7. 7.

    Scott Soames makes a compelling case for the centrality of Moore’s thought in the development of analytic philosophy in the twentieth century in his (2005)

  8. 8.

    For a more expansive and detailed account of the advantages of Frege’s logic over syllogistic logic, see Anthony Kenny (1995, 12–26).

  9. 9.

    He writes that “the mere invention of this ideography has, it seems to me, advanced logic” (1967, 7)

  10. 10.

    Although Gideon Makin (2000) makes a strong case for the seeing both Frege and Russell’s work as fundamentally oriented towards metaphysical questions rather than attempting to replace metaphysics with philosophy of language.

  11. 11.

    See Anthony Kenny’s discussion of the ‘unbridgeable gulf between concepts and objects’ and Frege’s reliance on common sense acquaintance with the distinction between predicates and names in his (1995, 121). Joan Weiner has an extended reading of the distinction between definition and elucidation for Frege in her (1990), especially pp. 99–104 and 227–280.

  12. 12.

    David Pears’ Bertrand Russell and the British Tradition in Philosophy (1972) is a prominent example of the empiricist reading of Russell’s turn away from British Idealism. Peter Hylton’s Russell, Idealism and the Emergence of Analytic Philosophy (1990) presents a more accurate and detailed analysis of the early philosophy of Russell and Moore which notes the centrality of abstract entities in Russell’s thought. In his early work, Russell often had recourse to abstract entities in ways which do not comport with the kind of empiricism that Pear and others have in mind.

  13. 13.

    See John Findlay’s (1963) for a very clear presentation of some of the subtleties of Meinong’s ontology.

  14. 14.

    One could argue that because the theory of descriptions makes all claims about fictional or unreal objects false, it is thereby too restrictive and potentially self-undermining. This objection forces Russell to introduce the distinction between primary and secondary occurrence of a term which fails to denote. The secondary occurrence of the term ‘Hamlet’ in a sentence like ‘Hamlet was a prince’ allows us to claim that what is really intended here is the true sentence ‘The play tells us that Hamlet was a prince’. Names for unreal or fictional objects can still play a role in true sentences in this sense.

  15. 15.

    One of the most explicit general criticisms of analytic philosophy as a movement is Stanley Rosen (1985). While Rosen’s discussion of the history of analytic philosophy is not reliable, his criticisms exemplify widely held complaints against mainstream philosophical practice.

  16. 16.

    Richard von Mises (1951) provides an introduction to positivism which emphasizes its cultural implications and contrasts prior philosophical orientations with the liberal model of inquiry and social progress to which the positivists aspired.

  17. 17.

    In his criticism of analytic philosophy Avrum Stroll emphasizes what he sees as the scientistic mainstream of analytic philosophy. He contrasts the vices of scientism with the virtues of the those philosophers who would draw a sharp distinction between science and philosophy (in his view this was Wittgenstein and Austin) One problem with this view is, among other things, the centrality of the distinction between science and philosophy in the work of the Vienna circle and specifically in Carnap’s distinction between scientific and non-scientific propositions. Stroll, like Rosen and other critics often seem more concerned with philosophical style or tone, than with any specific philosophical point.

  18. 18.

    See Michael Friedman’s A Parting of the Ways (2000) for a detailed discussion of the political and cultural background to Carnap’s criticism of Heidegger. The resolute opposition to metaphysics is more easily understood in historical context.

  19. 19.

    As Friedman (2000, 11–13) and others have noted, Carnap’s well known criticism of Heidegger’s account of nothingness; Heidegger’s notorious claim that “Nothing itself nothings [Das Nichts selbst nichtet]” is not a crude application of verificationism. Instead, Carnap sees Heidegger’s usage as violating the logical form of the concept of nothing. Heidegger’s vice is less a matter of metaphysics than of misology

  20. 20.

    The best discussion of Carnap’s constructional system is Alan Richardson’s Carnap’s Construction of the World. In general terms, my presentation owes a great deal to Michael Friedman’s reading of the Aufbau in, for example, “Carnap’s Aufbau Reconsidered” and his “Epis- temology in the Aufbau

  21. 21.

    Thanks to Stephen Elliot for pointing me towards “Empiricism, Semantics, and Ontology”.

  22. 22.

    ‘On what there is’, in From a logical point of view, second edition. Cambridge: Harvard university press, 1961 1–19

  23. 23.

    See her classic paper ‘Modalities and Intensional Languages’ in Modalities: Philosophical Essays, Oxford University Press, 1993. pp.3–39

  24. 24.

    Moore’s break with Idealism is defended in his article ‘The Nature of Judgment’, (1898)

  25. 25.

    See for example his The Ontology of Physical Objects (1990),

  26. 26.

    See Amie Thomasson’s ‘Artifacts and Human Concepts’ (forthcoming). And Crawford Elder’s Real Natures and Familiar Objects (2004)

  27. 27.

    Wittgenstein described the project this way: ”When philosophers use a word – “knowledge”, “being”, “object”, “I”, “sentence”, “name” – and try to grasp the essence of the thing, one must always ask oneself: is the word ever actually used in this way in the language-game which is its original home?

    What we do is to bring words back from their metaphysical to their everyday use.” Philosophical Investigations § 116

  28. 28.

    He writes:

    “Suppose we interviewed some spokesman for common sense. I think we would find that he adheres firmly to three theses:

    (1) Everything is actual

    (2) Actuality consists of everything that is spatiotemporally related to us, and nothing more (give or take some ‘abstract entities’). It is not vastly bigger, or less unified than we are accustomed to think.

    (3) Possibilities are not parts of actuality, they are alternatives to it.

    […] I speak as party to the conventions of the community in question. […] I am within my rights in standing with common opinion about the unification and the extent of actuality, at the expense of common opinion that everything is actual, I do of course disagree with common opinion. I acknowledge that as a fair objection.” (1986, 99–100)

  29. 29.

    Williamson (2004, 112) makes a similar point, noting examples of philosophers (van Inwagen 1995, Horgan 1996) who deny the existence of mountains.

  30. 30.

    For a more complete discussion of the role of intuition in contemporary philosophy, see Symons (2008)

  31. 31.

    Among the first paper to make an experimental case against the assumed consensus with respect to some philosophical intuition is Jonathon Weinberg, Shaun Nichols, Steven Stich (2001) on normative intuitions. In a recent paper Swain, et al, (forthcoming) conduct experiments on epistemic intuitions to similar effect. See their blog at http://experimentalphilosophy.typepad.com

References

  • Austin, J. 1964. Sense and sensibilia. ed. G.J. Warnock. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bealer, G. 2002. Modal epistemology and the rationalist renaissance. In Conceivability and possibility, eds. T. Szabo Gendler and J. Hawthorne. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bird, A. 2007. Nature’s metaphysics: Laws and properties. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bishop, M., and J.D. Trout. 2005.. Epistemology and the psychology of human judgment. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cao, T.Y. 2001. Philosophy of science: Retrospect and prospect. Studies in Dialectics of Nature 17(11):5–17.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R. 1928.Der logische Aufbau der Welt. Berlin-Schlachtensee: Weltkreis-Verlag (trans. R. George, 1967) The logical structure of the world. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R. 1934. Logische Syntax der Sprache. Springer Vienna. (trans. A. Smeaton, 1937) The logical syntax of language. London: Kegan Paul, Trench, Trubner & Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R. 1950. Empiricism, semantics and ontology. Revue Internationale de Philosophie (Bruxelles) 11:20–40.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R. 1963. ‘Intellectual autobiography’ and ‘replies and systematic expositions’. In The philosophy of rudolf carnap, ed. P.A. Schilpp, 3–84. La Salle, IL: Open Court.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dejnozka, J. 1996. The ontology of the analytic tradition and its origins. Realism and identity in Frege, Russell, Wittgenstein and Quine. New York, NY: Rowman & Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dummett, M. 1981. Frege: Philosophy of language. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Egan, A. 2004. Second order predication and the metaphysics of properties. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 82(1):48–66.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Elder, C. 2004. Real natures and familiar objects. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Findlay, J. 1963. Meinong’s theory of objects and values. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G. 1967[1879]. Begriffsschrift, a formula language, modeled upon that of arithmetic, for pure thought. In From Frege to Gödel: A source book in mathematical logic, 1879–1931, ed. J. van Heijenoort. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G. 1979. Posthumous writings, ed. H. Hermes, F. Kambartel, and F. Kaulbach (trans: Long, P. and White, R.). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, M. 1992. Epistemology in the aufbau. Synthese 93:15–57.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, M. 2000. A parting of the ways: Carnap, Cassirer and Heidegger. La Salle, IL: Open Court Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frank, P. 1963. The pragmatic component in carnap’s elimination of metaphysics. In The philosophy of Rudolf Carnap, ed. P.A. Schilpp, 159–164. La Salle, IL: Open Court Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heller, M. 1990. The ontology of physical objects. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hochberg, H. 1994. From Carnap’s Vienna to Meinong’s Graz: Gustav Bergmann’s ontological odyssey. Grazer Philosophischen Studien 48:1–50.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hogran, T. 1996. Kim on the Mind–Body Problem, British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 47:579–607.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hylton, P. 1990. Russell, idealism and the emergence of analytic philosophy. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hylton, P. 2004. Quine on reference and ontology. In The cambridge companion to Quine, ed. R. Gibson, 115–180. Cambridge: Cambridge university press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Jacquette, D. 2002. Ontology. Montreal, QC: Mc-Gill-Queens’s University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kenny, A. 1995. Frege: An introduction to the founder of modern analytic philosophy. Malden, MA: Blackwell

    Google Scholar 

  • Kim, J. 1996. Philosophy of mind. Boulder, CO: Westview.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. 1972. Psychophysical and theoretical identifications. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 50:249–258.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. 1986. On the plurality of worlds. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lowe, E.J. 2006. The four-category ontology: A metaphysical foundation for natural science. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Loux, M., and D. Zimmerman. 2003.Oxford handbook of metaphysics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Makin, G. 2001. Metaphysicians of meaning: Russell and Frege on sense and denotation. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marcus, R.B. 1961. Modalities and intensional language. Synthese 13:303–322.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Merricks, T. 2007. Truth and ontology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Moore, G.E. 1898. The nature of judgment. Mind 8(30):176–193.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moore, G.E. 1925. A defence of common sense. In Contemporary british philosophy (2nd series), ed. J.H. Muirhead, 193–223. London: Allen and Unwin. Reprinted in Philosophical papers and in * G. E. Moore: Selected Writings (1959) 106–133.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mumford, S. 2007. David Armstrong. Durham, NC: Acumen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, E. 1961. The structure of science. New York, NY: Harcourt Brace.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hill, O.C. 1997. Rethinking identity and metaphysics: On the foundations of analytic philosophy. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pears, D. 1972. Bertrand Russell and the British tradition in philosophy. London: Fontana.

    Google Scholar 

  • Poli, R., and P. Simons. eds. 1996. Formal ontology. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W.V. 1934(1966). Ontological remarks on the propositional calculus. In The ways of paradox and other essays, 57–63. New York, NY: Random House.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W.V. 1948. On what there is. Review of Metaphysics 2:21–38.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W.V. 1960. Word and object. New York, NY: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W.V. 1969. Ontological relativity and other essays. New York, NY: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ramsey, F.P. 1931. The foundations of mathematics and other logical essays, ed. R.B. Braithwaite. London: Routledge & Keegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Richardson, A. 1998. Carnap’s construction of the world. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosen, S. 1985. The limits of analysis. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. [1897] 1956. An essay on the foundations of geometry. New York, NY: Dover.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. [1903] 1992. The principles of mathematics, 1937, 2nd edn. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. [1914] 1993. Our knowledge of the external world. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schlipp, P. ed. 1944. The philosophy of Bertrand Russell. La Salle, IL: Open Court.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schlipp, P. ed. 1967. The philosophy of Rudolf Carnap. La Salle, IL: Open Court.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sider, T. 2003. Four-dimensionalism: An ontology of persistence and time. Oxford: Oxford University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, P.F. 1959. Individuals: An essay in descriptive metaphysics. London: Methuen.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Symons, J. 2008. Intuition and philosophical methodology. Axiomathes 18:67–89.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Symons, J. forthcoming. Functionalism and fallibility. Southwest Philosophical Studies

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, B., and H. Burkhardt. eds. 1991. Handbook of metaphysics and ontology. Munich: Philosophia Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Soames, S. 2005. Philosophical analysis in the twentieth century, vol. 2. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sosa, E. 2007. Experimental philosophy and philosophical intuition. Philosophical Studies 132:99–107.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Swain, S., J. Alexander, and J. Weinberg. Forthcoming. The instability of philosophical intuitions: running hot and cold on truetemp. Philosophy and phenomenological research

    Google Scholar 

  • Gendler, T.S., and J. Hawthorne. eds. 2002. Conceivability and possibility. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomasson, A. forthcoming. Artifacts and human concepts. Creations of the mind: Essays on artifacts and their representation, ed. S. Laurence, and E. Margolis. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Inwagen, P. 1995. Material beings. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Mises, R. 1951. Positivism: A study of human understanding. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wasserman, R. 2006. E.J. Lowe’s the four-category ontology. Notre dame philosophical review (2006.04.11) http://ndpr.nd.edu/review.cfm?id=6341 (last accessed November 28, 2008).

  • Weiner, J. 1990. Frege in perspective. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, T. 2004. Philosophical ‘intuitions’ and scepticism about judgement. Dialectica 58(1):109–153.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

This essay was made possible in part thanks to support from the John Templeton Foundation’s individual research awards program. I am also very grateful to two anonymous reviewers for their helpful suggestions. In addition I would like to thank Pablo Zavala, Stephen Elliott, and Roberto Poli for reading a draft of this manuscript and for offering some useful corrections

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to John Symons .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2010 Springer Netherlands

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Symons, J. (2010). Ontology and Methodology in Analytic Philosophy. In: Poli, R., Seibt, J. (eds) Theory and Applications of Ontology: Philosophical Perspectives. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-90-481-8845-1_16

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics