Skip to main content

The Objectivist Approach

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Book cover Probability and Social Science

Part of the book series: Methodos Series ((METH,volume 10))

  • 1369 Accesses

Abstract

The objectivist approach of probability cannot be applied to all feelings of uncertainty, but only to events liable to occur in identical conditions, during repeated trials. Different types of axioms were proposed during the beginning of the twentieth century and led to the general acceptation of Kolmogorov’s ones. However, as the probability of a hypothesis is a meaningless notion, we can only test with this approach the probability of obtaining the observed sample if the hypothesis is true. We then give examples of application of this approach to some social sciences (political arithmetic, epidemiology and sociology). Finally we try to identify in more details different problems raised by this analysis and show that, in fact, they are often interlinked.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Tam possum proiicere unum tria quinque, quam duo quatuor sex. Iuxta ergo hanc aeqalitatem pacta constant, si alea sit iusta; & tanto plus, aut minus, quanto a vera aequilitate longius distiterit.

  2. 2.

    Inquirendum nimirum restat, an aucto sic observationum numero ita continuό augeatur probabilitas assequendae genuinæ rationis inter numeros casuum, quibus eventus aliquis contingere & quibus non contingere potest, ut probabilitas hæc tandem datum quemvis certitudinis gradum superet.

  3. 3.

    While Fisher may be viewed as a frequentist in most of his writings, he gave a different definition of probability at the end of his life, noting that ‘no sub-set may be recognizable having a fraction possessing the characteristic differing from the fraction P of the whole’ (Fisher 1960). This concept of probability is generally regarded as unclear and has been little used since (Savage 1976).

  4. 4.

    Ita ex. gr. noti sunt numeri casuum in tesseris; in singulis enim tot manifestè sunt quot hedrae, iique omnes æquè proclives; cùm propter similitudinem hedrarum & conforme tesseræ pondus nulla sit ratio, cur una hedrarum pronior esset ad cadendum quàm altera, quemadmodum fieret, si hedræ dissimilis forent figurae, aut tessera una in parte ex ponderosiore material constaret quàm in altera.

  5. 5.

    eæque faciles.

  6. 6.

    quod sane in usu vitæ ciilis, ubi moraliter certum pro absoulte certo habetur.

  7. 7.

    Indeed, Fréchet (1951) remarks that this principle, while attributed to Cournot, ‘seems to have been already stated more or less clearly by D’Alembert’. But we should note that D’Alembert, while a great mathematician, made a number of errors in his reasoning on probability (Bertrand 1889; Delannoy 1895; Maupin 1895). However, as we shall see later, D’Alembert’s occasionally subjective stance in his reasonings gave rise to some of the criticisms directed against objectivist probabilists.

  8. 8.

    The acronym stands for the Zermelo-Fraenkel theory, formulated with the axiom of Choice.

  9. 9.

    This consistency is essential for the constructivist mathematical school, of which Gauss, Borel and Lebesgue are the best-known representatives: for them, mathematical objects exist only if there is a precise method that tells us how to construct them. By contrast, for the formalist school, of which Moritz Pasch and David Hilbert were the most famous representatives, the lack of contradiction in a system of axioms is a sufficient precondition for accepting that system. Despite siding with the constructivists, von Mises was not unduly troubled by these criticisms. He actually claimed that ‘collectives are in a sense ‘the rule,’ whereas lawfully ordered sequences are ‘the exception’.’

  10. 10.

    For consistency with the notations already used in this chapter, we have modified those used by Kolmogorov.

  11. 11.

    Author of a major work on probability theory (Feller 1950, 1961).

  12. 12.

    Ever since the Observations appeared, it has been claimed that their true author was William Petty. Petty himself claimed authorship when applying for a political office in Ireland. Some observers, such as Le Bras (2000), use this argument to prove that demography never was and never will be a science—contrary to the thesis advocated by Graunt’s supporters. Rather, because of the possibility that Petty might have founded it, demography should be viewed as a political instrument in the hands of political authorities. Le Bras’s contentions—particularly on the determination of the number of deaths—and his attacks on some Graunt specialists hardly allow us to take his demonstration seriously (for more details, see Reungoat 2004).

  13. 13.

    Hacking offers the following argument: ‘Graunt assumes a uniform death rate, that is, that there is a constant chance p of dying in a given year. If the chance of living 10 years is 0.5, consider a population of size N. The number who survive the first year is N(1−p). The number who survive the second is [N(1−p)−pN(1−p)] or N(1−p)2. The number who survive 10 years is N(1−p)10  =  0.5  N. Now let q be the chance that at least one man in a group of ten dies in a given year; then 1−q is the chance that no one dies. This is just (1−p)10, which, solving the above equation is 0.5. So, as Graunt says, q is also 0.5’.

  14. 14.

    We use the standard demographic notation for a probability (quotient), q, which Hacking writes p.

  15. 15.

    Leibniz (1675) gave the correct solution to this problem.

  16. 16.

    ‘quick Conceptions’: ‘live births’ in modern English.

  17. 17.

    Let us again note his misuse of his own table, when he confuses the number of deceased persons and living persons. He gives the percentage of individuals aged between 16 and 56 as 34%, which is in fact the percentage of deaths. According to his life table, the percentage of living persons is in fact 41%.

  18. 18.

    Halley’s exact words are as follows: ‘But the Deduction from those Bills of Mortality seemed even to their Authors to be defective: First, In that the Number of the People was wanting. Secondly, That the Ages of the People Dying was not to be had. And Lastly, That both London and Dublin by reason of the great and casual accession of Strangers who die therein, (as appeared in both, by the great Excess of the Funerals above the Births) rendered them incapable of being Standards for this purpose; [.]’

  19. 19.

    Ignoring Neumann’s table, Jaynes (2003), who describes Halley’s work in detail, regrets that Halley did not supply his data in more detailed form. However, despite Neumann’s detailed table, it is clearly impossible to reconstruct Halley’s tables without additional hypotheses.

  20. 20.

    Interestingly, Neumann distinguished between stillbirths and deaths occurring before the age of 1 year. This would have made it possible to determine separate probabilities of stillbirth and infant mortality.

  21. 21.

    Arbuthnot wrote: ‘in the vast Number of Mortals there would be but a small part of all the possible Chances, for its happening at any assignable time, that an equal Number of Males and Females should be born’.

  22. 22.

    D’Alembert returned to the subject in his twenty-third and twenty-seventh ‘mémoires’ (1768a, b).

References

  • Arbuthnott, J. (1710). An argument for divine providence, taken from the constant regularity observ’d in the birth of both sexes. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London, 27, 186–190.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bacon, F. (1620). Novum Organum. London: J. Bill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bellhouse, D. R. (2011) A new look at Halley’s life table. Journal of the Royal Statistical Society: Series A (Statistics in Society), 174(3), 823–832. The Royal Statistical Society Data Set Website: http://www.blackwellpublishing.com/rss/Readmefiles/A174p3bellhouse.htm. Accessed August 1, 2011.

  • Bernoulli, J. I. (1713). Ars conjectandi. Bâle: Impensis Thurnisiorum fratrum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bernoulli, D. (1760). Essai d’une nouvelle analyse de la mortalité causée par la petite vérole, et des avantages de l’inoculation pour la prévenir. Mémoires de l’Académie Royale des Sciences de l’Année 1760, pp. 1–45.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bertrand, J. (1889). Calcul des probabilités. Paris: Gauthier-Villard et Fils.

    Google Scholar 

  • Borel, E. (1898). Leçons sur la théorie des fonctions. Paris: Gauthier-Villars et fils.

    Google Scholar 

  • Borel, E. (1909). Eléments de la théorie des probabilités. Paris: Librairie Hermann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Borel, E. (1914). Le hasard. Paris: Librairie Félix Alcan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brian, E., & Jaisson, M. (2007). The descent of human sex ratio at birth (Methodos series, Vol. 4). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Broggi, U. (1907). Die Axiome der Wahrscheinlichkeitsrechnung. PhD thesis, Universität Göttingen, Göttingen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cantelli, F. P. (1932). Una teoria astratta del calcolo delle probabilità. Giornale dell’Istituto Italiano degli Attuari, 8, 257–265.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cantelli, F. P. (1935). Considérations sur la convergence dans le calcul des probabilités. Annales de l’I.H.P., 5(1), 3–50.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cantor, G. (1873). Notes historiques sur le calcul des probabilités, Comptes-rendus de la session de l’association de recherche scientifique, Halle, pp. 34–42.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cantor, G. (1874). Über eine Eigenschaft des Inbegriffes aller reellen algebraischen Zahlen. Journal de Crelle, 77, 258–262.

    Google Scholar 

  • Church, A. (1940). On the concept of a random sequence. Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society, 46(2), 130–135.

    Google Scholar 

  • Copeland, A. (1928). Admissible numbers in the theory of probability. American Journal of Mathematics, 50, 535–552.

    Google Scholar 

  • Copeland, A. (1936). Point set theory applied to the random selection of the digits of an admissible number. American Journal of Mathematics, 58, 181–192.

    Google Scholar 

  • Courgeau, D. (Ed.). (2003). Methodology and epistemology of multilevel analysis. Approaches from different social sciences (Methodos series, Vol. 2). Dordrecht/Boston/London: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Courgeau, D. (2004a). Du groupe à l’individu. Synthèse multiniveau. Paris: Ined.

    Google Scholar 

  • Courgeau, D. (2004b). Probabilités, démographie et sciences sociales. Mathématiques et Sciences Humaines, 42(3), 5–19.

    Google Scholar 

  • Courgeau, D. (2007a). Multilevel synthesis. From the group to the individual. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Courgeau, D., & Franck, R. (2007). Demography, a fully formed science or a science in the making. Population-E, 62(1), 39–45 (La démographie, science constituée ou en voie de constitution? Esquisse d’un programme. Population, 62(1), 39–46).

    Google Scholar 

  • Courgeau, D., & Lelièvre, E. (1989). Analyse démographique des biographies. Paris: Ined (English translation: (1992). Event history analysis in demography. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Spanish translation: (2001). Análisis demográfico de las biografías. México: El Colegio de México).

    Google Scholar 

  • Cournot, A.-A. (1843). Exposition de la théorie des chances et des probabilités. Paris: Hachette.

    Google Scholar 

  • D’Alembert, Jl. R. (1761a). Réflexions sur le calcul des Probabilités. In Opuscules Mathématiques (Vol. Tome II, pp. 1–25). Paris: David (Dixième Mémoire).

    Google Scholar 

  • D’Alembert, Jl. R. (1761b). Sur l’application du calcul des probabilités à l’inoculation de la petite vérole. In Opuscules Mathématiques (Vol. Tome II, pp. 26–46). Paris: David (Onzième mémoire).

    Google Scholar 

  • D’Alembert, Jl. R. (1768a). Extrait de plusieurs lettres de l’auteur sur différents sujets, écrites dans le courant de l’année 1767. In Opuscules Mathématiques (Vol. Tome IV, pp. 61–105). Paris: David (Vingt-troisième mémoire).

    Google Scholar 

  • D’Alembert, Jl. R. (1768b). Extraits de lettres sur le calcul des probabilités et sur les calculs relatifs à l’inoculation. In Opuscules Mathématiques (Tome IVth ed., pp. 283–341). Paris: David (Vingt-septième mémoire).

    Google Scholar 

  • de Moivre, A. (1711). De mensura sortis, seu, de probabilitate eventuum in ludis a casu fortuito pendentibus. Philosophical Transactions, 27(329), 213–264.

    Google Scholar 

  • de Moivre, A. (1718). The doctrine of chances: Or a METHOD of calculating the probabilities of events in PLAY. London: Millar (Third edition: 1756).

    Google Scholar 

  • de Montessus, R. (1908). Leçons élémentaires sur le calcul des probabilités. Paris: Gauthier Villars.

    Google Scholar 

  • de Montmort, P. R. (1713). Essay d’analyse sur les jeux de hazard (2nd ed.). Paris: Jacques Quillau.

    Google Scholar 

  • Delannoy, M. (1895). Sur une question de probabilités traitée par d’Alembert. Bulletin de la S.M.F., Tome 23, 262–265.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dellacherie, C. (1978). Nombres au hasard de Borel à Martin Löf, Gazette des Mathématiques du Québec, 11, 1978. (Version remaniée de l’Institut de Mathématiques, Université Louis-Pasteur de Strasbourg, (1978), 30 p).

    Google Scholar 

  • Descartes, R. (1647). Méditations, objections et réponses. In Œuvres et lettres. Paris: Gallimard.

    Google Scholar 

  • Durkheim, E. (1895). Les règles de la méthode sociologique. Paris: Alcan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Durkheim, E. (1897). Le suicide. Paris: Alcan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feller, W. (1934). Review of Kolmogorov (1933). Zentralblatt für Mathematik und ihre Grenzegebiete, 7, 216.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feller, W. (1950). An introduction to the theory of probability and its applications (Vol. 1). New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feller, W. (1961). An introduction to the theory of probability and its applications (Vol. 2). New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fisher, R. A. (1922b). On the mathematical foundations of theoretical statistics. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society Series A, 222, 309–368.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fisher, R. A. (1923). Statistical tests of agreement between observation and hypothesis. Economica, 3, 139–147.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fisher, R. A. (1935). The logic of inductive inference. Journal of the Royal Statistical Society, 98, 39–82.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fisher, R. A. (1956). Statistical methods and scientific inference. Edinburgh: Oliver and Boyd.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fisher, R. A. (1958). The nature of probability. Centennial Review, 2, 261–274.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fisher, R. A. (1960). Scientific thought and the refinement of human reasoning. Journal of the Operations Research Society of Japan, 3, 1–10.

    Google Scholar 

  • Franck, R. (2007). Peut-on accroître le pouvoir explicatif des modèles en économie ? In A. Leroux & P. Livet (dir.), Leçons de philosophie économique (Tome III, pp. 303–354). Paris: Economica.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fréchet, M. (1915). Sur l’intégrale d’une fonctionnelle étendue à un ensemble abstrait. Bulletin de la S.M.F., Tome 43, 248–265.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fréchet, M. (1938). Exposé et discussion de quelques recherches récentes sur les fondements du calcul des probabilités. In R. Wavre (Ed.), Les fondements du calcul des probabilités (Vol. II, pp. 23–55). Paris: Hermann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fréchet, M. (1951). Rapport général sur les travaux du calcul des probabilités. In R. Bayer (Ed.), Congrès International de Philosophie des Sciences, Paris, 1949; IV: Calcul des probabilités (pp. 3–21). Paris: Hermann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, M., & Savage, L. J. (1948). The utility analysis of choices involving risk. The Journal of Political Economy, LVI(4), 279–304.

    Google Scholar 

  • Galileo, G. (1613). Istoria e dimostrazioni intorno alle macchie solari e loro accidenti. Roma: Giacomo Mascardi.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gosset, W. S. (1908a). The probable error of a mean. Biometrika, 6(1), 1–25 (Student).

    Google Scholar 

  • Gosset, W. S. (1908b). Probable error of a correlation coefficient. Biometrika, 6(2–3), 302–310 (Student).

    Google Scholar 

  • Graetzer, J. (1883). Edmund Halley und Caspar Neumann: Ein Beitrag zur Geschichte der Bevölkerungsstatistik. Breslau: Schottlaender.

    Google Scholar 

  • Granger, G.-G. (1994). Formes, opérations, objets. Paris: Librairie Philosophique Vrin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Graunt, J. (1662). Natural and political observations mentioned in a following index, and made upon the bills of mortality. London: Tho: Roycroft, for John Martin, James Allestry, and Tho: Dicas. (French translation by Vilquin E., Observations Naturelles et Politiques répertoriées dans l’index ci-après et faites sur les bulletins de mortalité. (1977). Paris: Ined).

    Google Scholar 

  • Hacking, I. (1975). The emergence of probability. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hadamard, J. (1922). Les principes du calcul des probabilités. Revue de Métaphysique et de Morale, 29(3), 289–293.

    Google Scholar 

  • Halley, E. (1693). An estimate of the degrees of the mortality of mankind, drawn from curious tables of the births and funeral’s at the City of Breslau; with an attempt to ascertain the price of the annuities upon lives. Philosophical Transactions Giving some Accounts of the Present Undertaking, Studies and Labour of the Ingenious in many Considerable Parts of the World, XVII(196), 596–610.

    Google Scholar 

  • Henry, L. (1957). Un exemple de surestimation de la mortalité par la méthode de Halley. Population, 12(1), 141–142.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hilbert, D. (1902). Mathematical problems. Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society, 8(2), 437–439.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hoem, J. (1983). Multistate mathematical demography should adopt the notions of event history analysis. Stockholm Research Reports in Demography, 10.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jaynes, E. T. (2003). Probability theory: The logic of science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kamke, E. (1932). Über neure Begründungen der Wahrscheinlichkeitsrechnung. Jahresbericht der Deutschen Mathematiker-Vereinigung, 42, 14–27.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kendall, M. G. (1963). Ronald Aylmer Fisher, 1890–1962. Biometrika, 50(1/2), 1–15.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kolmogorov, A. (1933). Grundbegriffe der wahrscheinlichkeitsrenung. In Ergebisne der Mathematik, (Vol. 2) Berlin: Springer (English translation, Morrison, N. (1950). Foundations of the theory of probability New York: Chelsea).

    Google Scholar 

  • Kolmogorov, A. (1951). Bepoятнocть (Probability). In Great Soviet encyclopedia (Vol. 7, pp. 508–510). Moscow: Soviet Encyclopedia Publishing House.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, T. (1962). The structure of scientific revolutions. Chicago/London: The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, T. (1970). Postscript-1969. In The structure of scientific revolutions (2nd ed., pp. 174–210). Kuhn/Chicago/London: The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laemmel, R. (1904). Untersuchungen über die Ermittlung von Wahrscheinlichkeiten. PhD, Universität Zürich.

    Google Scholar 

  • Le Bras, H. (2000). Naissance de la mortalité. L’origine politique de la statistique et de la démographie. Paris: Seuil/Gallimard.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lebesgue, H. (1901). Sur une généralisation de l’intégrale définie. Comptes Rendus de l’Académie des Sciences, 132, 1025–1028.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leibniz, G.W. (1675). De problemata mortalitatis propositum per ducem de Roannez. Partie A du manuscrit traduite en français par M. Parmentier (1995). Paris: Librairie Philosophique Vrin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lévy, P. (1925). Calcul des probabilités. Paris: Gauthier-Villars.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lévy, P. (1936). Sur quelques points de la théorie des probabilités dénombrables. Annales de l’Institut Henri Poincaré, 6(2), 153–184.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lévy, P. (1937). Théorie de l’addition des variables aléatoires. Paris: Gauthier-Villars.

    Google Scholar 

  • Martin-Löf, P. (1966). The definition of random sequences. Information and Control, 7, 602–619.

    Google Scholar 

  • Masterman, M. (1970). The nature of a paradigm. In I. Lakatos & A. Musgrave (Eds.), Criticism and the growth of knowledge (pp. 59–89). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Matalon, B. (1967). Epistémologie des probabilités. In J. Piaget (Ed.), Logique et connaissance scientifique (pp. 526–553). Paris: Gallimard.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maupin, M. G. (1895). Note sur une question de probabilités traitée par d’Alembert dans l’encyclopédie. Bulletin de la S.M.S., Tome 23, 185–190.

    Google Scholar 

  • McKinsey, J. C. C., Sugar, A., & Suppes, P. (1953). Axiomatic foundations of classical particle mechanics. Journal of Rational Mechanics and Analysis, 2, 273–289.

    Google Scholar 

  • Newton, I. (1687). Philosophia naturalis principia mathematica. Londini: S. Pepys.

    Google Scholar 

  • Neyman, J., & Pearson, E. S. (1928). On the use and interpretation of certain test criteria for purposes of statistical inference. Part I. Biometrika, 20A, 175–240.

    Google Scholar 

  • Neyman, J., & Pearson, E. S. (1933a). On the problem of the most efficient tests of statistical hypotheses. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London Series A, 231, 289–337.

    Google Scholar 

  • Neyman, J., & Pearson, E. S. (1933b). The testing of statistical hypotheses in relation to probabilities a priori. Proceedings of the Cambridge Philosophical Society, 26, 492–510.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pearson, K. (1900). On the criterion that a given system of deviations from the probable in the case of a correlated system of variables is such that it can be reasonably supposed to have arisen from random sampling. Philosophical Magazine, 50(5th series), 157–175.

    Google Scholar 

  • Poincaré, H. (1912). Calcul des probabilités. Paris: Gauthier-Villars.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. (1959). The propensity interpretation of probability. Philosophy of Science, 10, 25–42.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. (1982). The postscript to the logic of scientific discovery (Quantum theory and the schism in physics, Vol. III). London: Hutchinson.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. (1983). The postscript of the logic of scientific discovery (Realism and the aim of science, Vol. I). London: Hutchinson.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pressat, R. (1966). Principes d’analyse. Paris: INED.

    Google Scholar 

  • Radon, J. (1913). Theorie und Anwendungen der absolut Additiven Mengenfunktionen. Sitzungsberichte der kaiserlichen Akademie der Wissenschaften, Mathematisch-Naturwissenschaftliche Klasse 122 IIa , 1295–1438.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reungoat, S. (2004). William Petty. Observateur des Îles Britanniques. Classiques de l’économie et de la population. Paris: Ined.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rohrbasser, J.-M. (2002). Qui a peur de l’arithmétique? Les premiers essais de calcul sur les populations dans la seconde moitié du XVIIe siècle. Mathématiques et Sciences Humaines, 159, 7–41.

    Google Scholar 

  • Royall, R. M. (1970). On finite population theory under certain linear regression models. Biometrika, 57(2), 377–387.

    Google Scholar 

  • Savage, L. J. (1976). On reading R.A. Fisher. The Annals of Statistics, 4(3), 441–500.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shafer, G., & Vovk, V. (2005). The origins and legacy of Kolmogorov’s Grundbegriffe. Working paper 4, Project web site: http://probabilityandfinance.com, 104 p. Accessed July 11, 2011.

  • Steinhaus, H. (1923). Les probabilités dénombrables et leur rapport à la théorie de la mesure. Fundamenta Mathematicae, 4, 286–310.

    Google Scholar 

  • Suppe, F. (1989). The semantic conception of theories and scientific realism. Urbana/Chicago: University of Illinois Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Suppes, P. (2002a). Representation and invariance of scientific structures. Stanford: CSLI Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Suppes, P. (2002b). Representation of probability. In P. Suppes (Ed.), Representation and invariance of scientific structures (pp. 129–264). Stanford: CSLI Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Süssmilch, J. P. (1741). Die göttliche Ordnung in den Veränderungen des menschlichen Geschlechts, aus der Geburt, Tod, und Fortpflanzung desselben erwiesen. Berlin: zu finden bei J.C. Spener.

    Google Scholar 

  • Todhunter, I. (1865). A history of the theory of probability from the time of Pascal to that of Laplace. Cambridge/London: Macmillan and Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tornier, E. (1929). Wahrscheinlichkeisrechnunug und zalhlentheorie. Journal für die Teine und Angewandte Mathematik, 60, 177–198.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Fraassen, B. (1980). The scientific image. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Imhoff, E., & Post, W. (1997). Méthodes de micro-simulation pour des projections de population, Population (D. Courgeau ed), 52 (4), pp. 889–932 ((1998). Microsimulation methods for population projections. Population. An English Selection (D. Courgeau ed), 10 (1), pp. 97–138).

    Google Scholar 

  • van Lambalgen, M. (1987). Von Mises’ definition of random sequences reconsidered. The Journal of Symbolic Logic, 32(3), 725–755.

    Google Scholar 

  • Venn, J. (1866). The logic of chance. London: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ville, J. A. (1939). Étude critique de la notion de collectif. Paris: Gauthier-Villars.

    Google Scholar 

  • Voltaire (1734). Lettre XI. Sur l’insertion de la petite vérole. In Lettres Philosophiques, Basle.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Mises, R. (1919). Grundlagen der wahrscheinlichkeitesrechnung. Mathematische Zeitschrift, 5, 52–99.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Mises, R. (1928). Wahrscheinlichkeit, Statistik und Wahrheit. Wien: Springer (English translation: (1957). Probability, statistics and truth. London: George Allen & Unwin Ltd).

    Google Scholar 

  • von Mises, R. (1932). Théorie des probabilités. Fondements et applications. Annales de l’Institut Henri Poincaré, 3(2), 137–190.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Neumann, J., & Morgenstern, O. (1944). Theory of games and economic behaviour. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Waismann, F. (1930). Logische Analyse des wahrscheinlichkeisbegriffs. Erkenntnis, 1, 228–248.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wald, A. (1936). Sur la notion de collectif dans le calcul des probabilités. Comptes Rendus des Séances de l’Académie des Sciences, 202, 180–183.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wargentin, P. W. (1766). Mortalité en Suède, selon le ‘Tabel-Verket’. Actes de l’Académie des Sciences de Stockholm.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wavre, R. (1938–1939). Colloque consacré à la théorie des probabilités, Fascicules 734–740; 766. Paris: Hermann.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2012 Springer Science+Business Media B.V.

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Courgeau, D. (2012). The Objectivist Approach. In: Probability and Social Science. Methodos Series, vol 10. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-2879-0_1

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics