Skip to main content
  • 2622 Accesses

The ascent of public choice theory2, including the public choice society and its journal, is clearly one of the great success stories of post-war social and political theory. Nevertheless, to look at it from the point of view of philosophy poses a task of critical appraisal rather than uncritical applause. Public choice theory as interpreted here essentially forms an economic approach to politics and to public law (the most comprehensive presentation of this view being Mueller, 2003). Therefore I shall focus on the role of economics’ core assumption of opportunistically rational and selfish behavior in public choice. As shown in the first part, (1) the views expressed by some classics of philosophy are at the root of modern public choice theory. Beyond that, some of them should be taken seriously as systematic contributions to present discussions about public choice in general and the role of the basic behavioral assumption of the rational economic man in particular. (2) On the basis of the discussion of the first part, the second assesses the public choice account of constitutional democracy in terms of individual rational choice. Philosophically promising amendments from the “neo-classical repair shop” that might conceivably solve some of the “paradoxes” of the standard economic approach to constitutional democracy are discussed. (3) The third part summarizes and concludes what may be seen as a “philosopher cum economist’s” view of public choice.

This chapter is a revised and updated version of an essay that first appeared in The Encyclopedia of Public Choice edited by Charles K. Rowley and Friedrich Schneider and published in 2004 by Kluwer Academic Publishers, Volume I, 235–244.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 189.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 249.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 249.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  • Albert, H. (1985). Treatise on Critical Reason. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, G. M. and R. D. Tollison. (1993). Wealth Maximization in Hell. Volume 13. Fairfax, VA: Center for Study of Public Choice.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arendt, H. (1951). The Origins of Totalitarianism. New York: Harcourt.

    Google Scholar 

  • Austin, J. (1954). The Province of Jurisprudence Determined. London: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Axelrod, R. (1984). The Evolution of Cooperation. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barry, N. (1981). An Introduction to Modern Political Theory. London: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baumol, W. J. (1972). Economic Theory and Operations Analysis. London: Prentice Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Benson, B. (1990). The Enterprise of Law. Justice Without the State. San Francisco: Pacific Research Institute for Public Policy.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brennan, H. G. and J. M. Buchanan. (1984). ‘‘Voter choice: Evaluating political alternatives.’’ American Behavioral Scientist, 28(2), 185-201.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brennan, H. G. and J. M. Buchanan. (1985). The Reason of Rules. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brennan, H. G. and K. Hartmut. (1990). ‘‘Logo logic.’’ Journal of Constitutional Political Economy, 1(1), 125-127.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brennan, H. G. and L. E. Lomasky. (1983). ‘‘Institutional aspects of ‘merit goods’ analysis.’’ Finanzarchiv, N.F., 41(2), 183-206.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brennan, H. G. and L. E. Lomasky (1984). ‘‘Inefficient unaminity.’’ Journal of Applied Philosophy, 1(1), 151-163.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brennan, H. G. and L. E. Lomasky. (1985). ‘‘The impartial spectator goes to Washington.’’ Economics and Philosophy, 1, 189-211.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brennan, H. G. and L. E. Lomasky. (1989). Large Numbers, Small Costs—Politics and Process— New Essays in Democratic Thought. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brennan, H. G. and L. E. Lomasky. (1994). Democracy and Decision. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, J. M. (1954). ‘‘Individual choice in voting and the market.’’ Journal of Political Economy, 62, 334-343.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, J. M. (1972). ‘‘Before public Choice,’’ in G. Tullock. (ed.) Explorations in the Theory of Anarchy. Blacksburg, VA.: Center for Study of Public Choice, pp. 27-37.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, J. M. (1979). ‘‘Politics without romance: A sketch of positive public choice theory and its normative implications.’’ IHS Journal, Zeitschrift des Instituts fu¨r Ho¨here Studien—Wien, 3, B1-B11.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, J. M. (1999). The Collected Works of James M. Buchanan. Indianapolis: Liberty Fund.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, J. M. (1999a). The Logical Foundations of Constitutional Liberty. Indianapolis: Liberty Fund.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, J. M. (1999b). Moral Science and Moral Order. Indianapolis: Liberty Fund.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, J. M. and Gordon T. (1962). The Calculus of Consent. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • de Jasay, A. (1989). Social Contract—Free Ride. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • de Jasay, A. (1996). ‘‘Justice as something else.’’ The Cato Journal, 16(2), 161-173.

    Google Scholar 

  • de Spinoza, B. (1951). A Theologico-Political Treatise. A Political Treatise. New York: Dover. Row.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frank, R. (1987). ‘‘If homo economicus could choose his own utility function, would he want one with a conscience?’’ The American Economic Review, 77(4), 593-604.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frank, R. (1988). The Passions within Reason: Prisoner’s Dilemmas and the Strategic Role of the Emotions. New York: Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frey, B. S. (1997). Not Just For the Money. An Economic Theory of Personal Motivation. Cheltenham: Edward Elgar Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frohlich, N. and J. A. Oppenheimer. (1992). Choosing Justice. An Experimantal Approach to Ethical Theory. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fudenberg, D. and T. Jean. (1992). Game Theory. Cambridge, London: The MIT Press (Massachusetts Institute of Technology).

    Google Scholar 

  • Guth, W. and K. Hartmut. (1998). ‘‘Towards a fully indirect evolutionary approach.’’ Rationality and Society, 10(3), 377-399.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Guth, W., S. Rolf, and S. Bernd. (1982). ‘‘An experimental analysis of ultimatum bargaining.’’ Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 3, 367-388.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Guth, W., L. Wolfgang, and S. Gunther. (1991). ‘‘On supergames and folk theorems: A conceptual analysis,’’ in R. Selten (ed.) Game Equilibrium Models. Morals, Methods, and Markets. Berlin Heidelberg New York: Springer, pp. 56-70.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hampton, J. (1988). Hobbes and the Social Contract Tradition. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hardin, R. (1982). ‘‘Exchange theory on strategic basis.’’ Social Science Information, 2, 251

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hart, H. L. A. (1961). The Concept of Law. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heyd, D. (1982). Supererogation. Its Status in Ethical Theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hobbes, T. (1682/1990). Behemoth or The Long Parliament. Chicago: Chicago University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hume, D. (1985). Essays. Moral, Political and Literary. Indianapolis: Liberty Fund.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kagel, J. H. and A. E. Roth (eds.) (1995). The Handbook of Experimental Economics. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, D. and T. Amos. (1984). ‘‘Choices, values and frames.’’ American Psychologist, 39, 341-350.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kliemt, H. (1986). ‘‘The veil of insignificance.’’ European Journal of Political Economy, 2(3), 333-344.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kliemt, H. (1987). ‘‘The reason of rules and the rule of reason.’’ Critica, 19, 43-86.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kliemt, H. (1993). ‘‘Constitutional commitments,’’ in P. H. Herder Dorneich (ed.) Jahrbuch fu¨r Neuere Politische O¨konomie. pp. 145-173.

    Google Scholar 

  • Margolis, H. (1982). Selfishness, Altruism, and Rationality. A Theory of Social Choice. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mueller, D. C. (2003). Public Choice III. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Myerson, R. B. (1991). Game Theory—Analysis of Conflict. Cambridge, London: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Olson, M. (1965). The Logic of Collective Action. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Palfrey, T. R. and R. Howard. (1984). ‘‘Participation and the provision of discrete public goods: a strategic analysis.’’ Journal of Public Economics, 24, 171-193.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Parsons, T. (1968). Utilitarianism. Sociological Thought. New York: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Robertson, D. H. (1956). Economic Commentaries. London: Staples Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roth, A. E. (1995). ‘‘Bargaining experiments,’’ in John H. Kagel and Alvin E. Roth (eds.) The Handbook of Experimental Economics. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 253-348.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ryle, G. (1931-32). ‘‘Systematically misleading expressions.’’ Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 32, 139-170.

    Google Scholar 

  • Selten, R. (1965). ‘‘Spieltheoretische Behandlung eines Oligopolmodells mit Nachfragetragheit.’’ Zeitschrift fu¨r die gesamte Staatswissenschaft, 12, 301-24, 667-689.

    Google Scholar 

  • Selten, R. (1975). ‘‘Reexamination of the perfectness concept for equilibrium in extensive games.’’ International Journal of Game Theory, 4, 25-55.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sugden, R. (2004). ‘‘What philosophy and public choice should not learn from one another’’, The American Journal of Economics and Sociology, Vol. 63, 207-211.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, M. (1987). The Possibility of Cooperation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, M. and Hugh W. (1982). ‘‘Chickens, whales, and lumpy goods: alternative models of public-goods provisions.’’ Political Studies, 30, 350-370.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tullock, G. (1967). Toward a Mathematics of Politics. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tullock, G. (1971). ‘‘The charity of the uncharitable.’’ Western Economic Journal, 9, 379-392.

    Google Scholar 

  • Urmson, J. O. (1958). ‘‘Saints and heroes,’’ in I. Melden (ed.) Essays in Moral Philosophy. Seattle: University of Washington Press, 198 ff.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2008 Springer Science + Business Media, LLC

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Kliemt, H. (2008). The Perspective of Philosophy. In: Readings in Public Choice and Constitutional Political Economy. Springer, Boston, MA. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-0-387-75870-1_14

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics