Skip to main content

Positivism Challenged: Interpretation, Integrity, and Law

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
  • 1813 Accesses

Abstract

Sometimes jurisprudence mimics the physical world, each new theory provoking an opposite and sometimes equally powerful theory. This is not an iron law, perhaps, but the claim is borne out by developments in Anglo-American jurisprudence the last quarter of the twentieth century. Hart’s powerful restatement of positivism at mid-century stimulated a revival of natural-law jurisprudence in the last two decades of the century. From different philosophical quarters, a variety of theories emerged pursuing quite different theoretical agendas, but all were united in their opposition to positivism. Rejecting Hart’s underlying empiricism, anti-positivist theories like those of John Finnis (1980, 1992, 1998) and Ernest Weinreb (1988, 1995) revived rationalist jurisprudence; Aristotle, Aquinas, and Kant, rather than Hume and Bentham, provided the philosophical foundations for these two quite different contemporary natural-law theories (see below, chap. 12). In contrast, Michael Moore (1985, 1992, 1995) offered a thoroughly modern, revisionist naturallaw theory, drawing on philosophical realism in contemporary metaphysics and meta-ethics. In Chapter 12, we will consider the most influential of these natural-law theories, but in this chapter we explore positivism’s most widely discussed challenger, Ronald Dworkin’s interpretive jurisprudence and “law as integrity.”

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   119.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   159.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   159.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Bibliography

  • ———. 1999b. “With Me, It’s All er Nuthin’”: Formalism in Law and Morality. University of Chicago Law Review 66: 530–64.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1990. Critical Legal Studies: A Liberal Critique. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aristotle. The Politics. Trans. T.A. Sinclair. Baltimore: Penguin Books, 1962.

    Google Scholar 

  • Austin, J.L. 1956–1957. A Plea for Excuses. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 57 (N.S.): 1–30.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burley, Justine. 2004. Ronald Dworkin and His Critics. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Burton, Steven J. 1987. Ronald Dworkin and Legal Positivism. Iowa Law Review 73: 109–29.

    Google Scholar 

  • Coleman, Jules L. 1982. Negative and Positive Positivism. Journal of Legal Studies 11: 139–64.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2000. Constraints on the Criteria of Legality. Legal Theory 6: 171–83.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2001b. Tort Law and Tort Theory: Preliminary Reflections on Method. In Philosophy and the Law of Torts. Ed. Gerald J. Postema, 183–213. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2002. Methodology. In The Oxford Handbook of Jurisprudence and Philosophy of Law. Ed. Jules Coleman and Scott Shapiro, 311–51. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2009. Beyond Inclusive Legal Positivism. Ratio Juris 22: 359–94.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, Ronald. 1963. Judicial Discretion. Journal of Philosophy, 60: 624–38.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1978. Taking Rights Seriously. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1983. A Reply by Ronald Dworkin. In Ronald Dworkin and Contemporary Jurisprudence. Ed. Marshall Cohen, 247–300. Totowa, NJ: Rowman & Allanheld.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1985. A Matter of Principle. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1986. Law’s Empire. Cambridge, MA: Belnap.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1987. Legal Theory and the Problem of Sense. In Issues in Contemporary Legal Philosophy. Ed. Ruth Gavison, 9–20. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1996c. Objectivity and Truth: You’d Better Believe It. Philosophy and Public Affairs 25: 87–139.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2006. Justice in Robes. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2001. Herbert Hart and the Semantic Sting. In Hart’s Postscript. Ed. Jules Coleman, 39–58. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1980. Natural Law and Natural Rights. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1987. On Reason and Authority in Law’s Empire. Law and Philosophy 6: 357–80.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1992. Natural Law and Legal Reasoning. In Natural Law Theory. Ed. Robert P. George, 134–57. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1998. Aquinas: Moral, Political, and Legal Theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fuller, Lon L. and William R. Perdue. 1936–1937. The Reliance Interest in Contract Damages. Yale Law Journal 46: 52–96, 373–420.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1987b. Legal Theory and the Problem of Sense: Comment. In Issues in Contemporary Legal Philosophy. Ed. Ruth Gavison, 21–34. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1987. The Political Content of Legal Theory. Philosophy of the Social Sciences 17: 1–20.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Green, T.H. 1889–1890. Works, 3 vols. Ed. R.L. Nettleship. London: Longmans, Green.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2006b. How Facts Make Law II. In Exploring Law’s Empire: The Jurisprudence of Ronald Dworkin. Ed. Scott Hershovitz, 265–90. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1955b. Review of Hägerström’s Inquiries into the Nature of Law and Morality. Philosophy 30: 369–73.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1987. Legal Theory and the Problem of Sense: Comment. In Issues in Contemporary Legal Philosophy: The Influence of H.L.A. Hart. Ed. Ruth Gavison, 35–42. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1994. The Concept of Law. 2nd ed. with Postscript. Ed. Penelope A. Bulloch and Joseph Raz. Oxford: Clarendon. (1st ed. 1961.)

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2002c. Substance and Method in Conceptual Jurisprudence and Legal Theory. Virginia Law Review 88: 1119–228.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2000. A Treatise of Human Nature. Ed. David Fate Norton and Mary J. Norton. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kramer, Matthew. 1999. In Defense of Legal Positivism: Law Without Trimmings. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kress, Kenneth. 1987. The Interpretive Turn. Ethics 97: 834–60.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1999. Coherentist Methodology is Morally Better than Either it Proponents or its Critics Think (But Still Not Good Enough). The Canadian Journal of Law and Jurisprudence 12: 83–108.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1996. Legal Realism. In A Companion to Philosophy of Law and Legal Theory. Ed. Dennis Patterson, 261–79. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1977. Principles, Positivism, and Legal Theory. Yale Law Journal 87: 415–35.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1993. The Moral Aspect of Legal Theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mackie, John. 1983. The Third Theory of Law. In Ronald Dworkin and Contemporary Jurisprudence. Ed. Marshall Cohen, 161–70. Totowa, NJ: Rowman & Allanheld.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marmor, Andrei. 1992. Interpretation and Legal Theory. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2006b. Legal Positivism: Still Descriptive and Morally Neutral. Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 26: 683–704.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Michelman, Frank I. 1986. The Supreme Court, 1985 Term: Foreword: Traces Of Self-Government. Harvard Law Review 100: 4–77.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moore, Michael. 1985. A Natural Law Theory of Interpretation. Southern California Law Review 58: 277–398.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1992. Moral Reality Revisited. Michigan Law Review 90: 2424–533.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1995. Good Without God. In Natural Law, Liberalism, and Morality. Ed. Robert P. George, 221–70. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2000. Educating Oneself in Public. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1997. Two Models of Principles. Iowa Law Review 82: 787–819.

    Google Scholar 

  • Postema, Gerald J. 1980. Bentham and Dworkin on Positivism and Adjudication. Social Theory and Practice 5: 347–76.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1997. Integrity: Justice in Workclothes. Iowa Law Review 82: 821–56.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2010b. Positivism and the Separation of Realists from their Skepticism: Normative Guidance, the Rule of Law, and Legal Reasoning. In The Hart-Fuller Debate in the 21st Century. Ed. Peter Cane, 259–79. Oxford: Hart.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1971. A Theory of Justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1983. Legal Principles and the Limits of Law. In Ronald Dworkin and Contemporary Jurisprudence. Ed. Marshall Cohen, 73–87. Totowa, NJ: Rowman & Allenheld.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2001b. Two Views of the Nature of the Theory of Law: A Partial Comparison. In Hart’s Postscript, Ed. Jules Coleman, 1–37. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Réaume, Denise. 1989. Is Integrity a Virtue? Dworkin’s Theory of Legal Obligation. University of Toronto Law Journal 39: 380–409.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2007. Ronald Dworkin. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sartorius, Rolf. 1971. Social Policy and Judicial Legislation. American Philosophical Quarterly 8: 151–60.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1991b. Rules and the Rule of Law. Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy 14: 645–94.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1996. Positivism as Pariah. In The Autonomy of Law. Ed. Robert P. George, 31–55. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2002b. Law, Plans, and Practical Reason. Legal Theory 8: 387–441.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Simmonds, N.E. 1987. Imperial Visions and Mundane Practices. Cambridge Law Journal 46: 465–88.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Soper, E. Philip. 1983. Legal Theory and the Obligation of a Judge: The Hart/Dworkin Dispute. In Ronald Dworkin and Contemporary Jurisprudence. Ed. Marshall Cohen, 3–27. Totowa, NJ: Rowman & Allanheld.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stavropoulos, Nicos. 1996. Objectivity in Law. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2001. Hart’s Semantics. In Hart’s Postscript. Ed. Jules Coleman, 59–98. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2009d. Who Needs Rules of Recognition? In The Rule of Recognition and the U.S. Constitution. Ed. Matthew Adler and Kenneth Himma, 327–49. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Waluchow, W.J. 1994. Inclusive Legal Positivism. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zipursky, Benjamin. 2001. The Model of Social Facts. In Hart’s Postscript. Ed. Jules Coleman, 219–70. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2011 Springer Science+Business Media B.V.

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Postema, G.J. (2011). Positivism Challenged: Interpretation, Integrity, and Law. In: A Treatise of Legal Philosophy and General Jurisprudence. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-90-481-8960-1_9

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics