Skip to main content
  • 1824 Accesses

Abstract

In this article, I introduce some main strands in the philosophical debate on the nature of causation. I begin by sketching David Hume’s influential discussion of causation (1739–1740). I then outline some modern descendants of Hume’s regularity theory, most importantly the necessary and sufficient conditions approach, and counterfactual theories, highlighting along the way the various problems faced by such accounts. I then introduce the main competitor to these theories, namely process-based accounts, and end by discussing problematic cases of causation by absence.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    This approach is also sometimes named the epistemic approach, because of its initial motivation by epistemic concerns. As we shall see, however, in more recent developments of the conditional approach, the focus on epistemic concerns has receded, making the more neutral term ‘conditional’ more appropriate.

  2. 2.

    Ducasse (1926) actually defends a version this view, but it has few modern adherents.

  3. 3.

    For a recent exposition and discussion of Hume’s theory of causation, see Beebee (2006)

  4. 4.

    For a selection of such theories, see Mill (1843), Braithwaite (1953), Hempel (1965) and Hart and Honere (1959).

  5. 5.

    For a selection of influential proposals, see Reichenbach (1956), Salmon (1980a), Cartwright (1979), and Hitchcock (1993).

  6. 6.

    For a recent discussion and modification, see Ramachandran (2004).

  7. 7.

    For more on Lewis’ ban on ‘backtracking conditionals’, see Lewis (1979; 1986); for criticism, see in particular Fine (1975), Horwich (1989), and Price (1992).

  8. 8.

    Wesley Salmon develops a very similar theory in his (1998).

  9. 9.

    Lewis employs a more complicated definition of biff, designed to satisfy the further desiderata of making causation an intrinsic relation, but I will not go into that here. For more on biff and intrinsicness, see Menzies (1999) and Lewis (2004b).

  10. 10.

    I have changed his notation in accordance with the convention adopted in this article.

References

  • Anscombe, G.E.M. 1971. Causality and determination. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beebee, H. 2004. Causing and nothingness. In Causation and counterfactuals, eds. J. Collins, et al. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beebee, H. 2006. Hume on causation. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Braithwaite, R.B. 1953. Scientific explanation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, N. 1979. Causal laws and effective strategies. Nous 13:419–439

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dowe, P. 2000. Physical causation. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dowe, P. 2001. A counterfactual theory of prevention and “causation” by omission. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 79:16–26.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dowe, P. 2004. Causes are physically connected to their effects: why preventers and omissions are not causes. In Contemporary debates in philosophy of science, ed. C. Hitchcock. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ducasse, C.J. 1926. On the nature and observability of the causal relation. Journal of Philosophy 23:57–68

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fine, K. 1975. Review of counterfactuals by David Lewis. Mind 84:451–458.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hall, N. 2004a. Two concepts of causation. In Causation and counterfactuals, eds. J. Collins, et al. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hall, N. 2004b. Causation and the price of transitivity. In Causation and counterfactuals, eds. J. Collins, et al. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hart, H.L.A., and A.M. Honore. 1959. Causation in the law. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, C.G. 1965. Aspects of scientific explanation. New York, NY: The Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hitchcock, C. 1993. A generalized probabilistic theory of causal relevance. Synthese 97:335–364

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hitchcock, C. 1995. Salmon on explanatory relevance. Philosophy of Science 62:304–320

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Horwich, P. 1989. Asymmetries in time. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hume, D. 1978. A treatise of human nature. ed. L.A. Selby-Bigge (orig.), 1739–1740. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kim, J. 1973. Causes and counterfactuals. Journal of Philosophy 70:570–572

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kvart, I. 1991. Transitivity and preemption of causal impact. Philosophical Studies 64:125–160

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. 1973a. Counterfactuals. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. 1973b. Causation. Journal of Philosophy 70:556–567

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. 1979. Counterfactual dependence and time’s arrow. Nous 13:455–476

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. 1986. Postscripts to “causation”. Philosophical Papers II. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. 2000. Causation as influence. Journal of Philosophy 97:182–197

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. 2004a. Causation as influence (expanded version). In Causation and counterfactuals, eds. J. Collins, et al. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. 2004b. Void and object. In Causation and counterfactuals, eds. J. Collins, et al. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mackie, J.L. 1965. Causes and conditions. American Philosophical Quarterly 2/4:245–255; 261–264

    Google Scholar 

  • Mellor, D.H. 1995. The facts of causation. London: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Menzies, P. 1999. Intrinsic versus extrinsic conceptions of causation. In Causation and laws of nature, ed. H. Sankey. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Menzies, P. 2004. Difference-making in context. In Causation and counterfactuals, eds. J. Collins, et al. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mill, J.S. 1843. A system of logic. London: Longmans.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pearl, J. 2000. Causality. Models, reasoning, and inference. Hardcover: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Price, H. 1992. Agency and causal asymmetry. Mind 101:501–520, New York: New York Academy of Sciences.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ramachandran, M. 2004. A counterfactual analysis of indeterministic causation. In Causation and counterfactuals, eds. J. Collins, et al. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reichenbach, H. 1956. The direction of time. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Salmon, W. 1980a. Probabilistic causality. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 61:50–74

    Google Scholar 

  • Salmon, W. 1980b. Causality: production and propagation. In Oxford readings in philosophy: Causation(Reprinted), eds. E. Sosa, et al. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Salmon, W. 1998. Causality and explanation. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Schaffer, J. 2000a. Trumping preemption. Journal of Philosophy 97:165–81

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schaffer, J. 2000b. Causation by disconnection. Philosophy of Science 67:285–300

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schaffer, J. 2001. Causes as probability raises of processes. Journal of Philosophy 98:75–92

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schaffer, J. 2004. Causes need not be physically connected to their effects: The case for negative causation. In Contemporary debates in philosophy of science, ed. C. Hitchcock. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stalnaker, R. 1968. A theory of conditionals. In Studies in logical theory, ed. N. Rescher. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tooley, M. 2003. Causation and supervenience. In Oxford handbook of metaphysics, eds. M. Loux, et al. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I wish to thank Johanna Seibt for helpful comments on an earlier draft of this article, and the Danish Research Council for Culture and Communication for financial support.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Asbjørn Steglich-Petersen .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2010 Springer Netherlands

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Steglich-Petersen, A. (2010). Causation. In: Poli, R., Seibt, J. (eds) Theory and Applications of Ontology: Philosophical Perspectives. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-90-481-8845-1_4

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics