Skip to main content

Should Parents Take Active Steps to Preserve Their Children’s Fertility?

  • Chapter
  • First Online:

Part of the book series: International Library of Ethics, Law, and the New Medicine ((LIME,volume 69))

Abstract

It has been argued that, when there is a probable imminent risk of loss of children’s fertility, their parents should take active steps to preserve their reproductive potential if possible – or even that children have a right to such interventions being undertaken on them on their behalf, as an expression of their right to an open future. In this chapter, I explore these proposals and some of their implications. I place the discussion of fertility preservation for children into the more general context of the choices that parents might have to help keep their children’s future reproductive (and parenting) choices open. I discuss the role of desert and fairness in arguments for fertility preservation and their relevance for framings of infertility in general, as well as the relation between having a (slight) possibility to reproduce and becoming a parent.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   79.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   99.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    There may be disagreement on whether this condition really lies at the core of the legitimacy of parental decision making. For the purposes of this chapter, I will assume that it does.

  2. 2.

    I am grateful to Guido Pennings for raising this point during the Q&A following my talk on this topic at the Maastricht symposium “Parental responsibility in the context of neuroscience and genetics”.

  3. 3.

    I thank my co-editor Kristien Hens for inspiring these concerns.

  4. 4.

    As my co-editor Dorothee Horstkötter pointed out, such a proposal “might also be tricky, because one could turn the argument around and say that ‘foreseeing and treating reproductive desires’ should entail a clear discouragement from engaging in a same-sex relationship, or – for women - in higher education and employment as that facilitates postponement.” This may be true, but by doing so they would restrict their children’s futures in other, more predictably harmful ways – and thus fail more, and more actively, at safeguarding their children’s interests than they would by not taking fertility preservation measures on their behalf.

References

  • BBC News, Ovarian transplant first welcomed. August 2, 2007. Available at news.bbc.co.uk/2/hi/health/6924014.stm. Accessed September 2016.

  • BBC News, Tech giants to freeze eggs for their female employees. October 15, 2014. Available at www.bbc.com/news/business-29626291. Accessed September 2016.

  • Biblarz, T., and J. Stacey. 2010. How does the gender of parents matter? Journal of Marriage and Family 72(1): 3–22.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bizet, P., et al. 2012. Sperm cryopreservation before cancer treatment: A 15-year monocentric experience. Reproductive Biomedicine Online 24(3): 321–330.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bornstein, M.H. (ed.). 2002. Handbook of parenting: Vol. 1: Children and parenting. Mahwah: Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bourke, E., et al. 2014. A qualitative exploration of mothers’ and fathers’ experiences of having a child with Klinefelter syndrome and the process of reaching this diagnosis. European Journal of Human Genetics 22(18): 18–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chuva de Sousa Lopes, S.M., and B.A.J. Roelen. 2015. Current status of in vitro differentiation of stem cells into gametes. Animal Reproduction 12(1): 46–51.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cutas, D., and K. Hens. 2015. Preserving children’s fertility: Two tales about children’s right to an open future and the margins of parental obligations. Medicine, Healthcare and Philosophy 18(2): 253–260.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davis, D.S. 1997. Genetic dilemmas and the child’s right to an open future. Hastings Center Report 27(2): 7–15.

    Google Scholar 

  • Demeestere, I., et al. 2015. Live birth after autograft of ovarian tissue cryopreserved during childhood. Human Reproduction 30(9): 2107–2109.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dittrich, R., et al. 2012. Live birth after ovarian tissue autotransplantation following overnight transportation before cryopreservation. Fertility and Sterility 97(2): 387–390.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dolin, G., D.E. Roberts, L.M. Rodriguez, and T.K. Woodruff. 2010. Medical hope, legal pitfalls: Potential legal issues in the emerging field of oncofertility. Oncofertility. Cancer Treatment and Research 156: 111–134.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • European Commission, Directorate-General for Employment, Social Affairs and Inclusion & Eurostat 2011. Demography report. (2010), Commission Staff Working Paper. Available at http://epp.eurostat.ec.europa.eu.

  • Eurostat. 2014. Unemployment statistics. Available at http://ec.europa.eu/eurostat/statistics-explained/index.php/Unemployment_statistics. Accessed September 2016.

  • Fallat, M.E., and J. Hutter. 2008. Preservation of fertility in pediatric and adolescent patients with cancer. Pediatrics 121(5): e1461–e1469.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feinberg, J. 1980. The child’s right to an open future. In Whose child? Children’s rights, parental authority, and state power, ed. W. Aiken and H. LaFollette. Totowa: Rowman and Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feinberg, J. 1992. Freedom and fulfilment: Philosophical essays. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fujita, K., et al. 2005. Transplantation of spermatogonial stem cells isolated from leukemic mice restores fertility without inducing leukemia. The Journal of Clinical Investigation 115(7): 1855–1861.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gies, I., et al. 2012. Spermatogonial stem cell preservation in boys with Klinefelter syndrome: To bank or not to bank, that’s the question. Fertility and Sterility 98(2): 284–289.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Golombok, S. 1998. New families, old values: Considerations regarding the welfare of the child. Human Reproduction 13: 2342–2347.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Golombok, S. 2000. Parenting: What really counts? London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Golombok, S. 2015. Modern families. Parents and children in new family forms. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Golombok, S., et al. 1995. Families created by the new reproductive technologies: Quality of parenting and social and emotional development of the children. Child Development 66: 285–298.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grundy, R., et al. 2001a. Fertility preservation for children treated for cancer (1): Scientific advances and research dilemmas. Archives of Disease in Childhood 84(4): 355–359.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grundy, R., et al. 2001b. Fertility preservation for children treated for cancer (2): Ethics of consent for gamete storage and experimentation. Archives of Disease in Childhood 84(4): 360–362.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hastings, P., et al. 2006. Children’s development of social competence across family types. At www.samesexmarriage.ca/docs/Justice_Child_Development.pdf. Accessed September 2016.

  • Hayashi, K., et al. 2011. Reconstitution of the mouse germ cell specification pathway in culture by pluripotent stem cells. Cell 146(4): 519–532.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hayashi, K., et al. 2012. Offspring from oocytes derived from in vitro primordial germ cell-like cells in mice. Science 338(6109): 971–975.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hens, K. 2017. The ethics of postponed fatherhood. International Journal of Feminist Approaches to Bioethics 10(1): 1.

    Google Scholar 

  • Herlihy, A.S., et al. 2011. Postnatal screening for Klinefelter syndrome: Is there a rationale? Acta Paediatrica 100(6): 923–933.

    Google Scholar 

  • Imbert, R., et al. 2014. Safety and usefulness of cryopreservation of ovarian tissue to preserve fertility: A 12-year retrospective analysis. Human Reproduction 29(9): 1931–1940.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jadoul, P., et al. 2010. Fertility preservation in girls during childhood: Is it feasible, efficient and safe and to whom should it be proposed? Human Reproduction Update 16(6): 617–630.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jahnukainen, K., et al. 2006. Clinical potential and putative risks of fertility preservation in children utilizing gonadal tissue or germline stem cells. Pediatric Research 59(4 Pt 2): 40R–47R.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kelleher, S., et al. 2001. Long-term outcomes of elective human sperm cryostorage. Human Reproduction 16(12): 2632–2639.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lamb, M. 2012. Mothers, fathers, families, and circumstances: Factors affecting children’s adjustment. Applied Developmental Science 16(2): 98–111.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lampic, C., A.S. Svanberg, P. Karlström, and T. Tyden. 2006. Fertility awareness, intentions concerning childbearing, and attitudes towards parenthood among female and male academics. Human Reproduction 21(2): 558–564.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Larcher, V. 2012. The ethical obligation to preserve fertility in the face of all therapies that might adversely affect it. Archives of Disease in Childhood 97(9): 767–768.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Layman, L.C. 2003. Genetic causes of human infertility. Endocrinology and Metabolism Clinics of North America 32(3): 549–572.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Legge 40, 19 February 2004, available at www.camera.it/parlam/leggi/04040l.htm.

  • Magelssen, H., et al. 2005. Twenty years experience with semen cryopreservation in testicular cancer patients: Who needs it? European Urology 48(5): 779–785.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mehta, A., and D.A. Paduch. 2012. Klinefelter syndrome: An argument for early aggressive hormonal and fertility management. Fertility and Sterility 98(2): 274–283.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nisker, J., F. Baylis, and C. McLeod. 2006. Choice in fertility preservation in girls and adolescent women with cancer. Cancer 107(7): 1606–1689.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pennings, G. 1999. Measuring the welfare of the child: In search of the appropriate evaluation principle. Human Reproduction 14(5): 1146–1150.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Poirot, C., and B. Schubert. 2011. Fertility preservation in prepubertal children. Bulletin du Cancer 98(5): 489–499.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quinn, G.P., et al. 2012. Preserving the right to future children: An ethical case analysis. The American Journal of Bioethics 12(6): 38–43.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rieker, P.P., et al. 1990. Adaptive behavioral responses to potential infertility among survivors of testis cancer. Journal of Clinical Oncology 8(2): 347–355.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rochman, B. 2011. Even as babies, cancer patients strive to preserve fertility. http://healthland.time.com/2011/03/22/children-having-children-when-a-kids-got-cancer-fertility-preservation-can-help/. Last Accessed September 2016.

  • Saito, K., et al. 2005. Sperm cryopreservation before cancer chemotherapy helps in the emotional battle against cancer. Cancer 104(3): 521–524.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Satkoske, V.B., and L.S. Parker. 2013. Preserving testicular tissue and a boy’s open reproductive future. The American Journal of Bioethics 13(3): 36–37.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scheib, J., and P. Hastings. 2012. Donor-conceived children raised by lesbian couples: Socialization and development in a new form of planned family. In Families – Beyond the nuclear ideal, ed. D. Cutas and S. Chan. London: Bloomsbury Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schmidt, L. 2010. Should men and women be encouraged to start childbearing at a younger age? Expert Reviews in Obstetrics Gynaecology 5(2): 145–147.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schover, L.R. 2005. Motivation for parenthood after cancer: A review. Journal of the National Cancer Institute Monographs 34: 2–5.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Simon, B., et al. 2005. Preserving fertility after cancer. CA: A Cancer Journal for Clinicians 55(4): 211–228.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smajdor, A. 2007. There’s no such thing as a free egg. BioNews. Available at www.bionews.org.uk/page_37947.asp. Accessed September 2016.

  • Smajdor, A., and D. Cutas. 2015. Will artificial gametes end infertility? Health Care Analysis 23: 134–147.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thomson, A.B., et al. 2002. Semen quality and spermatozoal DNA integrity in survivors of childhood cancer: A case–control study. Lancet 360(9330): 361–367.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Casteren, N.J., et al. 2008. Use rate and assisted reproduction technologies outcome of cryopreserved semen from 629 cancer patients. Fertility and Sterility 90(6): 2245–2250.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Daniela Cutas .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Cutas, D. (2017). Should Parents Take Active Steps to Preserve Their Children’s Fertility?. In: Hens, K., Cutas, D., Horstkötter, D. (eds) Parental Responsibility in the Context of Neuroscience and Genetics. International Library of Ethics, Law, and the New Medicine, vol 69. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-42834-5_12

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics