Skip to main content

Galileo on the Mathematical Physics of Terrestrial Extrusion

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Book cover Defending Copernicus and Galileo

Part of the book series: Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science ((BSPS,volume 280))

  • 1424 Accesses

Abstract

We have seen that the empirical astronomical objections and the scriptural theological objections were not the only arguments against the Copernican system. Equally important, strong, and consequential were the mechanical physical objections, involving such phenomena as falling bodies, the motion of projectiles, and the extruding power of whirling. They presupposed Aristotelian physics, based on the principles that rest is the natural state and motion requires a force; and their refutation required a new physics, based on the principles of inertia or conservation of motion and the composition of motion into independent components. Galileo took the physical objections as seriously as the astronomical ones, although he conceived the refutation of the former earlier than the refutation of the latter, since the answers to the physical difficulties were implied by his earlier research into a new physics, whereas the astronomical answers were the result of the telescope.

This chapter will examine how Galileo defended Copernicus from the extremely powerful objection based on the extruding power of whirling. We will see that Galileo criticized the extrusion objection in several distinct ways, but that his major criticism was that the objection was quantitatively invalid. Now, this quantitative invalidity turns out to be a flaw that is partly mathematical, partly physical, and essentially physical-mathematical. That is, the correct understanding of the phenomenon to which the objection appeals requires the proper combination of physical and mathematical principles, namely the skill of physical-mathematical reasoning. Thus, the structure of this chapter will be that of an inquiry into the nature of mathematical reasoning by means of a Galilean case study suggesting a definition of physical-mathematical reasoning.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Favaro 7: 214-244, Galilei (1967, 188-217; 1997, 171-212).

  2. 2.

    This corresponds to Galileo’s diagram in Favaro 7: 224, Galilei (1967, 198; 1997, 184).

  3. 3.

    This corresponds to Galileo’s diagram in Favaro 7: 225, Galilei (1967, 199; 1997, 186). But I have reproduced it from MacLachlan (1977, 175).

  4. 4.

    For other accounts, from which my own has benefited, see Boyer (1967, 245-247), Chalmers and Nicholas (1983), DiCanzio (1996, 144-145, 171-173, 353-354), Drake (1986a), Feldhay (1998), Gaukroger (1978, 189-195), Hill (1984), MacLachlan (1977), Pagnini (1964, 2: 383 n. 1, 387 n. 1, 415 n), Palmieri (2008a).

  5. 5.

    Galilei (1997, 172). Cf. Favaro 7: 215-216, Galilei (1967, 189).

  6. 6.

    Cf. Aristotle, On Sophistical Refutations 167a21.

  7. 7.

    Favaro 7: 221, Galilei (1967, 194-195; 1997, 180).

  8. 8.

    Favaro 7: 250, Galilei (1967, 223).

  9. 9.

    See MacLachlan (1977, 176-178) for this account and other details.

  10. 10.

    For a more modern argument along the same lines, see Chalmers and Nicholas (1983, 322).

  11. 11.

    Favaro 7: 237-244, Galilei (1967, 211-217; 1997, 203-212).

  12. 12.

    This corresponds to Galileo’s diagram in Favaro 7: 242, Galilei (1967, 216; 1997, 209).

  13. 13.

    Cf., for example, Chalmers and Nicholas (1983, 323-328), Gaukroger (1978, 193-195), Pagnini (1964, 2: 415 n).

  14. 14.

    This claim would need to be qualified if one wanted to take into account the effects of the irregularity of the earth’s surface; for then a body that had reached orbital velocity could be struck some time later by a mountain that was moving at a higher velocity due to the increased terrestrial rotation, and so the body would acquire additional velocity; eventually, such additions might increase the body’s velocity to the value required for escape extrusion. I thank Albert DiCanzio for this refinement.

  15. 15.

    This proof is not given in Galileo’s text; he just makes the assertion (7.6).

  16. 16.

    Once again, Galileo does not show these steps, though he gives explicit indication that 7.7 is based on 7.4, 7.5, and 7.6.

  17. 17.

    This claim is, of course, the (correct) law of fall discovered by Galileo.

  18. 18.

    Here I am indebted to MacLachlan (1977) and Hill (1984).

  19. 19.

    I have adapted this from MacLachlan (1977).

  20. 20.

    This objection is due to Jean Dhombres, who raised it at the International Conference on Logic and Mathematical Reasoning, Mexico City, 6-8 October 1997, where an earlier version of this chapter was first presented.

  21. 21.

    For some useful accounts along these lines, see Camerota (2004, 20-23, 386-387, 559-560), De Caro (1993), Galluzzi (1973), Koyré (1943; 1966; 1978), Shea (1972). These accounts are instructive not necessarily because they explicitly attribute to Galileo a conflation of mathematical and physical truth, but because they explicitly talk of his Platonism and mathematicism, and they implicitly suggest such a conflation; the most common instance of such implicit conflation is the interpretation that Galileo was certain about the truth of Copernicanism because of its mathematical simplicity. For a criticism of some aspects of such an interpretation and a clarification of such notions as Platonism, mathematicism, and realism, see Finocchiaro (1980; 1989, 7-8; 1997a, 335-356; 2005c, 554-555), as well as Chapters 3, 5, 9, 11 of this book.

  22. 22.

    Galilei (2008, 183); cf. Favaro 6: 232.

  23. 23.

    Here I am adopting Mario Biagioli’s interpretation that “Galileo’s audience for The Assayer was not twentieth-century historians and philosophers but early seventeenth-century courtiers. The image of the open book of nature appealed to them because of the sense of unmediated knowledge that it conveyed. True, one had to learn how to read those characters, but to learn a language was not like enslaving oneself to a philosophical system. Once that linguistic ability was acquired, the book was open and the interpretation free” (Biagioli 1993, 306-307).

  24. 24.

    Favaro 8: 197-213, Galilei (2008, 335-351).

  25. 25.

    Galilei (2008, 336); cf. Favaro 8: 198.

  26. 26.

    Galilei (2008, 349); cf. Favaro 8: 212. It should be noted that the ninth word of Salviati’s speech (scientist) is a literal translation of the original Italian word (scienziato); this strengthens further the point made in Section 4.1 above that although one must be careful to avoid anachronism when using terms like science and scientist instead of natural philosophy and philosopher, one must also avoid linguistic chauvinism or provincialism.

  27. 27.

    Favaro 7: 229-237, Galilei (1967, 203-210; 1997, 193-202). For other accounts of this passage, see Clavelin (1974, 404-421; 1996), Feldhay (1998), Wisan (1978).

  28. 28.

    Galilei (1997, 193). Cf. Favaro 7: 229, Galilei (1967, 203).

References

  • Biagioli M (1993) Galileo Courtier. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Boyer CB (1967) Galileo’s place in the history of mathematics. In McMullin 1967b:232-255

    Google Scholar 

  • Camerota M (2004) Galileo Galilei e la cultura scientifica nell’età della Controriforma. Salerno, Rome

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers A, Nicholas R (1983) Galileo and the dissipative effects of a rotating earth. Stud Hist Phil Sci 14:315-340

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clavelin M (1974). The natural philosophy of Galileo. Pomerans AJ (Trans). MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Clavelin M (1996). La philosophie naturelle de Galilèe. (2nd edn) Albin Michel, Paris

    Google Scholar 

  • De Caro M (1993) Galileo’s mathematical platonism. In Czermak 1993:13-22

    Google Scholar 

  • DiCanzio A (1996) Galileo: His science and His significance for the future of man. Adasi Publishing Company, Portsmouth

    Google Scholar 

  • Drake S (1986a) Galileo and the projection argument. Ann Sci 43:77-79

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feldhay R (1998) The use and abuse of mathematical entities. In Machamer 1998a:80-145

    Google Scholar 

  • Finocchiaro MA (1980) Galileo and the art of reasoning: rhetorical foundations of logic and scientific method. Reidel, Dordrecht

    Google Scholar 

  • Finocchiaro MA (2005c) Review essay of Michele Camerota’s new biography of Galileo. Early Sci Med 10:545-557

    Google Scholar 

  • Finocchiaro MA (trans. and ed) (1989) The Galileo affair: a documentary history. University of California Press, Berkeley

    Google Scholar 

  • Finocchiaro MA (trans. and ed) (1997a) Galileo on the world systems: a new abridged translation and guide. University of California Press, Berkeley

    Google Scholar 

  • Galilei G (1967) Dialogue concerning the two chief world systems. Drake S (trans and ed) 2nd revised edn. University of California Press, Berkeley

    Google Scholar 

  • Galilei G (1997) Galileo on the world systems: a new abridged translation and guide. Finocchiaro MA (trans and ed). University of California Press, Berkeley

    Google Scholar 

  • Galilei G (2008) The essential Galileo. Finocchiaro MA (ed and trans). Hackett Publishing Co., Indianapolis and Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Galluzzi P (1973) Il platonismo del tardo cinquecento e la filosofia di Galileo. In: Zambelli P (ed) Ricerche sulla cultura dell’Italia moderna. Laterza, Bari, pp 39-79

    Google Scholar 

  • Gaukroger S (1978) Explanatory structures. Humanities, Atlantic Highlands

    Google Scholar 

  • Hill DK (1984) The projection argument in Galileo and Copernicus. Ann Sci 41:109-133

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Huygens C (1673) Horologium oscillatorium. Paris

    Google Scholar 

  • Koyré A (1943) Galileo and Plato. J Hist Ideas 5:400-428

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Koyré A (1966) Etudes galiléennes. Hermann, Paris

    Google Scholar 

  • Koyré A (1978) Galileo studies. Mepham J (trans). Harvester, Hassocks

    Google Scholar 

  • MacLachlan JH (1977) Mersenne’s solution for Galileo’s problem of the rotating earth. Historia Mathematica 4:173-182

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pagnini P (ed) (1964) Opere (di Galileo Galilei). 5 vols. Salani, Florence

    Google Scholar 

  • Palmieri P (2008a) Galileus Deceptus, Non Minime Decepit: A Re-appraisal of a Counter-argument in Dialogo to the Extrusion Effect of a Rotating Earth. J Hist Astron 39:425-452

    Google Scholar 

  • Shea WR (1972) Galileo’s intellectual revolution. Science History Publications, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Wisan WL (1978) Galileo’s scientific method. In Butts and Pitt 1978:1-57

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Maurice A. Finocchiaro .

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2010 Springer Science+Business Media B.V.

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Finocchiaro, M.A. (2010). Galileo on the Mathematical Physics of Terrestrial Extrusion. In: Defending Copernicus and Galileo. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol 280. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-90-481-3201-0_5

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics