Skip to main content

Belief Ascription, Metaphor, and Intensional Identification

  • Chapter
  • 483 Accesses

Part of the book series: Text, Speech and Language Technology ((TLTB,volume 35))

This article discusses the extension of ViewGen, an algorithm derived for belief ascription, to the areas of intensional object identification and metaphor. ViewGen represents the beliefs of agents as explicit, partitioned proposition sets known as environments. Environments are convenient, even essential, for addressing important pragmatic issues of reasoning. The article concentrates on showing that the transfer of information in metaphors, intensional object identification, and ordinary, nonmetaphorical belief ascription can all be seen as different manifestations of a single environment-amalgamation process. The article also briefly discusses the extension of ViewGen to speech-act processing and the addition of a heuristic-based, relevance-determination procedure, and justifies the partitioning approach to belief ascription

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   169.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. Allen, J.F., & Perrault, C.R. (1978). Participating in dialogue understanding via plan deduction. Proceedings of the Second National Conference of the Canadian Society for Computational Studies of Intelligence. Toronto, Canada.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Anderson, A., & Belnap, J. (1975). Entailment: The logic of relevance and necessity. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Austin, J.L. (1962). How to do things with words. Oxford, England: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Ballim, A. (1986). Generating points of view. In Memoranda in computer and cognitive science (Tech. Rep. No. MCCS-86-68). Las Cruces: New Mexico State University, Computing Research Laboratory.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Ballim, A. (1987). The subjective ascription of belief to agents. In J. Hallam & C. Mellish (Eds.), Advances in artificial intelligence. Chichester, England: Wiley & Sons.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Ballim, A. (1988a, July). A language for representing and reasoning with nested belief. Proceedings of the First Annual Irish Conference on Artificial Intelligence and Cognitive Science. Dublin, Ireland.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Ballim, A. (1988b). Belief convictions, quantification, and default reasoning. Unpublished manuscript.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Ballim A., & Wilks, Y. (in press). Artificial believers. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Barnden, J.A. (1983). Intensions as such: An outline. Proceedings of the 8th International Joint Conference on Artificial Intelligence (pp. 347–353). Los Altos, CA: Morgan Kaufman.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Barnden, J.A. (1986). Imputations and explications: Representational problems in treatments of propositional attitudes. Cognitive Science, 10, 319–364.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  11. Barnden, J.A. (1987a). Interpreting propositional attitude reports: Towards greater freedom and control. In B. du Boulay, D. Hogg, & L. Steels (Eds.), Advances in artificial intelligence-II. Amsterdam: Elsevier (North-Holland).

    Google Scholar 

  12. Barnden, J.A. (1987b). Avoiding some unwarranted entailments between nested attitude reports. In Memoranda in computer and cognitive science (Tech. Rep. No. MCCS-87-113). Las Cruces: New Mexico State University, Computing Research Laboratory.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Barnden, J.A. (1988). Propositional attitudes, commonsense reasoning, and metaphor. Proceedings of the 10th Annual Conference of the Cognitive Science Society (pp. 347–353). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Barnden, J.A. (1989a). Towards a paradigm shift in belief representation methodology. Journal of Experimental and Theoretical Artificial Intelligence, 1, 131–161.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Barnden, J.A. (1989b). Belief, metaphorically speaking. Proceedings of the First International Conference on Principles of Knowledge Representation and Reasoning (pp. 21–32). San Mateo, CA: Morgan Kaufmann.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Barnden, J.A. (1990). Naive metaphysics: A metaphor-based approach to propositional attitude representation. In Memoranda in computer and cognitive science (Tech. Rep. No. MCCS-90-174). Las Cruces: New Mexico State University, Computing Research Laboratory.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Carbonell, J.G. (1982). Metaphor: An inescapable phenomenon in natural language comprehension. In W. Lehnert & M. Ringle (Eds.), Strategies for natural language processing. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Charniak, E. (1978). On the use of knowledge in language comprehension. Artificial Intelligence, 11, 225–265.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  19. Cohen, P., & Levesque, H. (1980). Speech acts and recognition of shared plans. Proceedings of the Third Biennial Conference of the Canadian Society for Computational Studies in Intelligence (pp. 263–271).

    Google Scholar 

  20. Cohen, P., & Levesque, H. (1985). Speech acts and rationality. Proceedings of the 23rd Annual Meeting of the Association for Computational Linguistics (pp. 49–60). University of Chicago.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Cohen, P.R., & Levesque, H.J. (1987, July). Intention = Choice + Commitment. Proceedings of the Sixth National Conference on Artificial Intelligence, 410–415. Seattle.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Cohen, J., & Margalit, A. (1972). The role of inductive reasoning in the interpretation of metaphor. In D. Davidson & G. Harman (Eds.), Semantics of natural language. Dordrecht, Holland: Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Creary, L.G. (1979). Propositional attitudes: Fregean representation and simulative reasoning. Proceedings of the Sixth International Joint Conference on Artificial Intelligence (pp. 176–181). Los Altos, CA: Morgan Kaufmann.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Davidson, D. (1978). What metaphors mean. Critical Inquiry, 5, 31–48.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  25. Dinsmore, J. (1987). Mental spaces from a functional perspective. Cognitive Science, 11, 1–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  26. Fagin, R., & Halpern, J.Y. (1987). Belief, awareness and limited reasoning. Artificial Intelligence, 34, 39–76.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  27. Falkenhainer, B., Forbus, K., & Gentner, D. (1986). The structure-mapping engine. Proceedings of the Fifth National Conference on Artificial Intelligence (pp. 272–278). Los Altos, CA: Morgan Kaufmann.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Fass, D.C. (1987). Collative semantics: An overview of the current Meta 5 program. In Memoranda in computer and cognitive science (Tech. Rep. No. MCCS-87-112). Las Cruces: New Mexico State University, Computing Research Laboratory.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Fauconnier, G. (1985). Mental spaces: Aspects of meaning construction in natural language. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Grosz, B.J. (1977). The representation and use of focus in a system for understanding dialogs. Proceedings of the Fifth International Joint Conference on Artificial Intelligence (pp. 67–76). Los Altos, CA: Morgan Kaufmann.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Hendrix, G.G. (1979). Encoding knowledge in partitioned networks. In N.V. Findler (Ed.), Associative networks. New York: Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Hobbs, J.R. (1983a). Metaphor interpretation as selective inferencing: Cognitive processes in understanding metaphor (Part 1). Empirical Studies of the Arts, 1, 17–33.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Hobbs, J.R. (1983b). Metaphor interpretation as selective inferencing: Cognitive processes in understanding metaphor (Part 2). Empirical Stuidies of the Arts, 1, 125–141.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Indurkhya, B. (1987). Approximate semantic transference: A computational theory of metaphor. Cognitive Science, 11, 445–480.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  35. Johnson, M. (1987). The body in the mind. Chicago: Chicago University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Johnson-Laird, J.N. (1983). Mental models. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  37. Konolige, K. (1983). A deductive model of belief. Proceedings of the Eighth International Joint Conference on Artificial Intelligence (pp. 377–381). Los Altos, CA: Morgan Kaufmann.

    Google Scholar 

  38. Lakoff, G. (1987). Women, fire, and dangerous things: What categories reveal about the mind. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  39. Lakoff, G., & Johnson, M. (1980). Metaphors we live by. Chicago: Chicago University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  40. Levesque, H. (1984). A logic of implicit and explicit belief. Proceedings of the Fourth National Conference on Artificial Intelligence (pp. 198–202). Los Altos, CA: Morgan Kaufmann.

    Google Scholar 

  41. Maida, A.S. (1983). Knowing intensional individuals. Proceedings of the Eighth International Joint Conference on Artificial Intelligence (pp. 382–384). Los Altos, CA: Morgan Kaufmann.

    Google Scholar 

  42. Maida, A.S. (1984). Belief spaces: Foundations of a computational theory of belief (Tech. Rep. No. CS-84-22). University Park: Pennsylvania State University, Department of Computer Science.

    Google Scholar 

  43. Maida, A.S. (1986). Introspection and reasoning about the beliefs of other agents. Proceedings of the Eighth Annual Conference of the Cognitive Science Society (pp. 187–195). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  44. Maida, A.S. (1988). A syntactic approach to mental correspondence. Proceedings of the Canadian Society for Computational Studies of Artificial Intelligence (pp. 53–58). Edmonton, Alberta.

    Google Scholar 

  45. Maida, A.S., & Shapiro, S.C. (1982). Intensional concepts in propositional semantic networks. Cognitive Science, 6, 291–330.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  46. Martins, J., & Shapiro, S. (1988). A model for belief revision. Artificial Intelligence, 35, 25–79.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  47. McCarthy, J., & Hayes, P. (1969). Some philosophical problems from the standpoint of artificial intelligence. In B. Meltzer & D. Michie (Eds.), Machine Intelligence 4. Edinburgh, U.K.: Edinburgh University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  48. Minsky, M. (1975). A framework for representing knowledge. In P.H. Winston (Ed.), The psychology of computer vision. New York: McGraw-Hill.

    Google Scholar 

  49. Perrault, R. (1987). Invited presentation. Meeting of the Association for Computational Linguistics. Stanford, CA.

    Google Scholar 

  50. Perrault, R. (1990). An application of default logic to speech act theory. In P. Cohen, J. Morgan, & M. Pollack (Eds.), Plans and intentions in communication and discourse. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  51. Perrault, R., & Allen, J. (1980). A plan-based analysis of indirect speech acts. American Journal of Computational Linguistics, 6, 167–182.

    Google Scholar 

  52. Quine, W.V.O. (1960). Word and object. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  53. Rapaport, W. (1986). Logical foundations for belief representation. Cognitive Science, 10, 371–422.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  54. Schiffer, S. (1972). Meaning. Oxford, U.K.: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  55. Searle, J. (1969). Speech acts, an essay in the philosophy of language. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  56. Shadbolt, N. (1983). Processing reference. Journal of Semantics, 2, 63–98.

    Google Scholar 

  57. Shapiro, S. (1976). The relevance of relevance. Indiana University, Computer Science Department, Bloomington.

    Google Scholar 

  58. Shapiro, S.C., & Rapaport, W.J. (1986). SNePS considered as a fully intensional pro-positional semantic network. Proceedings of the Fifth National Conference on Artificial Intelligence (pp. 278–283). Los Altos, CA: Morgan Kaufmann.

    Google Scholar 

  59. Sperber, D., & Wilson, D. (1986). Relevance, communication and cognition. Oxford, England: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  60. Subramanian, D., & Genesereth, M.R. (1987). The relevance of irrelevance. Proceedings of the 10th International Joint Conference on Artificial Intelligence (pp. 416–422). Los Altos, CA: Morgan Kaufmann.

    Google Scholar 

  61. Wiebe, J., & Rapaport, W. (1986). Representing de re and de dicto belief reports in discourse and narrative. Proceedings of IEEE, 74, 1405–1413.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  62. Wilks, Y. (1977). Making preferences more active. Artificial Intelligence, 8, 75–97.

    Google Scholar 

  63. Wilks, Y. (1986). Relevance and beliefs. In T. Myers, K. Brown, & B. McGonigle (Eds.), Reasoning and discourse processes. London: Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  64. Wilks, Y. (1990). Models and theories in artificial intelligence.In D. Partridge & Y. Wilks (Eds.), The foundations of artificial intelligence: A sourcebook. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  65. Wilks, Y., & Ballim, A. (1987). Multiple agents and the heuristic ascription of beliefs. Proceedings of the 10th International Joint Conference on Artificial Intelligence (pp. 118–124). Los Altos, CA: Morgan Kaufmann.

    Google Scholar 

  66. Wilks, Y., & Ballim, A. (1988). Shifting the belief engine into higher gear. In T. O’Shea & V. Sgurev (Eds.), Proceedings of the International Conference on AI Methodology and Systems Applications. Amsterdam: Elsevier Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  67. Wilks, Y., & Ballim, A. (1989a). Belief systems: Ascribing belief. In T. Christaller (Ed.), Kunstliche intelligenz (pp. 386–403). Berlin: Springer-Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  68. Wilks, Y., & Ballim, A. (1989b). The heuristic ascription of belief. In N.E. Sharkey (Ed.), Models of cognition: A review of cognitive science (pp. 1–23). Norwood, NJ: Ablex.

    Google Scholar 

  69. Wilks, Y., & Bien, J. (1979). Speech acts and multiple environments. Proceedings of the Sixth International Joint Conference on Artificial Intelligence (pp. 968–970). Tokyo, Japan.

    Google Scholar 

  70. Wilks, Y., & Bien, J. (1983). Beliefs, points of view, and multiple environments. Cognitive Science, 8, 120–146.

    Google Scholar 

  71. Wilks, T., Fass, D., Guo, C-M., McDonald, J., Plate, T., & Slator, B. (1989). A tractable machine dictionary as a resource for computational semantics. In B.K. Boguraev & T. Briscoe (Eds.), Computational lexicography for natural language processing. Harlow, U.K.: Longmans.

    Google Scholar 

  72. Wilks, Y., Fass, D., Guo, C-M., McDonald, J., Plate, T., & Slator, B. (in press). Providing machine tractable dictionary tools. In J. Pustejousky (Ed.), Semantics and the lexicon. Hingham, MA: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2007 Springer

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Ballim, A., Wilks, Y., Barnden, J. (2007). Belief Ascription, Metaphor, and Intensional Identification. In: Ahmad, K., Brewster, C., Stevenson, M. (eds) Words and Intelligence I. Text, Speech and Language Technology, vol 35. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/1-4020-5285-5_9

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/1-4020-5285-5_9

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-1-4020-5284-2

  • Online ISBN: 978-1-4020-5285-9

  • eBook Packages: Computer ScienceComputer Science (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics