Skip to main content

Reference, (In)Commensurability and Meanings

Some (Perhaps) Unanticipated Complexities

  • Chapter
Book cover Incommensurability and Related Matters

Part of the book series: Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science ((BSPS,volume 216))

Abstract

Received conceptions of the meanings of scientific terms assign to meanings an essentially benign methodological role: the meaning of a term consists of principles or inference rules which are, always or for the most part, (approximately) true or reliable. In fact, many scientific terms have meanings which are malignant: which are mainly false or misleading and which detract from, rather than contribute to, scientific progress. Kuhn’s conception of incommensurability can be fruitfully extended to take account of malignant meanings. Malignant meanings are especially implicated in cases, like that of human sociobiology, in which the influence of social ideology on scientific practice is especially profound.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  • Alexander, R. (1979). Darwinism and Human Affairs. Seattle: University of Washington Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alexander, R. (1987). The Biology of Moral Systems. New York: Aldyne de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barash, D. (1979). The Whisperings Within. New York: Harper and Row.

    Google Scholar 

  • Betzig, L., ed. (1997). Human Nature: A Critical Reader. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Block, N. and G. Dworkin, eds. (1976). The IQ Controversy. New York: Pantheon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boyd, R. (1983). “On the Current Status of the Issue of Scientific Realism.” Erkenntnis 19: 45–90.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boyd, R. (1985a). “Lex Orendi est Lex Credendi.” In P.Churchland and Hooker, eds., Images of Science: Scientific Realism Versus Constructive Empiricism. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boyd, R. (1985b). “Observations, Explanatory Power, and Simplicity.” In P. Achinstein and O. Hannaway, eds., Observation, Experiment, and Hypothesis In Modern Physical Science. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boyd, R. (1988). “How to be a Moral Realist.” In G. McCord, ed., Moral Realism. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boyd, R. (1989). “What Realism Implies and What It Does Not.” Dialectica 43: 5–29.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boyd, R. (1990a). “Realism, Approximate Truth and Philosophical Method.” In W. Savage, ed., Scientific Theories, Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science. Volume 14. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boyd, R. (1990b). “Realism, Conventionality, and ‘Realism About’.” In G. Boolos, ed., Meaning and Method. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boyd, R. (1991). “Realism, Anti-Foundationalism and the Enthusiasm for Natural Kinds.” Philosophical Studies 61: 127–148.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boyd, R. (1992). “Constructivism, Realism, and Philosophical Method.” In J. Earman, ed., Inference, Explanation and Other Philosophical Frustrations. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boyd, R. (1993). “Metaphor and Theory Change.” (second version) In A. Ortony, ed., Metaphor and Thought. 2nd edition. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boyd, R. (1995). “Postscript” to “How to be a Moral Realist.” In P. Moser and J. Trout, eds., Contemporary Materialism: A Reader. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boyd, R. (1999). “Kinds as the ‘Workmanship of Men’: Realism, Constructivism, and Natural Kinds.” Proceedings of the Third International Congress, Gesellschaft für Analytische Philosophie. Berlin: de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buss, D. (1989). “Sex Differences in Human Mate Preferences: Evolutionary Hypotheses Tested in 37 Cultures.” Behavior and Brain Sciences 12: 1–14, as reprinted in Betzig 1997.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R. (1950). “Empiricism, Semantics and Ontology.” Revue internationale de philosophie, 4th year.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cosmides, L. and J. Tooby. (1987). “From Evolution to Behavior: Evolutionary Psychology as the Missing Link.” In J. Dupre, ed., The Latest on the Best: Essays on Evolution and Optimality, pp. 277–306, Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Daly, M. and M. Wilson. (1997). “Child Abuse and Other Risks of not Living with Both Parents.” In L. Betzig, ed., Human Nature: A Critical Reader. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feigl, H. (1956). “Some Major Issues and Developments in the Philosophy of Science of Logical Empiricism.” In H. Feigl and M. Scriven, eds., Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, Volume 1. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Field, H. (1973). “Theory Change and the Indeterminacy of Reference.” Journal of Philosophy 70:462–481.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert, A. (1981). “Historical Theory and the Structure of Moral Argument in Marx.” Political Theory 9: 173–205.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert, A. (1982). “An Ambiguity in Marx’s and Engel’s Account of Justice and Equality.” American Political Science Review 76: 328–346.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert, A. (1984). “Marx’s Moral Realism: Eudaimonism and Moral Progress.” In J. Farr and T. Ball, eds., After Marx. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodman, N. (1973). Fact, Fiction and Forecast. 3rd edition. Indianapolis and New York: Bobbs-Merrill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gould, S. and R. Lewontin (1979). “The Spandrels of San Marco and the Panglossian Paradigm: A Critique of the Adaptationist Program.” Proc. Roy. Soc. Lon. (B) 205: 581–598.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hanson, N. (1958). Patterns of Discovery. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hoyningen-Huene, P. (1993). Reconstructing Scientific Revolutions: Thomas S. Kuhn’s Philosophy of Science, trans. A. Levine. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (1985). Vaulting Ambition: Sociobiology and the Quest for Human Nature. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kripke, S. (1971). “Identity and Necessity.” In M. Munitz, ed., Identity and Individuation. New York: New York University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kripke, S. (1972). “Naming and Necessity.” In D. Davidson and G. Harman, eds., The Semantics of Natural Language. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, T. (1970). The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. 2nd edition. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • LeVay, S. (1991). “A Difference in Hypothalamic Structure Between Heterosexual and Homosexual Men.” Science 253: 1034–1037.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • LeVay, S. (1993). Untitled Short Editorial Piece, The Nation, July 5, 1993.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewontin, R. (1976). “Sociobiology — a Caricature of Darwinism.” In PSA 1976 Volume 2, pp. 22–31.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lumsden, C. and E. Wilson. (1981). Genes Mind and Culture: The Coevolutionary Process. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Miller, R. (1985). “Ways of Moral Learning.” Philosophical Review 94: 507–556.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pinker, S. (1996). How the Mind Works. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1962). “The Analytic and the Synthetic.” In H. Feigl and G. Maxwell, eds., Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, Volume3. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1972). “Explanation and Reference.” In G. Pearce and P. Maynard, eds., Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1975a). Mind, Language and Reality. Philosophical Papers, Volume 2. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sherman, P. and H. Reeve. (1997). “Forward and Backward: Alternative Approaches to Studying Human Social Evolution.” In L. Betzig, ed., Human Nature: A Critical Reader. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sturgeon, N. (1984). “Moral Explanations.” In D. Copp and D. Zimmerman, eds., Morality, Reason and Truth. Totowa, N.J.: Rowman and Allanheld.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sturr, C. (1998). Ideology., Discursive Norms and Rationality. Ph.D. Dissertation, Ithaca, New York: Cornell University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thornhill, R. and N. Thornhill. (1990). “An Evolutionary Analysis of Psychological Pain Following Rape: I. The Effects of Victim’s and Marital Status.” Ethology and Sociobiology 11: 155–176.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Trivers, R. (1971). “The Evolution of Reciprocal Altruism.” Quarterly Review of Biology 46: 35–39, 45–47.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williams, G. (1975). Sex and Evolution. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, E. (1975). Sociobiology: The New Synthesis. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, E. (1978). On Human Nature. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wood, A. (1972). “The Marxian Critique of Justice.” Philosophy and Public Affairs 1: 244–282.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wood, A. (1979). “Marx on Right and Justice: A Reply to Husami.” Philosophy and Public Affairs 8: 267–295.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wood, A. (1984). “A Marxian Approach ‘to the Problem of Justice.’” Philosophica 33: 9–32.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2001 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Boyd, R.N. (2001). Reference, (In)Commensurability and Meanings. In: Hoyningen-Huene, P., Sankey, H. (eds) Incommensurability and Related Matters. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol 216. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-9680-0_1

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-9680-0_1

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-481-5709-9

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-015-9680-0

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics