Skip to main content

‘Is’, Semantical Games, and Semantical Relativity

  • Chapter
Paradigms for Language Theory and Other Essays

Part of the book series: Jaakko Hintikka Selected Papers ((HISP,volume 4))

Abstract

If there is a doctrine shared by almost all analysts of the semantics of natural language in these days, it is the distinction between the different senses of “is”: the “is” of predication, the “is” of identity, and the “is” of existence. The “is” of predication is often called the copula. Some writers add an alleged “is” of class-inclusion as the fourth reading. The most forceful philosophical proponent of the ambiguity of “is” is undoubtedly Bertrand Russell. In The Principles of Mathematics 1 he writes:

The word is is terribly ambiguous, and great care is necessary in order not to confound its various meanings. We have (1) the sense in which it asserts Being, as in “A is”; (2) the sense of identity; (3) the sense of predication, in “A is human”; (4) the sense of “A is a-man” ... which is very like identity.2 In addition to these there are less common uses... where a relation of assertions is meant ... which ... gives rise to formal implication.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. The Principles of Mathematics (Cambridge University Press, London, 1903; reprinted, George Allen and Unwin, London, 1937); see p. 64, note.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Russell departs from the typical trichotomists and partially anticipates recent treatments of quantifies phrases. On the received view, Russell’s sense (4) has usually been assimilated to the “is” of predication. Fora discussion of some more recent views, see, e.g., Jaakko Hintikka,’Quantifiers in Logic and Quantifiers in Natural Languages’, in S. Körner, editor, Philosophy of Logic (Basil Blackwell, Oxford, 1976), pp. 208–232. A couple of years later Russell changed his mind on this point.

    Google Scholar 

  3. George Allen and Unwin, London, 1914, p. 50.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Frege’s achievement in creating the modern concept of a formal system — as well as his reasons for not discussing semantical matters systematically — are brought out very clearly by Jean van Heijenoort, ‘Logic as Language and Logic as Calculus’, Synthese, Vol. 17 (1967), pp. 324–330.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Cf. also Jean van Heijenoort, editor, From Frege to Gödel (Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Mass., 1967 ).

    Google Scholar 

  6. Frege discusses the different senses of verbs for being in ‘Ober Begriff and Gegenstand’, p. 194 of the original (pp. 43–44 of the Geach and Black translation).

    Google Scholar 

  7. None of these analysts of language has in so many words committed himself to first-order logic as his only canonical notation in semantics. In practice each one of them has nevertheless relied on first-order logic heavily and indeed well-nigh exclusively. The only one of these four scholars whose predilection for standard quantifications! logic is not conspicuous is Noam Chomsky. For evidence, I can now conveniently refer to his new book, Essays on Form and Intcrpremdon, North-Holland, Amsterdam 1977, especially his essay on “Conditions on Rules of Grammar” contained therein. For instance, on p. 197 Chomsky says that his analysis “is pretty much along the lines of standard logical analysis of the sentences of natural language”.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Donald Davidson’s allegiance to quantificational languages is motivated purely pragmatically, as shown by his note ‘Action and Reaction’, Inquiry, Vol. 13 (1970), pp. 140–148. There he points out that his position is even compatible with a relativity of logical form to the underlying logical theory. This point seems to anticipate some of the conclusions I will defend later in the present essay. The important but subtler differences between Davidson and myself in this respect need a longer discussion than I can launch here. (Cf. especially Section 12 below.)

    Google Scholar 

  9. Unsurprisingly, early Wittgenstein maintained the ambiguity of “is”; see Tractatus Logico-Phiosophicus, Kogan Paul, London, 1922, proposition 3.323.

    Google Scholar 

  10. See the papers collected in Esa Saarinen, editor, Game-Theoreticd Semantics (D. Reidel, Dordrecht, 1978), where further references to the literature are also provided. Cf. also Jon Barwise, ‘On Branching Quantifiers in English’, Journd of Philosophical Logic, Vol. 8 (1979), pp. 47–80.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Game-theoretical semantics is accordingly truth-conditional, as I believe every satisfactory semantics must be. Our game rules correspond to the recursive clauses of a Tarskl-type truth-definition. In both, the notions of truth and falsity are largely taken for granted in so far u they apply to atomic sentences, and the main problem is to extend them to other sentences. But the way this extension is accomplished is different in the two cases. In Tarski-type semantics, the recursive clauses which effect the extension apply from the inside out, whereas in game-theoretical semantics the rules have to be applied from the outside in. This has several important consequences, including the ability of game-theoretical semantics to cope with failures of compo-sitionality (also known as the Frege Principle). For such applications, see Jaakko Hintikka’s contribution to Philosophy and Grammar, edited by Stig Ranger and Sven Öhman (D. Reidel, Dordrecht, 1980 ). Also, Tarskl-type truth-definitions assume u it were the pobility of surveying the whole domain D at a glance (in effect, of quanti-fication over D), whereas in game-theoretical semantics we analyze further the specific process that connects the language in question with the reality it can be used to describe.

    Google Scholar 

  12. This fragment is not characterized here explicitly, for it does not matter for the theoretical conclusions of this paper precisely what is and is not included in it. For this theory, cf., e.g., R. Duncan Luce and Howard Raiffa, Games and Decisions ( John Wiley, New York, 1957 ).

    Google Scholar 

  13. This is a much taller order than might first appear. Sentences which are “semantic-ally atomic” in the sense-that their truth-values are determined by the interpretation of the nonlogical words they contain can be far from simple structurally. Unless some-thing more is said, we must for instance allow some “semantically atomic” sentences to be in the passive voice. It seems to me that the perfect complement to game-theoretical semantics as applied to English is Joan Bresnan’s recent theory of certain aspects of the lexical component of English grammar. (Most of it is unpublished; for a partial anticipation, see Joan Bresnan, ‘A Realistic Transformational Grammar’, in Morris Halle et aL, editors, Linguistic Theory and Psychological Reality, M.I.T. Press, Cambridge, Mass., 1978, pp. 1–59.) For Bresnan’s theory provides us with an account of the connections between different semantically atomic sentences which enables us to formulate their precise truth-conditions.

    Google Scholar 

  14. It is important to realize that these are not problems that absolutely have to be solved in order for game-theoretical semantics to be viable. For there is nothing intrinsically meaningless or unsatisfactory about infinite games. However, the psycho-linguistic plausibility of our semantical games would undoubtedly suffer if they could be infinitely long.

    Google Scholar 

  15. In the game rules, “X”, “Y”,… are linguistic rather than logical symbols, referring to linguistic expressions and at the same time acting as placeholders for them, as linguists are wont to expect their symbols to behave.

    Google Scholar 

  16. We also need ordering principles to tell the players in what order the several game rules have to be applied.

    Google Scholar 

  17. In Esa Saarinen, editor, op. cit. (note 6 above), and also in Avishai Margalit, editor, Meaning and Use (D. Reidel, Dordrecht, 1978 ).

    Google Scholar 

  18. See Peter Geach, ‘Good and Evil’, Analysis, VoL 17 (1956), pp. 33–42, and cf. George Curme, English Grammar (1947).

    Google Scholar 

  19. See note 14 above.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Cf., e.g., Edward S. Klima, ‘Negation in English’, in J. J. Katz and Jerry Fodor, editors, The Structure of Language (Prentice-Hall, Englewood Cliffs, N.J., 1964), pp. 246–323 (See especially p. 279 and the references given there in note 12) and Robert P. Stockwell, Paul Schachter, and Barbara Partee, The Major Syntactical Structures of English (Holt, Rinehart and Winston, New York, 1973 ), Chapter 5. “ See note 14 above.

    Google Scholar 

  21. A translation of this kind is part of the program of generative semanticists; cf. George Lakoff, ‘Generative Semantics’, in Danny D. Steinberg and Leon A. Jakobovits, editors, Semantics: An Interdisciplinary Reader (Cambridge U.P., Cambridge, 1971), pp. 232–296. Their theories cannot be considered satisfactory, however. Among other failures, they cannot explain any exceptions to the general ordering principles mentioned in Jaakko Hintikka’s earlier papers.

    Google Scholar 

  22. See Charles Kahn, The Verb “Be” in Ancient Greek (D. Reidel, Dordrecht, 1973); cf. also G. E. L. Owen, ‘Aristotle in the Snares of Ontology’, in R. Bambrough, editor, New Essays on Plato and Aristotle ( Routledge and Regan Paul, London, 1965 ), pp. 69–95.

    Google Scholar 

  23. See De sopkisticis elentchis 166b28–37, 168a34—b10; 169b4–6; 179a33–37.

    Google Scholar 

  24. David Hilbert and Paul Bemays, Grundlagen der Mathematik I—II (Springer, Berlin, 1934–39).

    Google Scholar 

  25. Richmond Thomason, editor, Formal Philosophy: Selected Papers of Richard Montague (Yale U.P., New Haven, 1974), especially Chapter 8.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Cf. SÖren Stenlund, Combinators, X-Terms and Proof Theory (D. Reidel, Dordrecht, 1972), and the references given there.

    Google Scholar 

  27. See Jerry Fodor, The Language of Thought (Thomas Y. Crowell, New York, 1975); and cf. Peter Geach, Mental Acts ( Routledge and Kegan Paul, London, 1957 ).

    Google Scholar 

  28. J. J. Katz, Semantic Theory ( Harper and Row, New York, 1972 ), pp. 3–7.

    Google Scholar 

  29. See Jean van Heijenoort, ‘Logic as Language and Logic as Calculus’, Synthese, Vol. 17 (1967), pp. 324–330.

    Google Scholar 

  30. See Joseph E. Stoy, Denotation! Semantics (MIT Press, Cambridge, Mass., 1977), and references given there to Scott’s work.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Cf., e.g., Jeffrey Pelletier, editor, Mass Terms (D. Reidel, Dordrecht, forthcoming) with a bibliography.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Cf., e.g., Renate Bartsch, Adverbialsemantik (Athenäum, Frankfurt am Main, 1972 ), Chapter 14; Renate Bartsch and Theo Venneman, Semantic Structures ( Athenäum, Frankfurt am Main, 1972 ), Chapter 2.

    Google Scholar 

  33. See Veikko Rantala, ‘Urn Models: A New Kind of Non-Standard Model For First-Order Logic’, Journd of Philosophical Logic, Vol. 4 (1975), pp. 455–474.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  34. See note 6 above.

    Google Scholar 

  35. Acta Philosophcca Fennica, Vol. 28, No. 4 ( North-Holland, Amsterdam, 1976 ).

    Google Scholar 

  36. See, e.g., Knowledge and Belief ( Cornell U.P., Ithaca, N.Y., 1962 ).

    Google Scholar 

  37. See Hintikka (note 33 above), pp. 76–79.

    Google Scholar 

  38. Op. cit., pp. 72–74.

    Google Scholar 

  39. This follows from one of the conversational postulates discussed by Paul Grice, viz. from the one which enjoins a speaker not to make a weaker statement when he is in a position to make a stronger (and. relevant) statement. Hence the main phenomenon adduced by Lauri Karttunen as a reason for preferring his theory of questions, presented in Henry Hiz, editor, Questions (D. Reidel, Dordrecht, 1978), pp. 165–210, receives a most natural explanation on Hintíkka’s theory, too.

    Google Scholar 

  40. Op. cit., Chapters 6, 8–9.

    Google Scholar 

  41. This is not to say that speakers who have been brainwashed into relying on the framework of epistemic logic might not claim that English wh-questions are ambiguous, at least multiple ones. All that they would prove, however, is how easily affected and therefore frequently misleading our so-called intuitions are.

    Google Scholar 

  42. For the theoretical issues involved here, cf. op. cit., Chapters’ and II.

    Google Scholar 

  43. This example seems to originate from Emmon Bach’s unpublished note ‘Anti-pronominalization’ (Department of Linguistics, The University of Texas, January 15, 1969 ).

    Google Scholar 

  44. See The Semantics of Questions (note 33 above), pp. 115–119 and 147–149.

    Google Scholar 

  45. See C. L. Baker, ‘Notes on the Description of English Questions’, Foundations of Language, Vol. 6 (1970), pp. 197–219, for tests that can be used to distinguish free relative clauses from indirect questions, and for references to the linguistic literature relating to the distinction.

    Google Scholar 

  46. Emmon Bach, ’In Defense of Passive’ (unpublished).

    Google Scholar 

  47. Op. Cat. (note 33 above).

    Google Scholar 

  48. Charles Kahn, ‘Questions and Categories’, in Henry Hiz, editor, Questions (D. Reidel, Dordrecht, 1978 ), pp. 227–278.

    Google Scholar 

  49. This last section owes much to Steve Weis!et’s criticisms and comments. (One thing it does not owe to him are whatever mistakes it contains.)

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1998 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Hintikka, J. (1998). ‘Is’, Semantical Games, and Semantical Relativity. In: Paradigms for Language Theory and Other Essays. Jaakko Hintikka Selected Papers, vol 4. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-2531-6_4

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-2531-6_4

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-481-4930-8

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-017-2531-6

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics