Skip to main content

Kant’s Idealism on a Moderate Interpretation

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Book cover Kant's Idealism

Part of the book series: The New Synthese Historical Library ((SYNL,volume 66))

Abstract

For many interpreters, the holy grail of Kant scholarship is to find a meaning for the doctrine of transcendental idealism that is not only consistent, understandable in its origins, and not immediately absurd, but also does full justice to the complex fact that Kant insists on claiming both that there are ‘real appearances’ (Erscheinungen in contrast to blosser Schein), that is, appearances disclosing to us features of physical objects that are empirically real, and also that these features are nonetheless ‘mere appearances’ in contrast to ‘things in themselves’.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    See e.g., McDowell (1994: 42ff.); and Wood (2005). See my discussion of Wood’s treatment of idealism in Ameriks (forthcoming).

  2. 2.

    See e.g., Allison (2006). Wood (2005: 74) inclines strongly to favoring this reading, but he also recognizes that there are considerations that speak against it, offered by interpreters such as Guyer and Adams.

  3. 3.

    In the light of points made by Lucy Allais, I have come to prefer the term ‘moderate’, rather than terms such as ‘modesty’ or ‘humility’, because this term more directly indicates the ‘in-between’ status that is crucial here. On many points related to these issues I am very indebted to discussions with participants at conferences on this topic in London and Amsterdam.

  4. 4.

    See especially Allais (2007); Rosefeldt (2007); and my Interpreting Kant’s Critiques (Ameriks 2003, Chaps. 12, 13, and 14). Brief anticipations of this approach can be found in a remark about idealism as “a principle of modesty” in my Kant’s Theory of Mind (Ameriks 1982, 7), as well as in my review of Kantian Humility, by Rae Langton, in Ameriks (2000c). More extensive defenses of this general approach are given in my Interpreting Kant’s Critiques, ‘Introduction’, and Kant and the Historical Turn: Philosophy as Critical Interpretation (Ameriks 2006, Chaps. 3, 5, and 6). In this essay, I am primarily concerned with explaining just the general idea of the Moderate Interpretation, and for a more direct discussion of specific passages in Kant’s texts the reader is referred to the works cited in the footnotes.

  5. 5.

    See McDowell (2001, Chaps. 6 and 7), McGinn (1999, Chaps. 15 and 16), and Stroud (2000).

  6. 6.

    For details, see again the works cited above in note 4 above.

  7. 7.

    See Kant, Critique of the Power of Judgment (1790), §14. Stroud happens to discuss the example of green from a somewhat similar perspective in Stroud (1999: 170–171).

  8. 8.

    Kant contrasts his position with that of Locke and others in the Critique at Aix; A29=B45, and Prolegomena to any Future Metaphysics that Will be able to Come Forth as a Science (1783), First Part, Notes II and III (AA 4: 288–294).

  9. 9.

    See Kant’s use of these terms in the Prolegomena at AA 4: 287–294, and for further references see my Kant and the Historical Turn (Ameriks 2006, Chap. 3).

  10. 10.

    Hence I take Kant’s claim (Bxxvii) that it is absurd to speak of an appearance without anything that appears to be a substantive point with realist implications that are both empirical and not merely empirical.

  11. 11.

    A28=B44 (translations of the Critique of Pure Reason are from the Kemp Smith edition). Kant jumps hastily to presuming that space and time are the “only” such forms, because these forms have a special universal significance. He thereby overlooks the fact that even space may not be a fully universal structure of appearance (sounds, for example, might appear without appearing as spatial), and there may be other ways in which (other less than fully universal) features such as color and sound can also involve necessary structures, even of a synthetic a priori kind, that supplement the more general structures of space and time.

  12. 12.

    See B112. This point is already made in Metaphysics Herder, in Kant (1997: 3) (AA 28: 39).

  13. 13.

    I use the plural term for convenience here. Kant does not provide a theoretical argument for a plurality of things in themselves, but it is clear that he never takes monism very seriously.

  14. 14.

    See A226=B273. A ‘non-accidental modification’ would be one, for example, that would allow us, even ‘in this world’, to know things in a determinate non-sensory way.

  15. 15.

    See my ‘Hegel and Idealism’ (Ameriks 1991); Kant and the Fate of Autonomy (Ameriks 2000a, 276, n. 18); ‘Introduction: Interpreting German Idealism’ (Ameriks 2000b); and Kant and the Historical Turn (Ameriks 2006, Chap. 6).

  16. 16.

    See Beiser (2003).

  17. 17.

    See especially Kant’s essay ‘contra Eberhard’, On a Discovery whereby any New Critique of Pure Reason is Made Superfluous by an Older One (1790) in AA 8: 185–251, and see above note 8.

  18. 18.

    Even though Kant’s view is more metaphysical in his Inaugural Dissertation (On the Form and Principles of the Sensible and the Intelligible World), it is worth noting that even then, when he claims that there are some truths about things in themselves that we can determine, he does not go so far as to relapse into a Leibnizian view that there is an in principle analytically traceable connection that reveals the positive nature of particular finite things in themselves to be a full explanatory ground of the nature of corresponding particular appearances.

  19. 19.

    Here I am merely explaining the basic meaning of Kant’s position, and not endorsing or even trying to analyze in detail the Dialectic’s specific arguments. I concede that these arguments rest on several controversial presumptions, especially about the kind of quantitative determinacy that features supposedly would require in order to characterize things as things in themselves. See my Interpreting Kant’s Critiques (Ameriks 2003, Chap. 3).

  20. 20.

    See Langton (2007); and my Interpreting Kant’s Critiques (Ameriks 2003, Chap. 11). Something that Kant calls ‘unconditioned’ does not have to be unconditioned in all respects but can be unconditioned simply in respect to a particular category.

  21. 21.

    I will avoid the term ‘intrinsic’ here because it is now much disputed, after Langton’s interpretation and reactions to it, whether features of things in themselves must (as she contends) be non-relational, or non-dispositional, or (by definition, given, the mere addition of something like ‘the non-reducibility thesis’) non-phenomenal. On critiques of views in Langton’s Kantian Humility (Langton 1998), see Allais (2006); and my Interpreting Kant’s Critiques (Ameriks 2003, Chap. 5).

  22. 22.

    For a discussion and criticism of this inference, see my Kant’s Theory of Mind (Ameriks 1982, Chap. 7).

  23. 23.

    It may look as if I am concluding that there is nothing very odd about Kant’s doctrine of the ideality of all our determinate theoretical self-knowledge—but in fact this doctrine can be considered quite questionable as long as it rests on the general controversial doctrines that all our determinate self-knowledge really does have to involve spatiotemporal characterizations and that the metaphysical status of temporality in particular is in no way absolute.

  24. 24.

    Hanna (2006: 5).

  25. 25.

    Hanna (2006: 30).

  26. 26.

    Hanna (2006: 14).

  27. 27.

    Hanna (2006: 32).

  28. 28.

    Hanna (2006: 142, my emphasis; cf. ibid., 29).

  29. 29.

    I am using ‘noumenal’ in a broad sense, at first just to contrast with what is manifest or phenomenal, and leaving other characteristics open for the discussion that follows.

  30. 30.

    See Sellars (1963); and for a very helpful overview see C. F. Delaney (1977).

  31. 31.

    This is a term that Hanna invokes near the end of his book (2006: 439), for his own purposes in trying to construct a broadly naturalistic Kantian practical philosophy. See below, at n.39.

  32. 32.

    See Greene (2004: 472).

  33. 33.

    See above note 21.

  34. 34.

    See above note 21.

  35. 35.

    Hanna (2006: 32; cf. ibid., 169).

  36. 36.

    A802=B830.

  37. 37.

    Critique of the Power of Judgment, §90 (AA 5: 468; translation Pluhar).

  38. 38.

    Critique of Practical Reason (1788), Preface (translation Gregor).

  39. 39.

    Hanna (2006: 444).

  40. 40.

    Hanna (2006: 444).

  41. 41.

    Hanna (2006: 447).

  42. 42.

    See Kant, Critique of the Power of Judgment, §90 (AA 5: 464n.); and see my ‘The End of the Critiques: Kant’s Moral “Creationism”’ (Ameriks 2008).

  43. 43.

    See A537=B565, where Kant writes that “if […] appearances are not viewed as things in themselves […] they must themselves have grounds which are not appearances […][and] the consequence of insisting upon the [absolute] reality of appearances is to destroy all freedom” (translation modified).

References

  • Allais, L. 2006. ‘Intrinsic Natures: A Critique of Langton on Kant’. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 73: 143–169.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Allais, L. 2007. ‘Kant’s Idealism and the Secondary Quality Analogy’. Journal of the History of Philosophy 45: 459–484.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Allison, H. 2006. ‘Transcendental Realism, Empirical Realism, and Transcendental Idealism’. Kantian Review 11: 1–28.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ameriks, K. 1982. Kant’s Theory of Mind. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ameriks, K. 1991. ‘Hegel and Idealism’. The Monist 74: 386–402.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ameriks, K. 2000a. Kant and the Fate of Autonomy: Problems in the Appropriation of the Critical Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ameriks, K. 2000b. ‘Introduction: Interpreting German Idealism’. In K. Ameriks (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to German Idealism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 1–17.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Ameriks, K. 2000c. Review of Rae Langton Kantian Humility. Philosophical Books 41: 111–113.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ameriks, K. 2003. Interpreting Kant’s Critiques. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ameriks, K. 2006. Kant and the Historical Turn: Philosophy as Critical Interpretation. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ameriks, K. 2008. ‘The End of the Critiques: Kant’s Moral “Creationism”’. In P. Muchnik (ed.), Rethinking Kant: Volume 1. Newcastle: Cambridge Scholars Publishers, pp. 165–190.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ameriks, K. forthcoming. ‘On Reconciling the Transcendental Turn and Kant’s Idealism’. In S. Gardner (ed.), The Transcendental Turn. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beiser, F. 2003. ‘Two Concepts of Reason in German Idealism’. Internationales Jahrbuch des Deutschen Idealismus/International Yearbook of German Idealism 1: 15–27.

    Google Scholar 

  • Delaney, C. F. 1977. The Synoptic Vision. Essays on the Philosophy of Wilfrid Sellars. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Greene, B. 2004. The Fabric of the Cosmos: Space, Time and the Texture of Reality. New York: Random House.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hanna, R. 2006. Kant, Science, and Human Nature. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. 1997. Lectures on Metaphysics. Trans. and ed. K. Ameriks and S. Naragon. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Langton, R. 1998. Kantian Humility. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Langton, R. 2007. ‘Objective and Unconditioned Value’. The Philosophical Review 116: 157–185.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, J. 2001. Mind, Value and Reality. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, J. 2004. Mind and World. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McGinn, C. 1999. Knowledge and Reality: Selected Essays. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosefeldt, T. 2007. ‘Dinge an sich und sekundäre Qualitäten’. In J. Stolzenberg (ed.), Kant in der Gegenwart. Berlin and New York: de Gruyter, pp. 167–209.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Sellars, W. 1963. Science, Perception and Reality. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul and New York: Humanities Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stroud, B. 1999. ‘The Goal of Transcendental Arguments’. In R. Stern (ed.), Transcendental Arguments: Problems and Prospects. Oxford: Clarendon Press, pp. 155–172.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stroud, B. 2000. The Quest for Reality: Subjectivism and the Metaphysics of Color. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wood, A. 2005. Kant. Malden, MA: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Karl Ameriks .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2010 Springer Science+Business Media B.V.

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Ameriks, K. (2010). Kant’s Idealism on a Moderate Interpretation. In: Schulting, D., Verburgt, J. (eds) Kant's Idealism. The New Synthese Historical Library, vol 66. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-90-481-9719-4_2

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics