Skip to main content

Early Confucian Perspectives on Emotions

  • Chapter
  • First Online:

Part of the book series: Dao Companions to Chinese Philosophy ((DCCP,volume 3))

Abstract

The emotions were a central and constant feature of early ethical debates from antiquity onwards. Early Chinese thinkers diverged greatly in their attitudes toward the emotions, and in how they imagined their place in moral life. While for Confucius (Kongzi 孔子, 551–479 BCE) the morally cultivated person was one whose virtue was completed by joy and pleasure, likes and dislikes, and the fulfillment of his own desires, the Daodejing 道德經 called for the eradication of these very emotions and desires as a prerequisite to the achievement of oneness with the Way. While Mencius (Mengzi 孟子, 372–289 BCE) reasoned that certain innate feelings constituted the natural beginnings, or “sprouts” (duan 端) of virtue and moral action, Mozi 墨子(c. 480–390 BCE) regarded spontaneous feelings as inherently partial and thus the cause of injustice, corruption and extravagance on the part of rulers. Underlying such radically diverging perspectives on the role of emotions in moral and political were, more fundamentally, competing visions of what it meant to be human and how to fully realize our moral potential: do we achieve our proper human state through stillness, oneness, and solitude, or through movement, change, and engagement in the world of people and things? Can we rely on our "natural" and spontaneous feelings to lead us to right action or must we constrain and order these feelings through our intelligence and the use of institutions and cultural forms?

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Notes

  1. 1.

    The question of whether early Chinese thinkers themselves saw thinking and feeling (or reason and emotion) as distinct has been an issue of deep controversy. See, e.g., the debate over the cognitive content of Mencius’ view of emotions in Wong 1991 and Ihara 1991. Recently, Liu Qingping has challenged the traditional enterprise of analyzing the history of Chinese philosophy in terms of the presence or non-presence of “rational principles” by proposing that Chinese thought is rooted in “emotional principles” (see Liu 2011).

  2. 2.

    For positions on this debate over early meanings of qing, see, among others, Graham 1990: 59; Hansen 1995: 194–203; Allan 1997: 85; and Puett 2004: 37–43. Christoph Harbsmeier has written about the wide semantic range of the term qing, differentiating among seven basic groups of meanings. See Harbsmeier 2004. Eifring 2004 offers the most focused and historically comprehensive survey of qing and its evolving conceptions from antiquity through imperial times.

  3. 3.

    For an extensive discussion of how this correspondence plays out in traditional Chinese thinking about literature, see Owen 1985. Among later thinkers who opposed this merging of self and world (as conceived in terms of the pairing, qing 情 and jing 景) and stressed the importance of recognizing the subjective and objective as distinct realms, was Wang Fuzhi, who believed that their confounding resulted in a failure to see things in their true aspect. On this subject see Wong Siu-kit 1978.

  4. 4.

    Like many early texts, there is a messy textual history behind the Analects and we cannot, properly speaking assume that the received text represents the collected sayings of a historical figure Kong Qiu of Lu. I will refer to the Master’s voice in the text as “Confucius” out of a convenience justified by its general unity of perspective.

  5. 5.

    The translations given in this chapter are modified from Lau 1982. The given source passages from the Lunyu follow the format in Lau, Wah and Ching (1995a), which is given as ICS Lunyu. I have also actively consulted Edward Slingerland’s 2003 translation.

  6. 6.

    Shun Kwong-loi has thus argued for a broadened conception of ren as a “cluster of emotional dispositions and attitudes” that are embodied in li. In this context, Shun notes, li should likewise be considered more broadly as various norms that govern human conduct,” rather than as “ritual propriety,” which is the conventional translation. Shun 2002: 67.

  7. 7.

    Herbert Fingarette has likewise argued for an understanding of Confucian ritual in a way that emphasizes the aspect of commitment – focusing, however, on the way in which ritual enables individuals to actualize their virtue and create a sense of the sacred through the forging of community. In this way, ritual enables one’s moral convictions to become outwardly visible, transmuting moral identity into socially-embedded conduct (Fingarette 1998: 1–17).

  8. 8.

    See Yuri Pines’ important study of the intellectual and historical background to the emergence of Confucian thought (Pines 2002).

  9. 9.

    The “we” here needs to be qualified, for Confucius does not necessarily assume a universal “we.” It is, after all, only those who have embarked upon an arduous path of self-cultivation who are able to “fully realize their desires without crossing the line.” Moreover, as Erica Brindley has shown, the very possibility of this self-cultivation is strictly delimited by class and gender (Brindley 2009).

  10. 10.

    This increasing emphasis on realms of human life that are within human control can be seen in the evolving history of core concepts that would become central to Confucius’ ethical vision: tian 天 (Heaven), de 德 (virtue), ming 命 (mandate) ren 仁 (humaneness, etc). See Pines 2002: 164–204.

  11. 11.

    Herbert Fingarette has noted the “absence of an elaborated doctrine of an ‘inner psychic life’” in the Analects, arguing, however, that the vision of self found in this text is distinctive in Asian philosophical traditions in its assertion of the self and its aspirations as both positive and meaningful. Based on his examination of vocabulary connected to self and to willing (ji 己, shen 身, 欲, and zhi 志), Fingarette concludes, “Confucius is affirmative, rather than negative, about the role of personal will and of the self it expresses. Specifically, Confucius appeals to us to activate our will – something only we as individuals can do – as a prime means of realizing the ideal life” (Fingarette 1979: 134).

  12. 12.

    See Behuniak 2005: 1–22 for a thorough account of the conceptual history of qi and its connection to moral thought in Mencius’ thought and in Warring States philosophy in general. On the central role of qi in Mencius’ conception of the heart and of self-cultivation, see Chan 2002b.

  13. 13.

    For a comprehensive discussion of the moral and conceptual background of the issues discussed here, see Shun 1997.

  14. 14.

    Mencius 4A15; ICS Mengzi 7.15/38/14–15. “Mencius said, ‘There is in man nothing more ingenuous than the pupils of his eyes. They cannot conceal his wickedness. When he is upright within his breast, a man’s pupils are clear and bright; when he is not, they are clouded and murky. How can a man conceal his true character if you listen to his words and observe the pupils of his eyes?” Translations from the Mencius are adapted from Lau 1970. Original passage citations follow the format of Lau, Wah and Ching (1995b), which is given as ICS Mengzi. I have also consulted Van Norden’s 2008 translation and commentary.

  15. 15.

    I follow James Behuniak (who in turn follows Dobson, Legge, and Chan) in reading xin 心 as “feeling” rather than “mind” or “heart-mind” here since it is clear that that Mencius is referring to specific feelings and not a particular physical faculty or organ. There are, however, passages in which Mencius has in mind a particular faculty and not simply the operations of this faculty, as in Mencius 6A15, discussed below. For a discussion of the problem of translating xin, see Behuniak 2005: 26.

  16. 16.

    Both Lau 1970: 163 and Shun: 214–215 follow this line of reading qing and translate the term as “what is genuine.”

  17. 17.

    Van Norden points out this key distinction between 2A6 and 6A6, and proposes taking si as “reflection” in the following sense: “‘Reflection’” is focusing one’s attention upon and thinking about one’s feelings and the situations that elicit them. It is an activity that involves feelings, thoughts, and perception. (Van Norden 2008: 149).

  18. 18.

    In 7B35 Mencius also emphasizes the importance of reducing desires, which also suggests that what is problematic is not desire per se, but misdirected and immoderate desire.

  19. 19.

    On Mencius’ disputes with the views of other philosophical schools including the Yangists, Mohists, and Legalists, see Graham 1990, Bloom 1994, and Chen 2002.

  20. 20.

    Indeed, a major re-evaluation of early Chinese thought has been underway since the Guodian findings, and scholars like Tang Yijie have suggested that one major impact that the discovery of these texts has had on our understanding of Warring States philosophy is that it makes clear the central role of emotions in early thought. These findings have likewise prompted scholars to speculate that there existed a “Si-Meng” school (Si Meng Xue Pai) of thought that included Mencius, the author of the Guodian texts, and authors of critically significant chapters of the Li Ji, including the Yue Ji and the Zhong Yong. See Li Xueqin 1999: 75–79, Liao Mingchun 1999: 36–74, and Behuniak 2005: xviii-xx. On the Guodian materials and their intellectual content and contexts, see esp. Allan 2000, Ding 2000, GCBM 1999, SGCBM 1999, and PISGCBM.

  21. 21.

    the term xin assumes a more cognitive dimension in this text and its meanings cannot be effectively rendered as “heart,” as in the case of Mencius.

  22. 22.

    Other Guodian texts containing discussions of human nature (xing 性) and feelings (qing 情) are the Cheng zhi wen zhi 成之聞之 and the Yucong 語叢 nos. 1, 2, and 3. See Puett 2004 and Tang 2003.

  23. 23.

    I follow the published version of this text in Jingmen Shi bowuguan 1998. I have been greatly aided in my translation of this and subsequent passages by Michael Puett’s readings in Puett 2004.

  24. 24.

    Johanna Liu theorizes about the larger philosophical meaning of qing in her assertion that, in the Xing Zi Ming Chu, qing is “understood as the beginning of openness to the other in terms of ‘all things’ and ‘yi [propriety]’ as the ending, the final fulfillment towards which human feeling tends.” Liu 2008: 71.

  25. 25.

    As Michael Puett has argued, the ethical significance of qing in this text lies in its invocation as an explanation and justification of cultural institutions. Puett 2004: 43–50.

  26. 26.

    In English the only complete translation of Xunzi’s writings is Knoblock 1988–1994. Notable partial translations include Watson 1963 and Hutton 2001. I have actively consulted and borrowed from Knoblock’s translation in his renderings of certain passages. The passage numbering follows Knoblock and original source citations follow the format in Lau, Wah and Ching (1996), which will be given as ICS Xunzi.

  27. 27.

    Following Knoblock in translating bu mei 不美.

  28. 28.

    A major concern in Puett’s scholarship on qing (as well as on the issue of creation, zuo 作) is the issue of ambivalence, which points to a deeper agenda to justify the creation and use of culture. See Puett 2004. On this see Puett 2001.

  29. 29.

    On Xunzi’s account of self-cultivation as a process of shaping and habituation new dispositions and desires, see Kline 2006.

  30. 30.

    Borrowing Knoblock’s phrasing for fen 分.

  31. 31.

    Compare with similar statements in Guanzi 49, “Neiye,” 16.3a and Zhuangzi 20, 7.9a.

  32. 32.

    This passage has been significantly altered from Knoblock, who reads it as “His eye comes to love the five colors” etc., which is implausible given that Xunzi regards sensual pleasure as part of the inborn nature. It is much more likely that Xunzi is referring here to the new-found appreciation for learning in those who have fulfilled their human potential through self-cultivation. Michael Nylan elaborates at length upon Xunzi’s emphasis on pleasure as an end-product of self-cultivation. She notes how this concern was part of a larger discourse in Warring States/early Han thought in which the most prominent thinkers focused on the achievement of pleasure as “one of the best possible tools of persuasion to induce members of the ruling class to right action” as they conceived of it (Nylan 2001b: 73).

References

  • Allan, Sarah. 1997. The way of water and sprouts of virtue. Albany: State University of New York Press (Analyzes early Chinese philosophy by way of two basic and pervasive metaphors – water and plants).

    Google Scholar 

  • Allan, Sarah, and Crispin, Williams, eds. 2000. The Guodian Laozi: Proceedings of the International Conference, Dartmouth College, May 1998. Berkeley: The Society for the Study of Early China and Institute of East Asian Studies, University of California (Collection of papers and translations from a major conference on the study of the Laozi fragments recovered from the Guodian tomb – a finding that reveals the complex textual history of the received version of the Laozi).

    Google Scholar 

  • Behuniak Jr., James. 2005. Mencius on becoming human. Albany: State University of New York Press (A comprehensive examination of the ethical thought of Mencius, in historical and philosophical context).

    Google Scholar 

  • Bloom, Irene. 1994. Mencian arguments on human nature (Jen-hsing). Philosophy East and West 44: 19–53.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bloom, Irene. 1997. Human nature and biological nature in Mencius. Philosophy East and West 47(1): 21–32.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brindley, Erica. 2006a. Music and ‘Seeking One’s heart-mind’ in the Xing Zi Ming Chu. Dao: A Journal of Comparative Philosophy 5(2): 247–255.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brindley, Erica. 2006b. Music, cosmos, and the development of psychology in early China. T’oung Pao 92(1–3): 1–49.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brindley, Erica. 2009. ‘Why use and ox-cleaver to carve a chicken?’ The sociology of the Junzi ideal. Philosophy East and West 59(1): 47–70.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chan Alan, K.L. (ed.). 2002a. Mencius. Contexts and interpretations. Honolulu: University of Hawaii Press (Valuable collection of diverse, insightful essays on Mencius’ moral thought).

    Google Scholar 

  • Chan Alan, K.L. 2002b. A matter of taste: Qi (Vital Energy) and the tending of the heart (Xin) in Mencius 2A2. In ed Chan (2002a).

    Google Scholar 

  • Chen, Ning. 2002. The ideological background of the Mencian discussion of human nature. A eeexamination. In ed Chan 2002a.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Sousa, Ronald. 1987. The rationality of emotion. Cambridge: The MIT Press (A major study in the philosophy of emotions that argues for the vital role of emotions in structuring perception and representation).

    Google Scholar 

  • Ding, Sixin. 2000. Studies on the thought of the bamboo manuscripts from the Guodian Chu Tombs 郭店楚墓竹简思想研究. Beijing: Dongfang Chuban She.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eifring, Halvor (ed.). 2004. Love and emotions in traditional Chinese literature. Leiden/Boston: Brill (A collection of scholarly articles in English on conceptions of emotions in Chinese thought and literature).

    Google Scholar 

  • Fingarette, Herbert. 1979. The problem of self in the Analects. Philosophy East and West 29(2): 129–140.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fingarette, Herbert. 1998. Confucius. The secular as sacred. Long Grove: Waveland Press (Important interpretation of Confucian ritual inspired by the language philosophy of Ryle and Austin, focusing on its transformative and socializing function).

    Google Scholar 

  • Graham, A.C. 1990. The background of the Mencian theory of human nature. Tsing Hua Journal of Chinese Studies 6 (1967a): 215–71. Reprinted in Idem, Studies in Chinese philosophy and philosophical literature. Albany: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Guodian Chu Bamboo Manuscripts – Special Issue (GCBM) 郭店楚簡專號. 1999. Daojia Wenhua Yanjiu 17.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hansen, Chad. 1995. Qing (Emotions) in Pre-Buddhist Chinese thought. In Emotions in Asian thought. A dialogue in comparative philosophy, ed. Marks Joel and Roger T. Ames. Albany: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harbsmeier, Christoph. 2004. The semantics of Qing in Pre-Buddhist Chinese. In ed Eifring, 69–148.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harper, Donald. 1999. Warring states natural philosophy and occult thought. In The Cambridge history of ancient China: From the origins of Civilization to 221 B.C, ed. Loewe Michael, L. Edward, and Edward L. Shaughnessy. Cambridge/New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutton, Eric L. 2000. Does Xunzi have a consistent theory of human nature? In ed Kline, and Ivanhoe.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutton, Eric L. 2001. Xunzi. In Readings in classical Chinese philosophy, ed. Philip J. Ivanhoe and Bryan W. Van Norden. New York/London: Seven Bridges Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ihara, Craig K. 1991. David Wong on emotions in Mencius. Philosophy East and West 41(1): 45–53.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jingmen Shi bowuguan. 1998. Guodian Chumu Zhujian (GCZ). Beijing: Wenwu Chubanshe.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kline III, T.C. 2006. The therapy of desire in early confucianism: Xunzi. Dao: A Journal of Comparative Philosophy 5(2): 235–246.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kline III, T.C., and P.J. Ivanhoe. 2000. Virtue, nature, and moral agency in the Xunzi. Indianapolis: Hacking Publishing (Important collection of essays on central questions of Xunzi’s moral thought by prominent scholars of early Chinese philosophy).

    Google Scholar 

  • Knoblock, John, 1988–1994. Xunzi. A translation and study of the complete works. Stanford: Stanford University Press (First complete translation of Xunzi’s writings into English, with valuable introductory essays for each chapter).

    Google Scholar 

  • Lau, D.C. 1963. Lao Tzu. Tao De Ching. London/England: Penguin Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lau, D.C. 1970. Mencius. London/England: Penguin Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lau, D.C. 1982. The Analects. Harmondsworth/New York: Penguin Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lau, D.C., He. Che Wah, and Chen Fong Ching (eds.). 1995a. A concordance to the Lunyu 論語逐字索引. Hong Kong: Commercial Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lau, D.C., He. Che Wah, and Chen Fong Ching (eds.). 1995b. A concordance to the Mengzi 孟子逐字索引. Hong Kong: Commercial Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lau, D.C., He. Che Wah, and Chen Fong Ching (eds.). 1996. A concordance to the Xunzi 荀子逐字索引. Hong Kong: Commercial Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis Mark, Edward. 2006. The construction of space in early China. Albany: State University of New York Press (Broad inquiry into early thought and culture from the perspective of how of individual, society, and cosmos are conceived and ordered spatially).

    Google Scholar 

  • Li Xueqin. 1999. Si Si Zi in Jin Men Guodian Chu Bamboo Slips. In Studies on Guodian Chu bamboo slips. Shen Yang: Liao Ling Education Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Liao Mingchun.1999. Jing Men Guodian Chu tomb bamboo slips and pre-Qin confucianism. In: Studies on Guodian Chu bamboo slips. Shen Yang: Liao Ling Education Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Liu, Johanna. 2008. Music [yue] in classical confucianism: On the recently discovered Xing Zi Ming Chu. In Confucian ethics in retrospect and prospect, ed Vincent Shen, and Kwong-loi Shun. The Council for Research in Values and Philosophy.

    Google Scholar 

  • Liu, Qingping. 2011. Emotionales in Confucianism and Daoism: A new interpretation. Journal of Chinese Philosophy 38(1): 118–133.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lloyd, G.E.R. 1996. Adversaries and authorities. Investigations into ancient Greek and Chinese science. Cambridge/New York: Cambridge University Press (Explores major differences in scientific and philosophical approaches in ancient Greek and China, and examines the basis of these differences in their institutional contexts).

    Google Scholar 

  • Mozi 墨子. 2003. Mozi with Annotations 墨子譯注. Xin Zhifeng 辛志風 et al. eds. Ha’erbin: Heilong Jiang ren min chu ban she.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nivison, David. 1980. Mencius and motivation. Journal of the American Academy of Religion 47: 417–432.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, Martha. 2001. Upheavals of thought: The intelligence of emotions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press (A philosophical work on emotions that draws upon personal experience, literature, psychology and music, a leading scholar of the classical tradition argues that emotions are forms of intelligent perception and appraisal).

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nylan, Michael. 2001a. The five “Confucian Classics”. New Haven: Yale University Press. (Illuminating study of the compilation, uses and transmission of the canonical texts of the Confucian tradition; emotions are of particular importance in the chapter on the Odes).

    Google Scholar 

  • Nylan, Michael. 2001b. On the politics of pleasure. Asia Major 14(1): 73–124. 3rd Series.

    Google Scholar 

  • Owen, Stephen. 1985. Traditional Chinese poetry and poetics: Omen of the world. Madison: University of Wisconsin Press (A classic work by one of the foremost Western scholars of Chinese poetry, this book lays out the conceptual foundations of Tang poetry and shows how they differ fundamentally from those of Western poetry).

    Google Scholar 

  • Pines, Yuri. 2002. Foundations of confucian thought: Intellectual life in the Chunqiu period (722–453 B.C.E.). Honolulu: University of Hawaii Press (Broad-ranging study of pre-Confucian intellectual history based on an examination of the Zuo Zhuan; links developments in thought to broader political changes, including the shifting role of literati).

    Google Scholar 

  • Porkert, Manfred. 1974. The theoretical foundations of Chinese medicine: Systems of correspondence. Cambridge: MIT Press (Classic study of the conceptual foundations of Chinese medicine).

    Google Scholar 

  • Puett, Michael. 2001. The ambivalence of creation: Debates concerning innovation and artifice in early China. Stanford: Stanford University Press (Highlights the importance of artifice, building and creation as major preoccupations of early thought, and shows their significance for cultural institutions and empire-building in China).

    Google Scholar 

  • Puett, Michael. 2004. The ethics of responding properly: The notion of Qing in early Chinese. In ed Eifring.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rickett, W. Allyn. 1998. Guanzi. Political, economic, and philosophical essays from early China, A study and translation. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Authoritative translation of a fascinating synthetic text that spans many centuries and brings together a diverse array of philosophical perspectives, as well as topics ranging from mind and body cultivation, Five Phases cosmology, economics, military strategy, and agricultural technology.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shun, Kwong-loi. 1997. Mencius and early Chinese thought. Stanford: Stanford University Press (Most comprehensive philosophical study of Mencius’s thought in English, with analysis of major terms and issues within the context of early moral debates).

    Google Scholar 

  • Shun, Kwong-loi. 2002. Ren and Li in the Analects. In Confucius and the Analects: New essays, ed. Brian W. Van Norden. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sivin, Nathan, and 1. 1995. State, cosmos and body in the last three centuries B.C. Harvard Journal of Asiatic Studies 55: 5–37.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Slingerland, Edward. 2003. Confucius. With selections from traditional commentaries. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company (Philosophically engaged but readable translation of the Analects that incorporates historical commentaries to explicate important or controversial passages).

    Google Scholar 

  • Solomon, Robert C. 2004. Thinking about Feeling: Contemporary philosophers on emotions. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Studies on the Guodian Chu Bamboo Manuscripts (SGCBM) 郭店楚簡研究. 1999. Zhongguo Zhexue 20. Proceedings of the International Symposium on the Guodian Chu Bamboo Manuscripts (PISGCBM). 郭店楚简國際學術硏討會論文集 2000. Wuhan: Hubei ren min chu ban she.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tang, Yijie. 2003. Emotion in pre-Qin Ruist moral theory: An explanation of ‘Dao begins in Qing’. Philosophy East and West 53(2): 271–281.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Norden, Bryan. 2008. Mengzi. With selections from traditional commentaries. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company (A valuable new translation of the Mencius based on the author’s own interpretation of the text, and including the influential commentarial perspective of the twelfth century philosopher and scholar Zhu Xi).

    Google Scholar 

  • Watson, Burton. 1963. Hsün Tzu: Basic writings. New York: Columbia University Press. (A popular and widely used translation of selected chapters from the Xunzi).

    Google Scholar 

  • Wong, Siu-kit. 1978. Ch’ing and Ching in the critical writings of Wang Fu-chih. In Chinese approaches to literature from confucius to Liang Ch’i-ch’ao, ed. Rickett Adele Austin. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wong, David. 1991. Is there a distinction between reason and emotion in Mencius? Philosophy East and West 41(1): 31–44.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wong, David. 2000. Xunzi on moral motivation. In ed Kline III, and Ivanhoe.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Curie Virág Ph.D. .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2014 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Virág, C. (2014). Early Confucian Perspectives on Emotions. In: Shen, V. (eds) Dao Companion to Classical Confucian Philosophy. Dao Companions to Chinese Philosophy, vol 3. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-90-481-2936-2_9

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics