Skip to main content

Examples

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
  • 534 Accesses

Part of the book series: Studies in Linguistics and Philosophy ((SLAP,volume 89))

Abstract

When the semantics of predicate logic is based on concepts rather than relations, there no longer is a compositional context free grammar for it unless we restrict ourselves to a finite variable fragment. This shows that there is a semantic reason for the much discussed syntactic bottlenecks (or phases). It is furthermore argued that LF as used in Generative Grammar cannot rely on free variables in the way it does. Once this is acknowledged, however, it becomes possible to actually argue that sentences must have a particular syntactic structure since they do not allow for a compositional analysis of meaning. In particular, Dutch is not strongly context free if the semantics is spelled out in terms of concepts rather than relations. Further constructions being looked at include the English X-or-no-X-construction and respectively-constructions.

In this chapter we shall look at some examples. The first example will be standard predicate logic. It will be shown that if semantics is based on concepts and not on relations then there must be a limit on the number of free variables. The second example will be a fragment (Montague size) of English. Finally, we shall indicate how the present approach allows to get insights into sentence structure.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    This name is due to Kit Fine, which he used during a lecture at UCLA.

  2. 2.

    It is a subtle matter to see in what ways such meaning facts can at all bear on the question whether one sentence is derived from another. This is because interpretation happens only once in a derivation. The argument would roughly be this. Suppose that meaning is established at the beginning of the derivation (at deep structure). Now suppose that S is (more precisely: must be) derived from S through a transformation. Then the derivation that yields S from its deep structure also derives S on the way. Same deep structure, same meaning. (A dual argument can be used if interpretation is established at LF.) Hence if the two sentences have different meaning they cannot stem from the same deep structure.

References

  • Chomsky, Noam. 1986. Barriers. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fine, Kit. 2003. “The Role of Variables.” Journal of Philosophy 50:605–31.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gazdar, Gerald, Ewan Klein, Geoffrey Pullum, and Ivan Sag. 1985. Generalized Phrase Structure Grammar. London: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harrison, Michael A. 1978. Introduction to Formal Language Theory. Reading, MA: Addison Wesley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heim, Irene, and Angelika Kratzer. 1998. Semantics in Generative Grammar. Oxford: Blackwell Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huybregts, Riny. 1984. “Overlapping Dependencies in Dutch.” Utrecht Working Papers in Linguistics 1:3–40.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kac, Michael B., Alexis Manaster-Ramer, and William C. Rounds. 1987. “Simultaneous-Distributive Co-ordination and Context-Freeness.” Computational Linguistics 13:25–30.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kamp, Hans, and Uwe Reyle. 1993. From Discourse to Logic. Introduction to Modeltheoretic Semantics of Natural Language, Formal Language and Discourse Representation. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kracht, Marcus. 1995. “Syntactic Codes and Grammar Refinement.” Journal of Logic, Language and Information 4:41–60.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kracht, Marcus. 2003. Mathematics of Language. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Monk, Donald J. 1976. Mathematical Logic. Berlin, Heidelberg: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shieber, Stuart. 1985. “Evidence Against the Context–Freeness of Natural Languages.” Linguistics and Philosophy 8:333–43.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Steedman, Mark. 1990. “Gapping as Constituent Coordination.” Linguistics and Philosophy 13:207–63.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wechsler, Stephen. 1995. The Semantic Basis of Argument Structure. Dissertations in Linguistics. Stanford, CA: CSLI.

    Google Scholar 

  • Groenink, Annius. 1997. Surface Without Structure. Word Order and Tractability Issues in Natural Language Analysis. PhD thesis, University of Utrecht.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rogers, James. 1994. Studies in the Logic of Trees with Applications to Grammar Formalisms. PhD thesis, University of Delaware, Department of Computer & Information Sciences.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Marcus Kracht .

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2011 Springer Science+Business Media B.V.

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Kracht, M. (2011). Examples. In: Interpreted Languages and Compositionality. Studies in Linguistics and Philosophy, vol 89. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-2108-1_5

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics