Skip to main content

Cooperatives’ March to Modernity: Market-Oriented, Apolitical Cooperation

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Cooperation, Community, and Co-Ops in a Global Era

Part of the book series: International and Cultural Psychology ((ICUP))

  • 790 Accesses

Abstract

This chapter explains how commodity based, market exchange notions of cooperation were favored over collective, communal cooperation notions to form a fourth cooperative philosophy. It has become dominant as the cooperative praxis of the contemporary co-op movement. This chapter undertakes a detailed examination of its proposals. It critiques a prominent explication of this fourth cooperative social philosophy that has been articulated by John Restakis and endorsed by prominent cooperative spokespeople. Restakis endorses market-oriented cooperation as a third way between extreme capitalism and centralized socialism. The critique finds the theoretical and historical justification for this cooperative social philosophy to be specious. Restakis points two examples of pre-capitalist markets as models of cooperation that modern co-ops should follow. Yet, his examples include noncooperative institutions such as banks and the merchant class. Other pre-capitalist market relations such as equal exchange on simple economic markets are equally uncooperative. The chapter cites Marx’s critique of simple market relations as alienated. Restakis also condemns socialism as anti-cooperative. However, he is misinformed about Marxist theory. The chapter reiterates how Marx, Engels, Lenin, and Gramsci argued that socialism is cooperation writ large. The founding Marxists also accepted an auxiliary role for markets within socialism. Restakis commits an intellectual mistake by identifying socialism with the failed Stalinist and Maoist revolutions. These revolutions were socialist only in name. Their practices violated all the basic democratic, communal propositions of Marxist theory. Thus, the denunciation of socialism as antithetical to cooperation fails on theoretical and historical grounds. Restakis’ cooperative model also rejects political challenges to capitalism. The guiding principle is co-existence. Restakis argues that apolitical co-ops, operating as enclaves within capitalism, can humanize society. This chapter disputes his claim. It demonstrates that apolitical tactics can never resist the incessant anti-cooperative pressures of capitalism. On the contrary, cooperation can only flourish (within co-ops) and in the society at large, by directly challenging anti-cooperative practices, not by ignoring them.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

References

  • Restakis J (2010) Humanizing the economy: co-operatives in the age of capital. New Society Publishers, British Columbia

    Google Scholar 

  • Hochschild A (2012) The outsourced self: intimate life in market times. Metropolitan Books, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Sellers C (1991) The market revolution. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Marx K (1962) Capital, vol 3. Foreign Languages Publishing House, Moscow

    Google Scholar 

  • Engels F (1973) The origin of the family, private property, and the state. International Publishers (Originally published 1884), New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Hudis P (2012) Marx’s concept of the alternative to capitalism. Brill, Leiden

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Eagleton T (2011) Why Marx was right. Yale University Press, New Haven

    Google Scholar 

  • Engels F (1847) Principles of communism. http://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1847/11/prin-com.htm

  • Lebowitz M (2012) The contradictions of “real socialism”. Monthly Review Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Foster J, McChesney R (2012) The endless crisis. Monthly review 64:1–28

    Google Scholar 

  • Kasmir S (1996) The myth of Mondragon: cooperatives, politics, and working-class life in a Basque town. State University of New York Press, Albany

    Google Scholar 

  • Lenin V (1966) On Cooperation. In: Lenin V (ed) Collected Works, vol 33, (4th English edn). Progress Publishers, Moscow, pp 467–475 (Originally published 1923). http://www.marx2mao.com/Lenin/OC23.html

  • Marx K (1973) Grundrisse: introduction to the critique of political economy. Random House, New York (written in1857)

    Google Scholar 

  • Ozgun A (2010) A common word. Rethinking Marxism 22(3):374–381

    Google Scholar 

  • Rhodes Rita (1995) The international co-operative alliance during war and peace, 1910–1950. The International Co-operative Alliance, Geneva

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith R (2007) The eco-suicidal economics of Adam Smith. Capitalism, nature, socialism 18(2):22–43

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Velikonja M (2009) Lost in transition: nostalgia for socialism in post-socialist countries. East European Politics Societies 23:535–551

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Carl Ratner .

End Notes

End Notes

1. Marx says,

But whatever may be the social organization of the spheres of production, whose exchange of commodities the merchant promotes, his wealth exists always in the form of money and his money always serves as capital. Its form is always M—C—M’. Money, the independent form of exchange value, is his starting point, expansion of the exchange value his independent purpose. This M—C—M’ is the characteristic movement of merchants’ capital which distinguishes it from C—M—C, the exchange of commodities between the producers themselves, which has for its ultimate end the exchange of use-values (Marx 1962, p. 321).

2. This has important consequences for understanding social life. Social life is difficult to understand because it is a series of uncontrolled, unpredictable acts by independent individuals. Social life is the by-product of individual collisions. It is not consciously, rationally planned. It is therefore alien to the observers, not of their making. Even the wealthiest, most powerful, politically connected capitalist has no control over or knowledge about what other capitalists might do at any moment. The overall society is not within the grasp or understanding of any individual because competing, independent, and secretive other individuals are outside him.

This leads to the paradoxical problem that human social life is less understandable and less understood than natural phenomena. Social life should be more understandable because it is constructed by us. Natural phenomena—such as the formation of the universe, the formation of the earth, the phylogeny of species, and the chemical structure of water—are independent of humans and should be more mysterious than social phenomena that humans create themselves. However, natural phenomena obey strict natural laws that are comprehensible. Social life does not obey such strict laws because humans are active and creative agents. Social life can only be understood if social dynamics are rationally designed and administered by humans so that most individuals act concertedly. Capitalism, in particular, is not rationally designed, which makes its dynamics difficult to gage.

3. Experimental studies on decision making demonstrate that people are less altruistic when they are paid, or expect to be paid, for some behavior, compared to doing it as a community activity.

More organic, collective social relations are necessary to realize cooperation, social concern, social support, equality, and freedom to express oneself and control one’s social life (Ozgun 2010).

4. From the perspective of most people in eastern European countries, the recent communist/socialist past was better than the market economy that replaced it. In 1999, 50 % of Slovakians considered the former socialist regime to be ‘better than current democracy’. In the same year, in Russia, it was found that 85 % of Russians regret communism and Soviet Union’s demise. In 2004 the figure fell to 74 %. In 2002, 56 % of Poles were telling opinion pollsters that life ‘was better before’. In 1995 and 2003, 88 % and respectively, 86 % of Slovenians considered life in the former Yugoslavia, as ‘good’ and ‘very good’. More recently (2009) 72 % of Hungarians, 62 % of Bulgarians and Ukrainians, 60 % of Romanians, 45 % of Russians, 42 % of Lithuanians and Slovaks, 39 % of Czechs, and 35 % of Poles declared they were worse off than during communism (Velikonja 2009).

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2013 Springer Science+Business Media New York

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Ratner, C. (2013). Cooperatives’ March to Modernity: Market-Oriented, Apolitical Cooperation. In: Cooperation, Community, and Co-Ops in a Global Era. International and Cultural Psychology. Springer, New York, NY. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-4614-5825-8_5

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics