Skip to main content

Merleau-Ponty and the Transcendental Problem of Bodily Agency

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Book cover The Phenomenology of Embodied Subjectivity

Part of the book series: Contributions to Phenomenology ((CTPH,volume 71))

  • 2192 Accesses

Abstract

I argue that we find the articulation of a problem concerning bodily agency in the early works of the Merleau-Ponty which he explicates as analogous to what he explicitly calls the problem of perception. The problem of perception is the problem of seeing how we can have the object given in person through it perspectival appearances. The problem concerning bodily agency is the problem of seeing how our bodily movements can be the direct manifestation of a person’s intentions in the world. In both cases what, according to Merleau-Ponty, obscures a recognition of the phenomenon in question is a conception of our bodily capacities, i.e. our sensibility and our motility, which reduces these to the workings of mechanisms that are blind to meaning. I argue that both the problem concerning perception and the problem concerning bodily agency can be properly called transcendental. The problem of perception is transcendental because it concerns the very intelligibility of appearances and judgements with empirical content. The problem of bodily agency is transcendental in the sense that it concerns the very intelligibility of our bodily capacity to carry out intentions and by implication the intelligibility of our intentions as such.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    I use “SC” to refer to Merleau-Ponty’s La structure du comportement/The Structure of Behavior (1942). I refer first to the pagination of the English translation of SC (1983) and then to the page numbers in the French edition (1990). I shall use “PP” to refer to phénoménologie de la perception/Phenomenology of Perception (1945) and refer to the page numbers of Donald. A. Landes’ recent translation, which contains indication of the corresponding pages in the French edition.

  2. 2.

    Some more recent philosophers of action who explicitly take such an analogical approach to action are: Danto (1973), Hornsby (1980), Searle (1983), Hurley (1998), Enç (2003) and Dokic (2003).

  3. 3.

    It is controversial whether we should read Merleau-Ponty as committed to a relational account of perception. I have argued that he is committed to such in an account in Jensen (2013); Romdenh-Romluc presents a different line of argument, with the same conclusion (Romdenh-Romluc 2011, pp. 159–167).

  4. 4.

    At times Merleau-Ponty seems to use Husserl’s expression the natural attitude as synonymous with Objective Thought and contrasts it with the transcendental attitude (PP, p. 41, p. 510, n. 60). Qua natural attitude the assumption of scientific naturalism doesn’t seem to be a necessary feature of Objective Thought, but given the historical development of modern science, such naturalism has, on Merleau-Ponty’s reading, become an almost inescapable conception of the natural world.

  5. 5.

    Merleau-Ponty mentions different conceptions of causality: as transmission of movement or energy and a functional conception which doesn’t constrain the possible variables of the function to for instance spatio-temporal, physical events (PP, p. 75). Merleau-Ponty sometimes indicates that he takes modern physics to have undermined “Causal Thought” from within: He refers to Goldstein’s analogy between a proper understanding of organisms and the break with the classical notion of causality which Goldstein finds in quantum mechanics (SC 1983, p. 154/1990, p. 167; 1983, p. 193/1990, p. 208). Most likely it is also quantum mechanics Merleau-Ponty has in mind when he states that even physics itself recognizes the limits of its determinations and demands a reworking and a contamination of its own pure concepts (PP, p. 57).

  6. 6.

    Kant writes: “Now we find that our thought of the relation of all knowledge to its object carries with it an element of necessity; the object is viewed as that which prevents our modes of knowledge from being haphazard or arbitrary, and which determines them a priori in some definite fashion. For in so far as they are to relate to an object, they must necessarily agree with one another, that is, must possess that unity which constitutes the concept of an object” (Kant 2007, A104–105).

  7. 7.

    Quine claims to go beyond the discussion on whether sense-data or Gestalt has epistemic priority by replacing the concept of sense-data with the concept of observational sentences, i.e. sentences with a constant causal connection between stimuli and judgments manifest in behaviour (Quine 1969, p. 76). Merleau-Ponty’s arguments against the possibility of a finding a lawful connection between intentional or content-involving understandings of behaviour and stimuli describable in non-intentional terms delivered in The Structure of Behavior, seem, if successful, also to rule out Quine’s proposal.

  8. 8.

    See Jensen (2013) for a comparative analysis of Merleau-Ponty and McDowell’s versions of the negative transcendental argument.

  9. 9.

    In his discussion of the Schneider case and related neuro-pathological cases Merleau-Ponty distinguished between empiricist and intellectualist psychology, where the latter explains disturbances of motor behaviour with reference to disturbance of a representational function and the former explains the same disturbances in purely mechanistic, causal terms (PP, pp. 125–126, see Jensen 2009 for a discussion of these two models of action as they are played out in Merleau-Ponty’s analysis of the Schneider case).

  10. 10.

    The exact formulation of the Standard Causal Theory is a matter of controversy. This definition is appropriated from the one provided in Aguilar and Buckareff (2010). See Romdenh-Romluc’s contributions to this volume for a detailed discussion of how Merleau-Ponty’s positive account of bodily agency can be read as challenging the Standard Causal Theory (Romdenh-Romluc 2013).

  11. 11.

    The assumption of the agency-neutrality of bodily movements involved in bodily action is the common starting point of much modern philosophy action. For a survey of recent authors who ascribe to the idea of agency-neutral movements see Grünbaum (2008, p. 246, n. 4). The assumption is opposed with different versions of a so called disjunctive conception of bodily movements by amongst others Hornsby (1997), Haddock (2005) and Stout (2010).

  12. 12.

    The argument via Liepmann’s patient Mr. T. is structurally similar to at least one strand in Merleau-Ponty’s argumentation via Gelb and Goldstein’s case of Schneider. See Jensen (2009) for a more detailed analysis of the structure of Merleau-Ponty’s arguments for the existence of non-representational motor intentionality via the case of Schneider.

  13. 13.

    I leave it an open question to what extent a modern defenders of a representationalist picture of the mind could defend a model similar to Liepmann’s by restricting the model to the sub-personal level.

  14. 14.

    See Grünbaum (2006, p. 86) for the relevant notion of teleologically basic actions, developed via Hornsby’s notion (Hornsby 1980).

  15. 15.

    This line of argument draws heavily on Hornsby’s way of arguing for the alienating character of the picture in question (Hornsby 1998, pp. 388–89; Hornsby 2004a, b). Hornsby borrows the image of telekinetic powers from Bernhard Williams account of Descartes’ mind-body problem (Hornsby 1998, p. 389). McDowell indicates a comparable line of argument against the functionalism of Loar, which drives the explanandum of psychological explanations inwards and “away from the agent’s involvement with the world” (McDowell 1998, p. 333). Hornsby pursues a similar argument against a functionalist conception of the mental (1997, p. 114).

References

  • Aguilar, & Buckareff. (2010). The causal theory of action: Origins and issues. In Aguilar & Buckareff (Eds.), Causing human actions. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Anscombe, G. E. M. (1957/2000). Intention. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brewer, B. (1993). The integration of spatial vision and action. In N. Eilan, R. McCarthy, & B. Brewer (Eds.), Spatial representation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Danto, A. (1973). Analytical philosophy of action. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1980). Mental events. In Essays on actions and events. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dokic, J. (2003). The sense of ownership: An analogy between sensation and action. In J. Roessler & N. Eilan (Eds.), Agency and self-awareness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Enç, B. (2003). How we act. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Grünbaum, T. (2006). Awareness of action – In defence of a perceptual account. Ph.D. thesis, Faculty of Humanities, University of Copenhagen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grünbaum, T. (2008). The body in action. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 7(2), 243–261.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haddock, A. (2005). At one with our actions, but at two with our bodies – Hornsby’s account of action. Philosophical Explorations, 8(2), 157–172.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hornsby, J. (1980). Actions. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hornsby, J. (1997). Simple mindedness. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hornsby, J. (1998). Dualism in action. In A. O’Hear (Ed.), Current issues in philosophy of mind. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hornsby, J. (2004a). Agency and actions. In J. Hyman & H. Steward (Eds.), Agency and action, Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement: 55. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hornsby, J. (2004b). Agency and alienation. In C. Mario De & M. David (Eds.), Naturalism in question. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hume, D. (1748/2000). An enquiry concerning human understanding. Kitchener: Batoche.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hurley, S. (1998). Consciousness in action. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1988). Vorlesungen über Ethik und Wertlehre 1908–1914, Husserliana XXVIII. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1992). Ideen zu einer reinen Phänomenologie, Erstes Buch. Hamburg: Felix Meiner Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1996). Beilage V, §12 Husserliana XXX. Dordrecht/Boston/London: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jensen, R. T. (2009). Motor intentionality and the case of Schneider. In D. Legrand, T. Grünbaum, & J. Krueger (Eds.), Phenomenology and the cognitive sciences, Special issue: Dimensions of bodily subjectivity, 8(3), 2009, 371–388.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jensen, R. T. (2013). Merleau-Ponty and McDowell on the transparency of the mind. In R. T. Jensen & D. Moran (Eds.), International Journal of Philosophical Studies, Special issue: Intentionality, 21(3), 470–492.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (2007). Critique of pure reason (2nd ed., N. K. Smith, Trans.). Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, J. (1996). Mind and world. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, J. (1998). Functionalism and anomalous monism. In Mind, value and reality. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (1964). The primacy of perception. In The primacy of perception and other essays on phenomenological psychology, the philosophy of art, history and politics (J. M. Edie, Trans.). Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (1983). The structure of behavior (A. L. Fisher, Trans.). Pittsburg: Duquesne University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (1990). La structure du comportement. Paris: Quadrige/Presses Universitaires de France.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (2012). Phenomenology of perception (D. A. Landes, Trans.). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. O. (1969). Epistemology naturalized. In Ontological relativity and other essays. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rothi, L. J. G., & Heilman, K. M. (1996). Liepmann (1900 and 1905): A definition of apraxia and a model of praxis. In C. Code, C.-W. Wallesch, Y. Joanette, & A. R. Lecours (Eds.), Classic cases in neuropsychology. Hove: Psychology Press/Taylor & Francis.

    Google Scholar 

  • Romdenh-Romluc, K. (2011). Merleau-Ponty and phenomenology of perception. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Romdenh-Romluc, K. (2013). Habit and attention. In R. T. Jensen & D. Moran (Eds.), The phenomenology of embodied subjectivity (Contributions to phenomenology, Vol. 71). Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. (1983). Intentionality. An essay in the philosophy of mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stout, R. (2010). What you cause when you raise your arm. In J. Aguilar & A. Buckareff (Eds.), Causing human action: New perspectives on the causal theory of action. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taminiaux, J. (1991). The thinker and the painter. In M. C. Dillon (Ed.), Merleau-Ponty vivant. Albany: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

The author would like to thank Johan Gersel for his very helpful comments on a prior version of this paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Rasmus Thybo Jensen .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2013 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Jensen, R.T. (2013). Merleau-Ponty and the Transcendental Problem of Bodily Agency. In: Jensen, R., Moran, D. (eds) The Phenomenology of Embodied Subjectivity. Contributions to Phenomenology, vol 71. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-01616-0_3

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics