Skip to main content

Subsidiarity in the Writings of Aristotle and Aquinas

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Book cover Global Perspectives on Subsidiarity

Part of the book series: Ius Gentium: Comparative Perspectives on Law and Justice ((IUSGENT,volume 37))

Abstract

The philosophical origins of the principle of subsidiarity must be understood historically. This chapter argues that the critical point for the emergence of the principle lay in Thomas Aquinas’s theological interpretation of Aristotle’s political philosophy and his application of it to the institutional pluralism of medieval Europe. From Aristotle, Aquinas developed the idea that human societies naturally progress from families, through villages to entire city-states, but he recognised that what Aristotle said of city-states could be applied not only to cities but even more emphatically to political communities on the scale of provinces, kingdoms and (perhaps even) empires. Moreover, for Aquinas, the civil order was not the only ‘perfect community’ in Aristotle’s sense: there was also the church in all of its many grades and jurisdictions, alongside the many different religious orders and fraternities of medieval Europe, some of them also organised into their own graded hierarchies. Reflecting on the complexity of the society surrounding him, Aquinas acknowledged the many and various purposes for which various associations and forms of human community exist and are formed, giving rise to a whole host of familial, geographical, professional, mercantile, scholarly and other specialised societies. All of these groups and groupings, from the smallest to the largest, have their place and their proper function, according to Aquinas, and each should to be allowed to make its unique and special contribution as a means to integral human fulfillment, without undue interference from any others, including the state.

The support of Australian Research Council Discovery Grant DP 120101590 is gratefully acknowledged.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    John Paul II (1991).

  2. 2.

    Hittinger (2002).

  3. 3.

    Despite the evidence that Catholic social philosophy was one of the prime inspirations of the European doctrine, there is resistance to the invocation of Catholic principles: von Borries and Hauschild (1999, pp. 369–70). For a more sympathetic discussion of Catholic ideas in the context of the European principle of subsidiarity, see Barber (2005).

  4. 4.

    Pius XI (1931).

  5. 5.

    Leo XIII (1891).

  6. 6.

    See also Rerum Novarum, [7]: ‘Man precedes the State, and possesses, prior to the formation of any State, the right of providing for the substance of his body.’

  7. 7.

    Among them: Luigi Taparelli, Matteo Liberatore, Wilhelm Emmanuel von Ketteler and Oswald von Nell-Breuning.

  8. 8.

    Millon-Delsol (1992), Kelly (1993).

  9. 9.

    Part III of this chapter substantially draws on Aroney (2007).

  10. 10.

    I use the expression ‘city-state’ conscious of the difficulty of finding a precise English equivalent to the term polis.

  11. 11.

    A Greek household is not quite the same thing as a ‘family’ in the sense that we understand it today. A household then consisted of all of the property and persons under the authority of the head of the household, an emphasis very different from the close marital, parental and filial bonds with which we associate the family today. See Herlihy (1983).

  12. 12.

    On the ‘whole’ and its ‘parts’, see Aristotle, Metaphysics, VII.10–11 and the discussion in Newman (1950, Vol. II, pp. 125–127).

  13. 13.

    See, generally, Dobbs (1985, pp. 29–46).

  14. 14.

    See Booth (1981, pp. 203–26).

  15. 15.

    As forms of community, it is therefore anachronistic to interpret the household/city-state distinction in terms of the private/public distinction of modern thought. See the critique of Arendt (1958) in Salkever (1990, pp. 169–74, 179–83).

  16. 16.

    See Jaffa (1972, pp. 94–96), and compare Plato, Republic, II, 369a-c. On the composition of the polis in terms of households and villages as well as individuals, see also Newman (1950, Vol. II, pp. 111, 114; Vol. III, pp. 130, 132, 208). There may not altogether be a contradiction as between the individual citizen and the household, since although Aristotle referred to free women as well as free men as citizens, he seems generally to have assumed that the citizen who participates in the rule of the city will typically be an adult, male, head of a household. On this assumption, each citizen represents a household, and thus the city might be viewed quite consistently as both a composition of individual citizens and a composition of households.

  17. 17.

    See also Aristotle’s comments on marriage, reproduction and education in Politics, VII.16–17 and the comments in Pangle (1998, pp. 377–97, 381–2). For a contrary interpretation, which emphasises a kind of ‘constitutional pluralism’ in Aristotle, see Dobbs (1996) and compare Everson (1988, pp. 89–101). See also de Coulanges (1956, p. 219).

  18. 18.

    That is, including its immediate environs and surrounding countryside.

  19. 19.

    See the discussion of Cleisthenes’ reforms below.

  20. 20.

    See also Politics, II.6, 1265a13-18, criticizing Socrates’ ideal city of 5,000 warrior-citizens as being unrealistically large. Aristotle was well aware of ‘political communities’ which are ‘national’ in scale, but they are less than ideal: see, eg, Politics, III.3, 1276a25-34.

  21. 21.

    On the gradual expansion of the Athenian city-state into the whole of Attica, however, see Barker (1959, pp. 274, 298).

  22. 22.

    Lord (1987, p. 134). For the contrary view that Aristotle’s political theory was not necessary limited to political communities at the scale of individual cities and their immediate environs, see Everson (1996, xv–xix).

  23. 23.

    Ehrenberg (1969, pp. 103–31), Larsen (1968, pp. 202–7).

  24. 24.

    Larsen (1968, xi); Larsen (1945); Newman (1950, Vol. II, p. 232). For the texts, see Müller (1848–1874, Vol. II, pp. 102–77), especially fragments 91 and 145.

  25. 25.

    See Newman (1950, Vol. III, pp. 203–6).

  26. 26.

    Compare de Coulanges (1956, pp. 201–2), referring to the ‘profound gulf which always separated two cities’ and arguing that for this reason ‘the ancients were never able to establish, or even to conceive of, any other social organisation than the city’. See, likewise, Barker (1959, pp. 298–9), who concludes that Aristotle does not discuss ‘federation’ and thus regarded the city as the ‘final form of association’.

  27. 27.

    See also Newman (1950, Vol. II, pp. 150–51; Vol. III, pp. 346–7); Larsen (1945). On the tension between the Hellenic ‘nation’ and the Greek ‘city-states’, see Finley (1954).

  28. 28.

    Although, see Politics, III.6, 1278b31-1279a21.

  29. 29.

    See Politics, III.4, 1276b28-30, where Aristotle states that ‘the salvation of the community is the common business of them all [ie, all of the citizens of a particular city-state]’.

  30. 30.

    The constitution (politeia) is, Aristotle notes, the same as the government (politeuma): Politics, III.6, 1278b10-12; III.7, 1279a25-26. On the relationship between Aristotle’s concepts of city-state, community, citizenship, constitution and government, see Politics, III.4, 1276b30 and the discussion in Barker (1959, p. 307); Cartledge (2000, pp. 17, 20); Ehrenberg (1969, pp. 38–9, 43, 88); Newman (1950, Vol. II, pp. 156–7). The Aristotelian politeia, usually translated ‘constitution’, ‘regime’ or ‘form of government’, should not be confused, of course, with the modern idea of the written constitution as a judicially enforceable, ‘higher’ law.

  31. 31.

    See Strauss (1977, p. 45).

  32. 32.

    On the question of authorship, see Rhodes (1981, pp. 58–63).

  33. 33.

    Compare Herodotus, The Histories, V.66.2, 69.2. On the effects of Cleisthenes’ democratization and its motives, see Finley (1983, pp. 42–8), Sinclair (1988, pp. 3–4), Lewis (1997, pp. 77–98).

  34. 34.

    Cleisthenes is said, however, to have left the citizens free to belong to their clans (genê) and brotherhoods (phratrias) as they had before: Constitution of Athens, XXI.6.

  35. 35.

    Manville (1990, pp. 187–8).

  36. 36.

    The quotation is from Lord’s translation (Chicago, 1984). See also Politics, III.2, 1275b34-37.

  37. 37.

    See Gilbert (1895, pp. 200–210), Hignett (1952, pp. 136–8), Glotze (1965, pp. 122–3), Whitehead (1986), ch. 9: Manville (1990, pp. 187–94).

  38. 38.

    Whitehead (1986, p. 51).

  39. 39.

    Summa contra Gentiles (1259–1265). Unless indicated otherwise, in-text references to Aquinas’s works are to the book, section and paragraph numbers.

  40. 40.

    Grasso (2008, p. 34).

  41. 41.

    Sententia libri Politicorum (1269–1272).

  42. 42.

    On cities and provinces, see De Regno, I.2.4 [14]; on cities and kingdoms, see De Regno, I.14.5 [100]; on nations, see Quaestiones Disputatae de Veritate (1256–1259), 5.3 co; and on the universe as a whole, see ST, I-II, 91.1, 21.4, 100.5; ScG, I.42, 70–71, 78, 85–86, 93, 102, II.39, 42, III.64, 98.

  43. 43.

    In Quaestiones de quodlibet, II, 5.1 res., Aquinas (1256–1259, 1269–1272) likewise described and limited the authority of the head of a household to matters pertaining the management of the home, and that of a king to those matters pertaining to the government of the realm.

  44. 44.

    On medieval guilds in particular, see Berman (1983, pp. 390–92) and Black (1984).

  45. 45.

    See, further, Tierney (1997), Blythe (1992), Murphy (1997), Aroney (2007, pp. 198–220).

  46. 46.

    Scriptum super Sententiis magistri Petri Lombardi (1256b).

  47. 47.

    De Regno ad regem Cypri (c. 1267).

  48. 48.

    Contra impugnantes Dei cultum et Religionem (1256a), Summa Theologiae (1265–1268, 1271–1273).

  49. 49.

    For a discussion of the role of associations within Hobbes’s thought, see Robertson (1966).

  50. 50.

    Finnis (1998).

  51. 51.

    For a contrary view, see Murphy (2005, p. 148).

References

  • Aquinas, T. 1256a. Contra impugnantes Dei cultum et Religionem. In Opera omnia iussu Leonis XIII P. M. edita, t. 41. Romae: Ad Sanctae Sabinae, 1970. See Proctor, John (trans.). 1902. An Apology for the Religious Orders. London: Sands & Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aquinas, T. 1256b. Scriptum super Sententiis magistri Petri Lombardi = Commentum in quartum librum Sententiarum magistri Petri Lombardi. In Opera, t. 7/2. Parmae: Typis Petri Fiaccadori, 1858. See Molloy, Michael (trans.). 1985. Civil Authority in Medieval Philosophy: Lombard, Aquinas and Bonaventura. Lanham: University Press of America.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aquinas, T. 1256–1259. Quaestiones Disputatae de Veritate. In Opera omnia iussu Leonis XIII P. M. edita, t. 22. Quaestiones disputatae de veritate. Roma: Ad Sanctae Sabinae/Editori di San Tommaso, 1975-1970-1972-1973-1976. See Robert W. Mulligan, S.J. (trans.). 1952. St. Thomas Aquinas: Truth. Chicago: Henry Regnery Company, and Maurer, Armand (trans.). 1987. St. Thomas Aquinas: Faith, Reason and Theology: Questions I-IV of His Commentary on the De Trinitate of Boethius. Toronto: Pontifical Institute of Mediaeval Studies.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aquinas, T. 1256–1259, 1269–1272. Quaestiones quodlibetales, 9th ed, ed. Spiazzi. Taurino: Marietti, 1956. See Edwards, Sandra (trans.). 1983. St. Thomas Aquinas: Quodlibetal Questions 1 and 2. Toronto: Pontifical Institute of Mediaeval Studies.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aquinas, T. 1259–1265. Summa contra Gentiles = Liber de Veritate Catholicae Fidei contra Errores Infidelium seu Summa contra Gentiles. In Opera Omnia Santi Thomae Aquinatis Doctoris Angelici, t. 2–3. Taurini-Romae: Marietti, 1961. See Rickaby, Joseph. (trans.). 1905. Of God and His Creatures: An Annotated Translation (with Some Abridgement) of the Summa contra Gentiles of Saint Thomas Aquinas. London: Burns and Oates.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aquinas, T. 1265–1268, 1271–1283. Summa Theologiae. In Opera, t. 4–12. Romae: Ex Typographia Polyglotta SC de Propaganda Fide, 1888–1906. See Summa Theologiae. London: Burns & Oates, 1947–48, and London: Eyre & Spottiswoode, 1964–1976.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aquinas, T. 1267. De Regno ad regem Cypri. In Opuscula philosophica, 2nd ed, ed. Spiazzi. Taurini-Romae: Marietti, 1954. See Blythe, James (trans.). 1997. On the Government of Rulers: De Regimine Principum: Ptolemy of Lucca With Portions Attributed to Thomas Aquinas. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, and Phelan, Gerald, and I.Th. Eschmann (trans.). 1949. On Kingship, to the King of Cyprus. Toronto: Pontifical Institute of Mediaeval Studies.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aquinas, T. 1269–1272. Sententia libri Politicorum. In Opera, t. 48. Romae: Ad Sanctae Sabinae, 1971. See Lerner, Ralph, and Muhsin Mahdi (eds.). 1963. Medieval Political Philosophy: A Source Book. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arendt, H. 1958. The human condition. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aroney, N. 2007. Subsidiarity, federalism and the best constitution: Thomas Aquinas on city, province and empire. Law and Philosophy 26: 161.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barber, N.W. 2005. The limited modesty of subsidiarity. European Law Journal 11(3): 308.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barker, E. 1959. The political thought of Plato and Aristotle. New York: Dover Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beer, S. 1986. The rule of the wise and holy: Hierarchy in the thomistic system. Political Theory 14(3): 391–422.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berman, H.J. 1983. Law and revolution: The formation of the Western legal tradition. Harvard: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Black, A.J. 1984. Guilds and civil society in European political thought from the twelfth century to the present. London: Methuen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blythe, J. 1992. Ideal government and the mixed constitution in the Middle Ages. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Booth, W.J. 1981. Politics and the household: A commentary on Aristotle’s politics book one. History of Political Thought 2: 203.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cartledge, P. 2000. Greek political thought: The historical context. In The Cambridge history of Roman and Greek political thought, ed. C. Rowe and M. Schofield. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • de Coulanges, N.D.F. 1956. The ancient city: A study on the religion, laws, and institutions of Greece and Rome. Garden City, New York: Doubleday.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dobbs, D. 1985. Aristotle’s Anticommunism. American Journal of Political Science 29(1): 29.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dobbs, D. 1996. Family matters: Aristotle’s appreciation of women and the plural structure of society. American Political Science Review 90(1): 74.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ehrenberg, V. 1969. The Greek state, 2nd ed. London: Methuen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Everson, S. 1988. Aristotle on the foundations of the state. Political Studies 36: 89.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Everson, S. (ed.). 1996. The politics and the constitution of Athens. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Finley, M.I. 1954. The ancient Greeks and their nation. British Journal of Sociology 5: 253–264.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Finley, M. 1983. Politics in the ancient world. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Finnis, J. 1998. Aquinas: Moral, political, and legal theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert, G. 1895. The Constitutional Antiquities of Sparta and Athens, Trans. E.J. Brooks and T. Nicklin. New York: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilby, Thomas. 1958. The political thought of Thomas Aquinas. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Glotze, G. 1965. The Greek city and its institutions. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul Ltd.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grasso, K. 2008. The subsidiary state: Society, the state and the principle of subsidiarity in Catholic social thought. In Christianity and civil society, ed. J. Heffernan Schindler. Lanham: Lexington Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Herlihy, D. 1983. The making of the medieval family: Symmetry, structure, and sentiment. Journal of Family History 8(2): 116.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hignett, C. 1952. A history of the Athenian constitution to the end of the fifth century B.C. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hittinger, R. 2002. Social pluralism and subsidiarity in Catholic social doctrine. Annales Theologici 16: 385.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jaffa, H. 1972. Aristotle. In History of political philosophy, 2nd ed, ed. L. Strauss and J. Cropsey. Chicago: Rand McNally and Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • John Paul II. 1991. Centesimus Annus: Encyclical letter on the Hundredth Anniversary of Rerum Novarum, May 1.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelly, J. 1993. The influence of Aquinas’ natural law theory on the principle of “corporatism” in the thought of Leo XIII and Pius XI. In Things old and new: Catholic social teaching revisited, ed. F.P. McHugh and S.M. Natale, 104. Lanham, Maryland: University Press of America.

    Google Scholar 

  • Larsen, J.A.O. 1945. Representation and democracy in hellenistic federalism. Classical Philology 40(2): 65.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Larsen, J.A.O. 1968. Greek federal states: Their institutions and history. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leo XIII. 1891. Rerum Novarum: Encyclical letter on capital and labor, May 15.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. 1997. Cleisthenes and Attica. In Selected papers in Greek and near Eastern history. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Lord, C. 1984. The politics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lord, C. 1987. Aristotle. In History of political philosophy, 3rd ed, ed. L. Strauss and J. Cropsey. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Manville, P. 1990. The origins of citizenship in ancient Athens. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Millon-Delsol, C. 1992. L’Etat Subsidiaire. Paris: Presses universitaires de France.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mueller, F.H. 1943. The principle of subsidiarity in the Christian tradition. The American Catholic Sociological Review 4: 144–157.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Müller, K. 1848–1874. Fragmenta historicum graecorum: Apollodori Bibliotheca cum fragmentis, 5 vols. Paris

    Google Scholar 

  • Murphy, M. 1997. Consent, custom, and the common good in Aquinas’s account of political authority. The Review of Politics 59(02): 323.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Murphy, M.C. 2005. The common good. The Review of Metaphysics 59(1): 133.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nederman, C.J. 1987. Aristotle as authority: Alternative Aristotelian sources of late mediaeval political theory. History of European Ideas 8(1): 31–44.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Newman, W.L. 1950. Politics of Aristotle, 3 vols. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pangle, T. 1998. Justice among nations in Platonic and Aristotelian political philosophy. American Journal of Political Science 42(2): 377.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Phelan, G., and I.Th. Eschmann (trans.). 1949. On Kingship, to the King of Cyprus. Toronto: Pontifical Institute of Mediaeval Studies.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pius XI. 1931. Quadragesimo Anno: Encyclical letter on reconstruction of social order, May 15.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rhodes, P.J. 1981. A Commentary on the Aristotelian ‘Athenaion Politeia’. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Robertson, D.B. 1966. Hobbes’s theory of associations in the seventeenth-century milieu. In Voluntary association: A study of groups in free societies. Richmond: John Knox Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Salkever, S. 1990. Finding the mean. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scully, E. 1981. The place of the state in society according to Thomas Aquinas. The Thomist 45(3): 407–429.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sinclair, R. 1988. Democracy and participation in Athens. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Strauss, L. 1977. The city and man. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tierney, B. 1997. The idea of natural rights: Studies on natural rights, natural law and church law 1150–1625. Atlanta: Scholars Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Borries, R., and Malte Hauschild. 1999. Implementing the subsidiarity principle. Columbia Journal of European Law 5: 369.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Gierke, O. 1968. Political Theories of the Middle Age. Trans. F. Maitland. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Whitehead, D. 1986. The Demes of Attica, 508/7-ca. 250 B.C.: A political and social study. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woolf, C.N.S. 1913. Bartolus of Sassoferrato: His position in the political thought of his time. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Nicholas Aroney .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2014 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Aroney, N. (2014). Subsidiarity in the Writings of Aristotle and Aquinas. In: Evans, M., Zimmermann, A. (eds) Global Perspectives on Subsidiarity. Ius Gentium: Comparative Perspectives on Law and Justice, vol 37. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-8810-6_2

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics