Skip to main content

Further Transcendental Procedures

  • Chapter

Part of the book series: Contributions to Phenomenology ((CTPH,volume 1))

Abstract

As transcendental on-looker attending to the essential demarcations of mental life in the transcendental natural attitude, I have now taken the first step in unbuilding reduction of the fully real, objective world to the primordial quasi-objective world (in the wide sense of the term “primordial”). At the same time, I also indicated the sorts of phenomenological affairs uncovered as peculiar to this “upper story” of oriented constituting.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   169.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. See Dorion Cairns, Conversations with Husserl and Fink, p. 102.

    Google Scholar 

  2. See above, p. 61 for the wide sense of the term, “primordial.”

    Google Scholar 

  3. See Cairns, pp. 45f.

    Google Scholar 

  4. The manuscript is identified as “D 3,” p. 34; cited by Alwin Diemer, Edmund Husserl. Versuch einer systematischen Darstellung seiner Phänomenologie, p. 220, note 99.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Husserl, Ideen II, section 15b, p. 38.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Husserl, Cartesian Meditations, p. 116.

    Google Scholar 

  7. For the Humean dimension of consciousness at issue here, see Aron Gurwitsch, “On the Intentionality of Consciousness,” Studies, pp. 125ff.

    Google Scholar 

  8. See F. Kersten, “William James and Franz Brentano,” pp. 179f.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Husserl, Ideas, I, sections 85, 97. For a careful analysis of the distinctions mantioned here, see Rudolf Boehm, “Les ambiguités des concepts husserliens d’ ‘immanence’ et de ‘transcendence’,” pp. 482–526. See also Harmon Chapman, Sensations and Phenomenology, Chapters V and VII. Chapman notes, p. 150, that the term, “hyletic data,” has a much wider extension than the term, “sense data:” “‘Hyletic data’ embraces the sensory in general, including besides the traditional sensations such sensory impressions as those of pleasure, pain, tickling, kinaesthetic sensations, and the like, also such sensory occurances as impulses, feelings, and emotions in the sphere of the will.” However, the term also has a narrower signification, according to which hyletic data are sharply distinguished from other such data as listed by Chapman precisely because they can be animatingly construed as adumbrations of appearances of something physical—the same cannot be said, on Husserl’s view, of kinaesthesias, impulses, sensations of pleasure and pain. It is the narrower signification of the term, “hyletic data,” with which I deal here, and I believe that it is the basic one for Husserl. The whole question deserves a much longer study; see, in addition, Herman Asemissen, Strukturanalytische Probleme der Wahrnehmung in der Phänomenologie Husserls, section 4ff.; Karl Schuhman, Die Fundamentalbetrachtung der Phänomenologie Zum Weltproblem in der Philosophie Edmund Husserls, pp. 156ff.; Robert Sokolowski, Husserlian Meditations. How Words Present Things, sections 49, 50.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Husserl, Ideas, I, p. 173.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Ibid., pp. 65, 172, 205. See also Husserl, “Vorlesungen zur Phänomenologie des inneren Zeitbewusstseins,” sections 8, 42; and “Notizen zur Raumkonstitution,” pp. 220ff.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Aron Gurwitsch, The Field of Consciousness, pp. 265ff.; see also Chapman, op. cit., Chapter VII; and Sartre, L’Etre et le néant, pp. 26f.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Gurwitsch, p. 269.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Husserl, Ideen, III, p. 14. (The translation is mine.) See also Ideas, I, section 36, p. 65; section 85, p. 172, where Husserl’s distinction between hyletic data and “strivings” [“Triebe”] is misleading because it tends to confuse, for example, the striving to actualize certain kinaesthetic processes with the processes themselves either actualized or to be actualized. The confusion results from what I believe is the mistaken idea that hyletic data are not only involved in doxic sensuous perceivings but also in non-doxic intentionalities as well, such as lovings, hatings, likings, dislikings, appreciaf’ings, approvings, and so forth. Accordingly, Husserl can speak, e.g., of sensations of pleasantness, of sensations of striving. By eventually setting aside as a logical construct Husserl’s idea of hyletic data, and by following instead the phenomenological procedures under discussion here, such “sensations” turn out to be non-existent. That is to say, there are no discoverable cases of hyletic data construed as adumbrations of “pleasant appearances” in and through which something liked is presented. Of course, to assert that there are no “sensations of pleasure” signifies that pleasure is rather a posited character and not a noematic determination. For a somewhat different translation of Husserl’s 1912 manuscript, see Edmund Husserl, Phenomenology and the Foundations of the Sciences, translated by Ted E. Klein and William E. Pohl, pp. 12f.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Husserl, Phänomenologische Psychologie, p. 165. Mention must be made here of the earlier attempt of Sokolowski to untangle the various expressions of Husserl’s concept of hyletic data in The Formation of Husserl’s Concept of Constitution, pp. 51ff., 110ff., 139ff., 210ff. Sokolowski finds a revision of the concept of hyletic data in connection with the development of genetic phenomenology; with that, “sense data and noeses are no longer conceived as two distinct elements; they are now seen to be one immanent reality, one inner flow of consciousness” (p. 211). But this would seem to be Husserl’s view all along according to which the temporal form is the same for hyletic data and noeses; see above, p. 81. To proceed to say that hyletic data are now but one step in genetic constitution (p. 211) would signify, at the very least, that not all noeses and sense data are “one inner flow of consciousness” (hence they are still distinct from other noeses in other steps of genetic constitution). See also Chapman, op. cit., p. 152; Schuhmann, op. cit., pp. 128f., 77ff., and 77, note 3 where the concept of hyletic data is understood as a concept of relation, of the relation of hyle and noesis. The concept of hyletic data is introduced when we ask, not what something transcendent to consiousness is, but instead when we ask how it is constituted; thus Schuh-mann: “Aside from all noetic ‘formation and alteration’--to use Hegel’s phrase--hyle is just an ‘empty place,’ i.e., simply whatever you please. No preformation is derived from it that would only need be repeated, so to speak, by noetic production. Given hyle in and for itself is only the task of positing something or other transcendent. The noetic sense-bestowal effected on it is its determinedness according to independent interpretation” (p. 158). (The translation is mine.) Hyletic data serve, then, to present something transcendent which is real and mundane (pp. 159f.) and as the basis for noetic “interpretation.” It would seem as though Hume and Berkeley had finally joined hands across the Hegelian “empty place.” I am not certain that Schuhmann’s account answers Gurwitsch’s polemical point any better than Sokolowski’s.

    Google Scholar 

  16. See Gurwitsch, op. cit., pp. 114ff., 137ff., 271f.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Husserl, “Vorlesungen,” p. 367.

    Google Scholar 

  18. “Vorlesungen,” section 1, p. 370 (The translation is mine.) cf. English translation, p 44. See also p. 385 for examples of the “temporal content” such as a sound or tone with its “own temporality.” (English translation, pp. 43f.) —The whole issue involved here is complex; in other places in the lectures Husserl is consistent with the concept of hyletic data. Though he may, at times, seem to be unwitting about his concept, in the light of the polemics with respect to which he introduced the concept he was not uncritical. The concept of hyletic data often bothered him, and he seems to have been aware of the fact the account of the constituting of time should confirm or disconfirm what he says about hyletic data; see Ideas, I, pp. 162f.; also Sokolowski, The Formation of Husserl’s Concept of Constitution, p. 140; Schuhmann, p. 77.

    Google Scholar 

  19. See Ideas, I, section 43; Erfahrung und Urteil, section 19.

    Google Scholar 

  20. : See below, Part II, Introduction, where these accounts will be formulated so as to establish a literary and historical framework for specific investigations of space and time. For general overviews, see Maurice Pradine, Philosophie de la sensation, I, pp. 78ff.; Werner Gent, Die Philosophie des Raumes und der Zeit, II, pp. 206ff.; Maurice Merleau-Ponty, Phénoménologie de la perception, Part I, Chapters 1, 2; Part II, Chapter 2; and Heinrich Hofmann, “Untersuchungen über den Empfindungsbegriff,” pp. 37–50. The latter is especially important for the development of the phenomenological “analogue” to nineteenth and twentieth century theories of space perception.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Rudolph Hermann Lotze, Medicinische Psychologie, oder Physiologie der Seele, section 30, pp. 358f., 367–368, and section 31, pp. 381f., 386f. (For a definitive statement some twenty years later, see Lotze’s appendix to Carl Stumpf, Über den psychologischen Ursprung der Raumvorstellung, pp. 315f.) For a more recent version in this century of Lotze’s theory, modified to be sure, see Stephan Witasek, Grundlinien der Psychologie, pp. 171f., 201f. Hermann von Helmholtz, “Die Tatsachen in der Wahrnehmung,” in Vorträge und Reden, pp. 223ff. Oswald Hering, “Der Raumsinn und die Bewegungen des Auges,” in Hermann’s Handbuch der Physiologie, pp. 343ff. Theodor Lipps, “Die Raumanschauung und die Augenbewegungen,” Zeitschrift für Psychologie und Physiologie der Sinnesorgane, III, pp. 124–171. John Stuart Mill, An Examination of Sir William Hamilton’s Philosophy, I, pp. 383ff. Alexander Bain, The Senses and the Intellect, pp. 183f., 366f.

    Google Scholar 

  22. See John Locke, Essay Concerning Human Understanding, Book II, Chapter XIII, sections 2f., 22f.; George Berkeley, A Treatise Concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge, Sections XLIV, CVXf., and A New Theory of Vision, Section XLVI; David Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature, Book I, section 11. A significant discussion of these views is found in Harmon Chapman, op. cit., Chapter IV.

    Google Scholar 

  23. David Katz, Der Aufbau der Tastwelt, sections 2f., 14f., 46ff.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Merleau-Ponty, op. cit., pp. 318f., 323; English translation, pp. 274ff., 278f.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Mill, op. cit., p. 282.

    Google Scholar 

  26. For this transformation of the Kantian set of problems, see Jules Vuillemin, Physique et Métaphysique Kantiennes, section 35f.

    Google Scholar 

  27. See in this connection, William James, Principles of Psychology, II, pp. 270f.; Stumpf, op. cit., pp. 57f.

    Google Scholar 

  28. For a characteristic expression of this view, see Lotze, op. cit., section 28, pp. 328f., section 31, pp. 378f.; Helmholtz, op. cit., p. 228.

    Google Scholar 

  29. See Aron Gurwitsch, The Field of Consciousness, pp. 52ff., 57ff., for an explanation of the sort of fallacy involved in the introduction of such supervenient factors. By rejecting such factors, we do nothing else than reaffirm the basis for rejecting the theory of hyletic data.

    Google Scholar 

  30. For a critical discussion of this view, see Ernst Cassirer, Philosophie der symbolischen Formen, III, Chapter Three.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Husserl, “Die Welt der lebendigen Gegenwart und die Konstitution der ausserleiblishen Umwelt,” pp. 339.; English translation, p. 248, col a.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Husserl, “Notizen zur Raumkonstitution,” p. 28 (the translation is mine); “Welt der lebendigen Gegenwart und die Konstitution der ausserleiblichen Umwelt,” pp. 339.; English translation, p. 248.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Husserl, “Notizen zur Raumkonstitution,” p. 28. Husserl develops this procedure in a number of “D” manuscripts; see for example, those published as Ding and Raum, pp. 309ff. However, Husserl would not seem to recognize the broad sense of the phrase, “setting kinaesthesia at zero.”

    Google Scholar 

  34. See Ding and Raum, p. 328. What I have been considering corresponds to what Husserl there distinguishes as the “second level” of visual space constitution.

    Google Scholar 

  35. See ibid., pp. 309f., 329f., 371f.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Claesges, Edmund Husserls Theorie der Raumkonstitution, p. 100 (the translation is mine). See also Schuhmann, op. cit., pp. 162ff.

    Google Scholar 

  37. See Gurwitsch, op. cit., pp. 71ff., 87ff.

    Google Scholar 

  38. Cf. Claesges, pp. 86f. To be sure, Claesges, pp. 133ff., does seek to reformulate the notion of hyletic data. In so far, he says, as the constituting of the physical thing is concerned, the hyletic datum is to be regarded as an “aspect Datum” [Aspektdatum]; it is, accordingly, treated noetically-noematically--that is, the datum is the noetic correlate of a sensuous intending to it, hence that on which the perceiving of the physical thing is founded. However, Claesges then goes on to say that the hyletic datum is also a “local Datum” [Stellungsdatum], that is, a datum in the “ideal system of loci pertaining to kinaesthe-sias” endowed with the character of sensation and having a role in the constituting of the organism and, therefore, he states, pertaining to the “noetic side of (kinaesthetic) consciousness” (p. 135)—a version of Husserl similar to that of Sokolowski and Schuhmann mentioned earlier where the hyletic datum is both a “content” transcendent to mental life and a “content” of mental life. But by what means is it decided that the datum is one or the other “content”? Or is the datum both at the same time? For a very similar dilemma in William James’s concept of “radical empiricism,” see F. Kersten, “Franz Brentano and William James,” loc. cit., pp. 186f.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1989 Kluwer Academic Publishers

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Kersten, F. (1989). Further Transcendental Procedures. In: Phenomenological Method: Theory and Practice. Contributions to Phenomenology, vol 1. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-2265-5_3

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-2265-5_3

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-94-010-7515-2

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-009-2265-5

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics