Skip to main content

Arguments, Conflicts, and Decisions

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
  • 1634 Accesses

Part of the book series: Computational Social Sciences ((CSS))

Abstract

The relationship between conflict and argumentation presents an interesting ambivalence, both in ordinary language and in theoretical models: although argumentation is often depicted as a discursive practice aimed at reasonable resolution of an initial conflict, arguments are also frequently perceived as inherently conflictual engagements, more akin to vicious fights than to rational discussion. In this paper, I argue that a decision-theoretic approach to argumentation allows to make sense of this tension, and I review some empirical evidence in favor of this claim. In turn, this highlights the complex role that conflict plays in orienting our argumentative moves. I conclude by offering some implications, both theoretical and practical, of this particular view of arguments, conflicts, and decisions.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    But not always, e.g., in instances of what Walton (1998) labels eristic confrontation, where the dialogical goal is to vent one’s feelings at the opponent, not to solve any underlying conflict of opinion—on the contrary, often with the reasonable expectation of exacerbating it.

  2. 2.

    Costs and benefits are crucial also in relevance theory (Sperber and Wilson 1986; Wilson and Sperber 2002), but with several important differences with respect to the decision-theoretic approach outlined here (for discussion of this point, see Paglieri 2013b).

  3. 3.

    The studies presented in this section refer to persuasion dialogues (Walton 1998), in which each party tries to prove a point that the other party is resistant to accept. Such focus on persuasion will result in frequent reference to the notion of “winning the argument” as a criterion for success. This does not imply that winning is invariably the purpose of arguing in general: as it is often emphasized in the literature (Walton and Krabbe 1995; Walton 1998; Paglieri and Castelfranchi 2010), arguing can be motivated also by other goals, personal or dialogical. Nonetheless, arguers are still concerned with success, defined in terms of whatever goal they are striving to achieve.

  4. 4.

    Both studies are published (Study 1: Hample et al. 2011; Study 2: Cionea et al. 2011), and readers are referred to those articles for further methodological elucidation.

  5. 5.

    The reason why the argument happens to be prolonged will also affect the arguer’s choice: that is, argument quality and argument duration are not entirely independent from each other. Consider for instance counter argumentation, that is, arguments from the other party aimed at undermining or undercutting one’s own arguments (see Pollock 1992; Prakken 2000; Besnard and Hunter 2001). Given extant evidence on how preexposure to counterarguments affects resistance to persuasion (e.g., Petty and Cacioppo 1977), the amount of counter argumentation experienced so far is likely to matter for deciding whether and how to terminate the exchange.

  6. 6.

    In group discussion, this interacts also with polarization, as an effect of being exposed to novel arguments (from other like-minded arguers) in favor of one’s previous position: as it has been repeatedly shown in social psychology (for a review and discussion, see Myers and Lamm 1976; Isenberg 1986; Sunstein 2002), this leads groups of like-minded people to develop positions far more extreme than those previously held by their individual members. The interplay of radicalization and polarization explains why multiparty argumentation, e.g., debates on social media, easily produces partisanship, that is, the predominance of relatively few views, each quite extreme and fanatically opposed to any dissenting voice.

  7. 7.

    Incidentally, the findings reviewed in Sect. 7.3.1 provide preliminary support to lexicographic decision making in argument engagement, since arguers consider only a very limited and rigidly prioritized subset of considerations in deciding whether to enter an argument or not.

References

  • Amgoud L, Maudet N (2002) Strategical considerations for argumentative agents. In: Benferhat S, Giunchiglia E (eds) Proceedings of NMR-2002. IRIT, Toulouse, pp 399–407

    Google Scholar 

  • Bem SL (1974) The measurement of psychological androgyny. J Consult Clin Psychol 42:155–162

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Benoit W, Benoit P (1987) Everyday argument practices of naïve social actors. In: Wenzel J (ed) Argument and critical practices. Speech Communication Association, Annandale, pp 465–474

    Google Scholar 

  • Benoit P, Benoit W (1990) To argue or not to argue: how real people get in and out of interpersonal arguments. In: Trapp R, Schuetz J (eds) Perspectives on argumentation: essays in honor of Wayne Brockriede. Waveland, Prospect Heights, pp 55–72

    Google Scholar 

  • Besnard P, Hunter A (2001) A logic-based theory of deductive arguments. Artif Intell 128:203–235

    Article  MATH  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Burnstein A, Vinokur A, Trope Y (1973) Interpersonal comparison versus persuasive argumentation: a more direct test of alternative explanations for group induced shifts in individual choice. J Exp Soc Psychol 9:236–245

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cionea I, Hample D, Paglieri F (2011) A test of the argument engagement model in Romania. In: Zenker F (ed) Argumentation: cognition & community. Proceedings of OSSA 2011. CD-ROM. OSSA, Windsor

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen D (2005) Arguments that backfire. In: Hitchcock D (ed) the uses of argument. Proceedings of OSSA 2005. OSSA, Hamilton, pp 58–65

    Google Scholar 

  • Crawford V (1982) A theory of disagreement in bargaining. Econometrica 50(3):607–638

    Article  MATH  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Esser J (1998) Alive and well after 25 years: a review of groupthink research. Organ Behav Hum Decis Process 73(2–3):116–141

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gigerenzer G, Goldstein D (1996) Reasoning the fast and frugal way: models of bounded rationality. Psychol Rev 103:650–669

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert M (1997) Coalescent argumentation. Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, Mahwah

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodwin J (2005) What does arguing look like? Informal Logic 25:79–93

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodwin J (2007) Argument has no function. Informal Logic 27:69–90

    Google Scholar 

  • Hample D (2005) Arguing: exchanging reasons face to face. Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, Mahwah

    Google Scholar 

  • Hample D (2006) Argument production. In: van Eemeren FH, Hazen MD, Houtlosser P, Williams DC (eds) Contemporary perspectives on argumentation: views from the Venice argumentation conference. Sic Sat, Amsterdam, pp 9–22

    Google Scholar 

  • Hample D (2009) Commentary on Fabio Paglieri’s “Ruinous arguments: escalation of disagreement and the dangers of arguing”. In: Ritola J (ed) Argument cultures: proceedings of OSSA 2009. CD-ROM. OSSA, Windsor, pp 1–4

    Google Scholar 

  • Hample D, Benoit P (1999) Must arguments be explicit and violent? A study of naive social actors’ understandings. In: van Eemeren F, Grootendorst R, Blair JA, Willard C (eds) Proceedings of ISSA 1998. SicSat, Amsterdam, pp 306–310

    Google Scholar 

  • Hample D, Dallinger J (1990) Arguers as editors. Argumentation 4:153–169

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hample D, Dallinger J (1992) The use of multiple goals in cognitive editing of arguments. Argumentation Advocacy 28:109–122

    Google Scholar 

  • Hample D, Benoit P, Houston J, Purifoy G, Vanhyfte V, Wardwell C (1999) Naive theories of argument: avoiding interpersonal arguments or cutting them short. Argumentation Advocacy 35:130–139

    Google Scholar 

  • Hample D, Werber B, Young D (2009) Framing and editing interpersonal arguments. Argumentation 23:21–37

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hample D, Paglieri F, Na L (2011) The costs and benefits of arguing: predicting the decision whether to engage or not. In: van Eemeren F, Garssen B, Godden D, Mitchell G (eds) Proceedings of ISSA 2010. Sic Sat, Amsterdam, pp 718–732

    Google Scholar 

  • Hicks D (1991) A descriptive account of interpersonal argument. In: Parson DW (ed) Argument in controversy. Speech Communication Association, Annandale, pp 167–181

    Google Scholar 

  • Infante D, Rancer A (1982) A conceptualization and measure of argumentativeness. J Pers Assess 46:72–80

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Infante D, Wigley C (1986) Verbal aggressiveness: an interpersonal model and measure. Commun Monogr 53:61–69

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Isenberg DJ (1986) Group polarization: a critical review and meta-analysis. J Pers Soc Psychol 50(6):1141–1151

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Janis I (1982) Groupthink: psychological studies of policy decisions and fiascoes. Houghton Mifflin, Boston

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnson R (2000) Manifest rationality: a pragmatic theory of argument. Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, Mahwah

    Google Scholar 

  • Karunatillake N, Jennings N (2005) Is it worth arguing? In: Rahwan I, Moratïs P, Reed C (eds) Argumentation in multi-agent systems. Proceedings of ArgMAS’04. Springer, Berlin, pp 234–250

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Martin RW, Scheerhorn DR (1985) What are conversational arguments? Toward a natural language user’s perspective. In: Cox JR, Sillars MO, Walker GB (eds) Argument and social practice. Speech Communication Association, Annandale, pp 705–722

    Google Scholar 

  • Myers DG, Lamm H (1976) The group polarization phenomenon. Psychol Bull 83:602–627

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Paglieri F (2007) No more charity, please! Enthymematic parsimony and the pitfall of benevolence. In: Hansen H, Tindale C, Johnson R, Blair JA (eds) Dissensus and the search for common ground. OSSA, Windsor, pp 1–26, CD-ROM

    Google Scholar 

  • Paglieri F (2009) Ruinous arguments: escalation of disagreement and the dangers of arguing. In: Ritola J (ed) Argument cultures: proceedings of OSSA 2009. OSSA, Windsor, pp 1–15, CD-ROM

    Google Scholar 

  • Paglieri F (2013a) Choosing to argue: towards a theory of argumentative decisions. J Pragmat 59B:153–163

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Paglieri F (2013b) Argumentation, decision and rationality. In: Mohammed D, Lewinski M (eds) Virtues of argumentation: proceedings of OSSA 2013. OSSA, Windsor, pp 1–13, CD-ROM

    Google Scholar 

  • Paglieri F (2013c) Agreements as the grease (not the glue) of society: a cognitive and social science perspective. In: Ossowski S (ed) Agreement technologies. Springer, Berlin, pp 43–52

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Paglieri F, Castelfranchi C (2010) Why argue? Towards a cost-benefit analysis of argumentation. Argument Comput 1:71–91

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Paglieri F, Woods J (2011a) Enthymematic parsimony. Synthese 178:461–501

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Paglieri F, Woods J (2011b) Enthymemes: from reconstruction to understanding. Argumentation 25(2):127–139

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Petty R, Cacioppo J (1977) Forewarning, cognitive responding, and resistance to persuasion. J Pers Soc Psychol 35(9):645–655

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Petty R, Cacioppo J (1986) Communication and persuasion: central and peripheral routes to attitude change. Springer, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pollock J (1992) How to reason defeasibly. Artif Intell 57:1–42

    Article  MATH  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Prakken H (2000) On dialogue systems with speech acts, arguments, and counterarguments. In: Ojeda-Aciego M, de Guzan IP, Brewka G, Moniz Pereira L (eds) Logics in artificial intelligence: proceedings of JELIA 2000. Springer, Berlin, pp 224–238

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Prunty A, Klopf D, Ishii S (1991) Argumentativeness: Japanese and American tendencies to approach and avoid conflict. Commun Res Rep 7:75–79

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rahwan I, Larson K (2009) Argumentation and game theory. In: Rahwan I, Simari G (eds) Argumentation in artificial intelligence. Springer, Berlin, pp 321–339

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Riveret R, Prakken H, Rotolo A, Sartor G (2008) Heuristics in argumentation: a game-theoretical investigation. In: Besnard P, Doutre S, Hunter A (eds) Proceedings of COMMA 2008. Ios Press, Amsterdam, pp 324–335

    Google Scholar 

  • Schoemaker P (1982) The expected utility model: its variants, purposes, evidence and limitations. J Econ Lit 20(2):529–563

    Google Scholar 

  • Secchi D (2011) Extendable rationality: understanding decision making in organizations. Springer, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sperber D, Wilson D (1986) Relevance: communication and cognition. Blackwell, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Sunstein CR (2002) The law of group polarization. J Polit Philos 10(2):175–195

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Surowiecki J (2004) The wisdom of crowds: why the many are smarter than the few and how collective wisdom shapes business, economies, societies and nations. Little/Brown, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Svejnar J (1986) Bargaining power, fear of disagreement, and wage settlements: theory and evidence from the U.S. Industry. Econometrica 54(5):1055–1078

    Article  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren F, Grootendorst R (2004) A systematic theory of argumentation: the Pragma-dialectical approach. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Vuchinich S (1990) The sequential organization of closing in verbal family conflict. In: Grimshaw AD (ed) Conflict talk. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 118–138

    Google Scholar 

  • Walton D (1998) The new dialectic: conversational contexts of argument. University of Toronto Press, Toronto

    Google Scholar 

  • Walton D, Krabbe E (1995) Commitment in dialogue: basic concepts of interpersonal reasoning. SUNY Press, Albany

    Google Scholar 

  • Walton D, Reed C, Macagno F (2008) Argument schemes. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson D, Sperber D (2002) Truthfulness and relevance. Mind 111:583–632

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

This research was supported by the project PRISMA—PiattafoRme cloud Interoperabili per SMArt-government, funded by the Italian Ministry of Education, University and Research (MIUR) and by the research network SINTELNET—European Network for Social Intelligence, funded by the European Union. I am indebted to Cristiano Castelfranchi, Jean Goodwin, Dale Hample, Marcin Lewinski, Steve Patterson, and Frank Zenker for their helpful comments on some of the ideas detailed in this paper and to the organizers and participants of the events where this work was presented and discussed: the OSSA conference on “Virtues of argumentation” (Windsor, May 23–25, 2013), the workshop on “Computational models of natural argument” (Rome, June 14, 2013), the conference on “Conflict and communication” (Rome, October 29–31, 2013), and the ArgLab workshop on “Argumentation and rational decisions” (Lisbon, December 5, 2013). While I greatly benefited from debating my ideas with other argumentation scholars, I take full responsibility for any lingering defect of this work.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Fabio Paglieri .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2015 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Paglieri, F. (2015). Arguments, Conflicts, and Decisions. In: D'Errico, F., Poggi, I., Vinciarelli, A., Vincze, L. (eds) Conflict and Multimodal Communication. Computational Social Sciences. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-14081-0_7

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-14081-0_7

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-319-14080-3

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-319-14081-0

  • eBook Packages: Computer ScienceComputer Science (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics