Skip to main content

In Defence of Meaningful Work as a Public Policy Concern

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Philosophy and Political Engagement

Part of the book series: International Political Theory ((IPoT))

Abstract

Breen critically examines the arguments put forward by those for whom ethical considerations either do not play or should not play a role in modern politics. Breen challenges three distinct claims to the effect that the demand for meaningful work, grounded upon an ethical ideal of such work as partly constitutive of a good human life, is either not a significant, a feasible, or an acceptable concern of public policy in liberal capitalist societies. Based on a detailed examination of the work of Jürgen Habermas, Will Kymlicka, and Alasdair MacIntyre, among others, as well as a thorough analysis of the possibilities for meaningful work in modern economic contexts, Breen provides a timely analysis of the place of ethics in both politics and philosophy.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 19.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 29.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    On the various dimensions of meaningfulness attaching to work, see Yeoman (2014, pp. 8–38). On the distinction between ‘external’ and ‘internal goods’, see MacIntyre (1985, pp. 187–197) and Sect. 3 below.

  2. 2.

    See Smith’s (1979 [1776], pp. 13–24) analysis of pin production for a classic account of the detailed division of labour.

  3. 3.

    It is worth distinguishing the demand for meaningful work from the demand for ‘decent work’, that is, work characterized by proper remuneration, safe working conditions, fair employment practices, et cetera (see ILO 2015). Although these demands are related, they remain distinct: one can have decent work that provides little scope for autonomy or individual flourishing, and meaningful work that is poorly remunerated and undertaken in dangerous environments.

  4. 4.

    In this section I draw on earlier analyses of Habermas (Breen 2007, 2015).

  5. 5.

    Indeed, Habermas repeatedly rejects the view that labour or work has a normative significance comparable with that of the ideal of communicative action (see Habermas 1987a, p. 340, 1987b, pp. 63, 82, 341–49, 1991, pp. 33–4, 38).

  6. 6.

    Sitton (1998, p. 81). For related arguments, see Honneth (1995) and McCarthy (1991).

  7. 7.

    See, for instance, the discussions in Breen (2007), Keat (2000), and Muirhead (2004).

  8. 8.

    MacIntyre (1985, p. 227). Notice my focus here is mainly on After Virtue, where MacIntyre excoriates the capitalist present but denies the prospect of any wide-ranging transformation of ‘the new dark ages which are already upon us’ (MacIntyre 1985, p. 263). In later texts he strikes a more hopeful, and to my mind welcome, chord, arguing the capitalist economic order ‘can be successfully resisted and even changed’ (MacIntyre 2015, p. 17).

  9. 9.

    The local communities MacIntyre (1999, p. 143) refers to include New England fishing villages, Mayan towns in Mexico and Guatemala, and Welsh mining communities.

  10. 10.

    In comparing LMEs and CMEs, Keat (2008a, p. 80) clarifies ‘that the term ‘Liberal’, in ‘LMEs’, is used in its economic [primacy of free market relations], not its political, sense’. This is an important clarification because CME societies, with regard to their support for civil rights and liberties, are politically no less liberal than LME societies.

  11. 11.

    I concentrate on Kymlicka for reasons of space, though he himself draws extensively upon fellow neutralist liberals, including Dworkin (1978), Arneson (1987), and Rawls (1971). My argument in this section is indebted to Keat’s (2008b, 2009, 2011) critique of the attempt to exclude ethics from politics and political economy.

  12. 12.

    On work’s role in both engendering and hindering self-esteem, see Gomberg (2007) and Lane (1991).

  13. 13.

    See, for instance, Hauser and Roan (2007), Kohn and Schooler (1983), and Kornhauser (1964).

  14. 14.

    Against the assumption (Kymlicka 2002, p. 247) that neutrality can be maintained in such decisions, Chan (2000, p. 19) makes it clear that in ‘providing and supporting options, the state cannot avoid evaluating the intrinsic merit of the options’.

  15. 15.

    It is essential to note here that ‘not all perfectionist action is a coercive imposition of a style of life. Much of it could be encouraging and facilitating action of the desired kind, or discouraging undesired modes of behaviour’ (Raz 1986, p. 161). It is this moderate, liberty-preserving, perfectionism, not a coercive perfectionism, that is endorsed by most defenders of a right to meaningful work (see Keat (2011), Muirhead (2004), and Roessler (2012)).

  16. 16.

    I am grateful to Allyn Fives, Russell Keat, Cillian McBride, Paddy McQueen, Geoff Moore, Fabian Schuppert, and Ruth Yeoman for their discussion of the themes addressed in this chapter.

References

  • Arneson, R. (1987). Meaningful work and market socialism. Ethics, 97(3), 517–545.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berggren, C. (1992). The Volvo experience. New York: ILR Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Boltanski, L., & Chiapello, E. (2007). The new spirit of capitalism. London: Verso.

    Google Scholar 

  • Booth, W. J. (1994). On the idea of the moral economy. American Political Science Review, 88(3), 653–667.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Braverman, H. (1998). Labor and monopoly capital. New York: Monthly Review Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Breen, K. (2007). Work and emancipatory practice. Res Publica, 13(4), 381–414.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Breen, K. (2012). Production and productive reason. New Political Economy, 17, 611–632.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Breen, K. (2015). Freedom, democracy, and working life. In A. Azmanova & M. Mihai (Eds.), Reclaiming democracy (pp. 34–49). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chan, J. (2000). Legitimacy, unanimity, and perfectionism. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 29(1), 5–42.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Durkheim, E. (1964 [1893]). The division of labor in society (G. Simpson, Trans.). New York: Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, R. (1978). Liberalism. In S. Hampshire (Ed.), Public and private morality (pp. 113–143). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Gomberg, P. (2007). How to make opportunity equal. Oxford: Blackwell Publishing.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. (1971). Toward a rational society. London: Heinemann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. (1973). Theory and practice. Boston: Beacon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. (1984). The theory of communicative action: Vol. I. Reason and the rationalization of society. Cambridge: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. (1987a). The theory of communicative action: Vol. II: System and lifeworld—A critique of functionalist reason. Cambridge: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. (1987b). The philosophical discourse of modernity. Cambridge: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. (1991). What does socialism mean today? The revolutions of recuperation and the need for new thinking. In R. Blackburn (Ed.), After the fall (pp. 25–46). London: Verso.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. (1992). Further reflections on the public sphere. In C. Calhoun (Ed.), Habermas and the public sphere (pp. 421–461). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hall, P., & Soskice, D. (2001). An introduction to varieties of capitalism. In P. Hall & D. Soskice (Eds.), Varieties of capitalism: The institutional foundations of comparative advantage (pp. 1–68). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Hauser, R. M., & Roan, C. L. (2007). Work complexity and cognitive functioning at midlife. CDE Working Paper No. 2007–08. Retrieved July 20, 2015, from http://www.ssc.wisc.edu/cde/cdewp/2007-08.pdf.

  • Honneth, A. (1995). Work and instrumental action. In A. Honneth (Ed.), The fragmented world of the social (pp. 15–49). New York: SUNY Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Honneth, A. (2014). Freedom’s right. Cambridge: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hsieh, N.-H. (2008). Justice in production. Journal of Political Philosophy, 16(1), 72–100.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • International Labor Organization (ILO). (2015). Decent work agenda. Retrieved July 20, 2015, from http://www.ilo.org/global/about-the-ilo/decent-work-agenda/lang--en/index.htm.

  • Keat, R. (2000). Cultural goods and the limits of the market. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Keat, R. (2008a). Practices, firms and varieties of capitalism. Philosophy of Management, 7(1), 77–91.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Keat, R. (2008b). Social criticism and the exclusion of ethics. Analyse und Kritik, 30(2), 291–315.

    Google Scholar 

  • Keat, R. (2009). Anti-perfectionism, market economies and the right to meaningful work. Analyse und Kritik, 31(1), 121–138.

    Google Scholar 

  • Keat, R. (2011). Liberalism, neutrality and varieties of capitalism. In N. H. Smith & J.-P. Deranty (Eds.), New philosophies of labour (pp. 347–370). Leiden: Brill.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kohn, M., & Schooler, C. (1983). Work and personality. Norwood, NJ: Alex Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kornhauser, A. (1964). Mental health of the industrial worker: A Detroit study. New York: John Wiley & Sons.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kymlicka, W. (2002). Contemporary political philosophy: An introduction (2nd ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lane, R. E. (1991). The market experience. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • MacIntyre, A. (1985). After virtue: A study in moral theory (2nd ed.). London: Duckworth.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacIntyre, A. (1994). A partial response to my critics. In J. Horton & S. Mendus (Eds.), After MacIntyre: Critical perspectives on the work of Alasdair MacIntyre (pp. 283–304). Cambridge: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacIntyre, A. (1999). Dependent rational animals: Why human beings need the virtues. London: Duckworth.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacIntyre, A. (2015). The irrelevance of ethics. In A. Bielskis & K. Knight (Eds.), Virtue and economy (pp. 7–21). Farnham: Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • McCarthy, T. (1991). Complexity and democracy: or the seducements of systems theory. In A. Honneth & H. Joas (Eds.), Communicative action (pp. 119–139). Cambridge: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Miller, D. (1994). Virtues, practices and justice. In J. Horton & S. Mendus (Eds.), After MacIntyre: Critical perspectives on the work of Alasdair MacIntyre (pp. 245–264). Cambridge: Polity.

    Google Scholar 

  • Muirhead, R. (2004). Just work. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Murphy, J. B. (1993). The moral economy of labor. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. (1971). A theory of justice. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raz, J. (1986). The morality of freedom. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roessler, B. (2012). Meaningful work: Arguments from autonomy. Journal of Political Philosophy, 20(1), 71–93.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ruskin, J. (2007 [1853]). The stones of Venice: Vol. II. The sea stories. New York: Cosimo.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schwartz, A. (1982). Meaningful work. Ethics, 92(4), 634–646.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sitton, J. F. (1998). Disembodied capitalism: Habermas’s conception of the economy. Sociological Forum, 13(1), 61–83.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, A. (1979 [1776]). The wealth of nations. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Veltman, A. (2015). Is meaningful work available to all people? Philosophy and Social Criticism, 41(7), 725–747.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weber, M. (1992 [1930]). The protestant ethic and the spirit of capitalism. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yeoman, R. (2014). Meaningful work and workplace democracy. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Copyright information

© 2016 The Editor(s) (if applicable) and The Author(s)

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Breen, K. (2016). In Defence of Meaningful Work as a Public Policy Concern. In: Fives, A., Breen, K. (eds) Philosophy and Political Engagement. International Political Theory. Palgrave Macmillan, London. https://doi.org/10.1057/978-1-137-44587-2_8

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics