Skip to main content

A Formal Logical Hybrid Theory of Argumentation and Explanation

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
  • 1043 Accesses

Part of the book series: Law and Philosophy Library ((LAPS,volume 92))

Abstract

A logical account of the hybrid theory. This logical theory combines abductive, model-based reasoning (as is often used in diagnostical knowledge systems) with a formal framework for defeasible argumentation. A formal dialogue game, detailing a protocol for a rational discussion about the facts, is also defined.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD   169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    The formal theory has been published in a more condensed form as (Bex et al., 2010).

  2. 2.

    This conception of rule is based on, but not the same, as Hage and Verheij’s definition of a rule, see (Verheij et al., 1998) 2003 .

  3. 3.

    Note that these rules may have different names in the various deductive systems. See (Gabbay et al., 1993) for an overview.

  4. 4.

    Hage’s theory of rules and reasons was initiated by Hage and further formally developed in cooperation with Verheij (cf. Verheij, 1996; Verheij et al., 1998) .

  5. 5.

    Sartor argues that the legality of a (legal) norm (n: pq is legal), modelled in the logic of Prakken and Sartor (Prakken and Sartor, 1996, see p. 4), allows for the derivation of the norm n itself.

  6. 6.

    For more on the discussion of model-theoretic semantics for nonmonotonic logics, see Prakken and Vreeswijk, 2002.

  7. 7.

    Prakken uses the argumentation system from his thesis in much of his work and has proposed extensions of his basic work together with Sartor (e.g. Prakken and Sartor, 1997). In this thesis, I will mostly refer to Prakken’s original system.

  8. 8.

    art. 339 par. 1 sub. 1 and art. 340 DPC, which determine that a judge’s observations are legally valid evidence.

  9. 9.

    Formally, consistency of the set I E can only be defined if the pieces of evidence are not labelled with their names. However, here it will be simply assumed that consistency is determined on the basis of the propositional content of the evidential data, ignoring the names.

  10. 10.

    Strictly speaking, these events can be either events or states of affairs.

  11. 11.

    However, model-based diagnosis should not be equated with abductive reasoning, as there are other types of model-based reasoning (e.g. Bayesian Belief Networks) and other types of symbolic diagnosis (e.g. consistency-based diagnosis). See Lucas, 1997 for an overview.

  12. 12.

    In the current framework, time is not explicitly represented. However, it is assumed that events can only be caused by other events which precede them and thus a sequence of events implicitly assumes temporal relations between the events.

  13. 13.

    Recall that a suspect’s testimony is here also regarded as a witness testimony.

  14. 14.

    However, in the simple examples below the arguments for the explananda will often not be explicitly mentioned.

  15. 15.

    Note that a player may be committed to two arguments that attack each other or to two alternative explanations for the explananda.

  16. 16.

    See (Bex and Prakken, 2004) for a way to integrate such a speech act in a dialogue game similar to the current game.

References

  • Allen, J.F. and Ferguson, G. (1994) Actions and events in interval temporal logic. Journal of Logic and Computation 4:5, 531–579.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bex, F.J., van Koppen, P.J., Prakken, H. and Verheij, B. (2010) Evidence for a good story – a hybrid theory of arguments, stories and criminal evidence. Artificial Intelligence and Law 18, 2.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bex, F.J. and Prakken, H (2004) Reinterpreting arguments in dialogue: an application to evidential reasoning. JURIX 2004: The 17th Annual Conference, 119–129, IOS Press, Amsterdam.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bex, F.J. and Prakken, H. (2008) Investigating stories in a formal dialogue Game. Computational Models of Argument. Proceedings of COMMA 2008, 73–84, IOS Press, Amsterdam.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bex, F.J., Prakken, H., Reed, C. and Walton, D.N. (2003) Towards a formal account of reasoning about evidence: argumentation schemes and generalisations. Artificial Intelligence and Law 11, 125–165.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bex, F.J., Prakken, H. and Verheij, B. (2007a) Formalising argumentative story – based analysis of evidence. Proceedings of the 11th International Conference on Artificial Intelligence and Law, 1–10, ACM Press, New York, (New York).

    Google Scholar 

  • Bondarenko, A., Dung, P.M., Kowalski, R.A. and Toni, F. (1997) An abstract, argumentation – theoretic approach to default reasoning. Artificial Intelligence 93:1–2, 63–101.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bylander, T., Allemang, D., Tanner, M.C. and Josephson, J.R. (1991) The computational complexity of abduction. Artificial Intelligence 49:1–3, 25–60.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Console, L. and Dupré, D.T. (1994) Abductive reasoning with abstraction axioms. Lecture Notes in Computer Science, Vol. 810, 98–112, Springer, Berlin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Console, L. and Torasso, P. (1991) A spectrum of logical definitions of model – based diagnosis. Computational Intelligence 7:3, 133–141.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Poot, C.J., Bokhorst, R.J., Koppen, P.J. van and Muller, E.R. (2004) Rechercheportret – Over Dillemma’s in de Opsporing, Kluwer, Alphen a.d. Rijn.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dung, P.M. (1995) On the acceptability of arguments and its fundamental role in nonmonotonic reasoning, logic programming and n – person games. Artificial Intelligence 77:2, 321–357.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gabbay, D.M., Hogger, C.J. and Robinson, J.A. (1993) Handbook of Logic in Artificial Intelligence and Logic Programming, Volume 1, Logical Foundations, Oxford University Press, Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gordon, T.F., Prakken, H. and Walton, D. (2007) The Carneades model of argument and burden of proof. Artificial Intelligence 171:10–15, 875–896.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hage, J.C. (1996) A theory of legal reasoning and a logic to match. Artificial Intelligence and Law 4:3, 199–273.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kautz, H.A. (1991) A formal theory of plan recognition and its implementation. In Allen, J.F., Kautz, H.A., Pelavin, R.N., and Tenenberg, J.D. (eds.), Reasoning About Plans, 69–124, Morgan Kaufmann, San Mateo (California).

    Google Scholar 

  • Konolige, K. (1994) Using default and causal reasoning in diagnosis. Annals of Mathematics and Artificial Intelligence 11:1, 97–135.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Loui, R.P. (1998) Process and policy: resource – bounded nondemonstrative reasoning. Computational Intelligence 14:1, 1–38.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lucas, P. (1997) Symbolic diagnosis and its formalisation. The Knowledge Engineering Review 12, 109–146.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pollock, J.L. (1987) Defeasible reasoning. Cognitive Science 11:4, 481–518.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pollock, J.L. (1995) Cognitive Carpentry: A Blueprint for How to Build a Person, MIT Press, Cambridge (Massachusetts).

    Google Scholar 

  • Poole, D. (1988) A logical framework for default reasoning. Artificial Intelligence 36:1, 27–47.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Poole, D. (1994) Representing diagnosis knowledge. Annals of Mathematics and Artificial Intelligence 11:1, 33–50.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Prakken, H. (1997) Logical Tools for Modelling Legal Argument, Kluwer Academic Publishers, Dordrecht.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prakken, H. (2005b) Coherence and flexibility in dialogue games for argumentation. Journal of Logic and Computation 15, 1009–1040.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Prakken, H. (2006) Formal systems for persuasion dialogue. The Knowledge Engineering Review 21:02, 163–188.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Prakken, H. and Sartor, G. (1996) A dialectical model of assessing conflicting arguments in legal reasoning. Artificial Intelligence and Law 4:3, 331–368.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Prakken, H. and Sartor, G. (1997) Argument – based extended logic programming with defeasible priorities. Journal of Applied Non – classical Logics 7, 25–75.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prakken, H. and Vreeswijk, G. (2002) Logics for defeasible argumentation. In Goebel, R. and Guenthner, F. (eds.), Handbook of Philosophical Logic, 219–318, Kluwer Academic Publishers, Dordrecht.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rahwan, I., Ramchurn, S.D., Jennings, N.R., McBurney, P., Parsons, S. and Sonenberg, L. (2004) Argumentation – based negotiation. The Knowledge Engineering Review 18:04, 343–375.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rahwan, I. and Reed, C. (2009) The argument interchange format. In Rahwan, I. and Simari, G. (eds.), Argumentation in Artificial Intelligence, Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reiter, R. (1980) A logic for default reasoning. Artificial Intelligence 13, 81–132.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sartor, G. (2008) Legality Policies and Theories of Legality: From ‘Bananas’ to Radbruch’s Formula. EUI Working Papers LAW 27.

    Google Scholar 

  • Verheij, B. (1996) Rules, Reasons, Arguments: Formal Studies of Argumentation and Defeat, Doctoral dissertation, University of Maastricht.

    Google Scholar 

  • Verheij, B. (2003a) DefLog: On the logical interpretation of prima facie justified assumptions. Journal of Logic and Computation 13:3, 319–346.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Verheij, B. (2003b) Dialectical argumentation with argumentation schemes: an approach to legal logic. Artificial Intelligence and Law 11:2, 167–195.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Verheij, B. (2005a) Evaluating arguments based on Toulmin’s scheme. Argumentation 19:3, 347–371.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Verheij, B., Hage, J.C. and Herik, H.J. van den. (1998) An integrated view on rules and principles. Artificial Intelligence and Law 6:1, 3–26.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Walton, D.N. (2002) Legal Argumentation and Evidence, Penn, State University Press, University Park (Pennsylvania).

    Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, T.J., Schum, D.A. and Twining, W.L. (2005) Analysis of Evidence, 2nd edition, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Braak, S.W. van den (2010) Sensemaking Software for Crime Analysis. Doctoral dissertation, Intelligent Systems Group, Utrecht University (SIKS Dissertation Series No. 2010–2012).

    Google Scholar 

  • Wagenaar, W.A., Koppen, P.J. van and Crombag, H.F.M. (1993) Anchored Narratives: The Psychology of Criminal Evidence, St. Martin’s Press, New York (New York).

    Google Scholar 

  • Keppens, J. and Schafer, B. (2005) Assumption – based peg unification for crime scenario modelling. JURIX 2005: The 18th Annual Conference, 49–58, IOS Press, Amsterdam.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kowalski, R. and Sergot, M. (1986) A logic – based calculus of events. New Generation Computing 4:5, 67–94.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Floris J. Bex .

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2011 Springer Science+Business Media B.V.

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Bex, F.J. (2011). A Formal Logical Hybrid Theory of Argumentation and Explanation. In: Arguments, Stories and Criminal Evidence. Law and Philosophy Library, vol 92. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-0140-3_5

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics