Skip to main content

Futures Assessed: How Technology Assessment, Ethics and Think Tanks Make Sense of an Unknown Future

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Governing Future Technologies

Part of the book series: Sociology of the Sciences Yearbook ((SOSC,volume 27))

Abstract

“Zeitdiagnoses” such as reflexive modernization (Beck et al. 1994) call attention to the fact that our societies monitor their technological future in an ambivalent way: They keep one eye on benefits or innovations, and on risks or dangers the other. But it might be worthwhile taking a closer look at this ambivalence, for it also sets the ground for a division of labour. Despite of the fuzzy and intricate nature of the boundaries that separate those social domains in which the bright side of emerging technologies is up for speculation, from those in which the unintended consequences are subjected to deliberation, the two different social realms can be distinguished along the lines of the societal demands they address.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    The concept of a discourse consisting of articulations that do not only utter “bricks”, but also use bricks to produce a meaningful structure shows many resemblances to concepts employed in Actor Network Theory, particularily to the notion of “association” (cf. Latour 2005).

  2. 2.

    We refer to Aristotle’s famous example in De Interpretatione 9.

  3. 3.

    For Switzerland, cf. Baumgartner et al. 2003; for Germany, cf. Paschen et al. 2003; for Austria, cf. ITA 2006.

  4. 4.

    Interestingly, for uncertainties that underwent no specification, no institution was mentioned to deal with them. Thus, instead of assigning an institution the investigation of the possibility of a “grey goo”, this scenario has been excluded as a mere “distraction from more pressing concerns”.

  5. 5.

    For the specification of a paradigm in terms of a “disciplinary matrix”, see the postscript to the second edition of Kuhn 1970.

  6. 6.

    Since we are not interested in doing ethics, but rather in observing it, the many reasons for or against the distinction between what belongs to the domain of morality and what belongs to the domain of ethics plays a minor role here.

  7. 7.

    Ebbesen, Mette, Svend Andersen, and Flemming Besenbacher. 2006. “Ethics in Nanotechnology: Starting from Scratch?” Bulletin of Science, Technology & Society 26:451–462.

  8. 8.

    Berne, R. W. 2004. “Tiny ethics for big challenges: calling for an ethics of nanoscale science and technology.” Circuits and Devices Magazine, IEEE 20:10.

  9. 9.

    Such symmetry of communication, specific to science, was already noted by Merton 1973 [1942].

  10. 10.

    Besides this essential function, citations serve a wide range of other functions, as highlighted in the field of citation analysis. For the theoretical significance of such analyses in the context of STS, see Leydesdorff 1998.

  11. 11.

    Ebbessen et al. refer to the 5th edition of Beauchamp, T. L., and J. F. Childress. 2001. Principles of biomedical ethics. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. The principles are: respect for autonomy, beneficence, nonmaleficence, and justice.

  12. 12.

    This dependency has remained undetected within the field. Even defenders of principalism have asked themselves what the difference is: “Fundamentals of bioethics or fundamentalism in ethics?” (Quante 2000). At the same time the dispute between “A critique of principlism” (Clouser and Gert 1990) and “Against Relativism” (Macklin 1999) is connected to the irritating question of whether applied ethics allows for a theory of morality or not.

  13. 13.

    Interestingly, Bern strongly refutes such determinism: “In fact, disagreements over which future technologies are myth and which are realistic […] begin with the assumption that technology is a willful, evolving reality rather than a directed, socially constructed one. It assumes that technology evolves separately from human imagination, ambitions, and dreams when in fact technology is by its nature a social construction” (Berne 2004: 12). Although such a deterministic attitude is negated on a theoretical level, on a practical level, however, Bern has nothing to propose by way of a different way of thinking.

  14. 14.

    This finding however does not mean that ethicists do not seek to influence the ongoing debate about possible consequences of nanotechnology – on the contrary.

  15. 15.

    An overview as well as an evaluation of pTA projects in different European countries is provided by Joss and Bellucci 2002. For the US context, see Guston 1999. An anthology which discusses such a “democratization of expertise” critically was edited by Maasen and Weingart 2005.

References

  • Arnall, A. H. (2003), Future Technologies, Today’s Choices – Nanotechnology, Artificial Intelligence and Robotics; A Technical, Political and Institutional Map of Emerging Technologies, London: Greenpeace Environmental Trust.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barber, B. R. (1984), Strong Democracy. Participatory Politics for a New Age. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baumgartner, W., B. Jäckli, B. Schmithüsen and F. Weber (2003), Nanotechnologie in der Medizin, Bern: Zentrum für Technologiefolgen-Abschätzung beim Schweizerischen Wissenschafts- und Technologierat.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bechmann, G. (2007), ‘Die Beschreibung der Zukunft als Chance oder als Risiko? TA zwischen Innovation und Prävention’, Technikfolgenabschätzung – Theorie und Praxis 16: 34–44.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beck, U., A. Giddens and S. Lash (1994), Reflexive Modernization: Politics, Tradition and Aesthetics in the Modern Social Order. Standford, CA: Standford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berne, R. W. (2004), ‘Tiny Ethics for Big Challenges: Calling for an Ethics of Nanoscale Science and Technology’, Circuits and Devices Magazine, IEEE 20(3): 10.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clouser, K. D. and B. Gert (1990), ‘A Critique of Principlism’, The Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 15(2): 219–236.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, J. (1989), ‘Deliberative Democracy and Democratic Legitimacy’, in A. Hamlin, P. Pettit (eds.) The Good Polity, Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Daston, L. (1992), ‘Objectivity and the Escape from Perspective’, Social Studies of Science 22(4): 597–618.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • David, V.K., and P.B. Thompson (eds.) (2008), What Can Nanotechnology Learn from Biotechnology, Oxford: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Decker, M. (2006), ‘Eine Definition der Nanotechnologie: Erster Schritt für ein interdisziplinäres Nanotechnology Assessment’, in A. Nordmann, J. Schummer, A. Schwarz (eds.), Nanotechnologien im Kontext, Berlin: Akademische Verlagsgesellschaft.

    Google Scholar 

  • Derrida, J. (1988), Limited Inc, Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dryzek, J. (1990), Discursive Democracy: Politics, Policy, and Political Science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ebbesen, M., S. Andersen and F. Besenbacher. (2006), ‘Ethics in Nanotechnology: Starting from Scratch?’, Bulletin of Science, Technology & Society 26: 451–462.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Elster, J. (ed.) (1998), Deliberative Democracy, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fleck, L. (1980 [1935]), Entstehung und Entwicklung einer wissenschaftlichen Tatsache. Einführung in die Lehre vom Denkstil und Denkkollektiv, Frankfurt a. M.: Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Guston, D. H. (1999), ‘Evaluating the First US Consensus Conference: The Impact of the Citizens’ Panel on Telecommunications and the Future of Democracy’, Science, Technology, & Human Values 24(4): 451–482.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ITA (2006), Nanotechnologiebegleitmassnahmen: Stand und Implikationen für Österreich, Wien: Institut für Technikfolgen-Abschätzung der Österreichen Akademie der Wissenschaften.

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, M. (1994), Moral Imagination; Implications of Cognitive Science for Ethics, Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Joss, S. and S. Bellucci (eds.) (2002), Participatory Technology Assessment – European Perspectives, London: Athenaeum Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kearnes, M., P. Macnaghten and J. Wilsdon (2006), Governing at the Nanoscale. People, Policies and Emerging Technologies, London: Demos.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, T. (1970), The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laclau, E. and C. Mouffe (1985), Hegemony and Socialist Strategy: Towards a Radical Democratic Politics, London: Verso.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lane, R. E. (1966), ‘The Decline of Politics and Ideology in a Knowledgeable Society’, American Sociological Review 31: 649–662.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Latour, B. (2005), Reassembling the Social: An Introduction to Actor-Network-Theory, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leydesdorff, L. (1998), ‘Theories of Citation?’, Scientometrics 43: 5–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maasen, S. and Peter Weingart (eds.) (2005), Democratization of Expertise? Exploring Novel Forms of Scientific Advice in Political Decision-Making, Dordrecht, NL: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Macklin, R. (1999), Against Relativism: Cultural Diversity and the Search for Ethical Universals in Medicine, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merton, R. K. (1973 [1942]), ‘The Normative Structure of Science’ (orig. ‘A Note on Science and Democracy’, Journal of Legal and Political Sociology 1: 115–126). in Merton, R. K. (ed.), The Sociology of Science: Theoretical and Empirical Investigations, Chicago: University of Chicago Press: 115–126,

    Google Scholar 

  • Munich Re (2002), Nanotechnologie – Was kommt auf uns zu?, München: Münchener Rückversicherungs-Gesellschaft.

    Google Scholar 

  • N.N. (2003), ‘Fear of the unknown: Nanotechnology’, Materials Today 6(9): 14.

    Google Scholar 

  • Paschen, H., C. Coenen, T. Fleischer, R. Grünwald, D. Oertel and C. Revermann (2003), Nanotechnologie, Berlin: Büro für Technikfolgen-Abschätzung beim Deutschen Bundestag (TAB) / The Office of Technology Assessment at the German Bundestag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quante, M. (2000), ‘Fundamentals of Bioethics or Fundamentalism in Ethics?’, Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy V3(2):203.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Radford, T. (2003), ‘Brave New World or Miniature Menace? Why Charles Fears Grey Goo Nightmare’, in The Guardian (April 29): 3.

    Google Scholar 

  • Royal Society and Royal Academy of Engineering (2004), Nanoscience and Nanotechnlogies: Opportunities and Uncertainties, London: Royal Society & Royal Academy of Engineering.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. R. (1969), Speech acts. An Essay in the Philosophy of Language, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. R. (1979), ‘What is an Intentional State?’, Mind (New Series) 88(349): 74–92.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stichweh, R. (1984), Zur Entstehung des modernen Systems wissenschaftlicher Disziplinen. Physik in Deutschland 1740–1890, Frankfurt a. M.: Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Swiss Re (2004), ‘Nanotechnology. Small Matter, Many Unknows’, in Risk perception, Zurich: Swiss Reinsurance Company (SwissRe).

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (2001), Philosophical Investigations, Oxford: Blackwell Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Mario Kaiser .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2009 Springer Science+Business Media B.V.

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Kaiser, M. (2009). Futures Assessed: How Technology Assessment, Ethics and Think Tanks Make Sense of an Unknown Future. In: Kaiser, M., Kurath, M., Maasen, S., Rehmann-Sutter, C. (eds) Governing Future Technologies. Sociology of the Sciences Yearbook, vol 27. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-90-481-2834-1_10

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics