Skip to main content

Suicide, Assisted Suicide and Euthanasia

  • Chapter
  • 169 Accesses

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Endnotes and References

  1. The problem is beautifully described in a short story by Richard Selzer who offers an insight into the emotional problem health care professionals encounter in such situations. The story does not offer a solution—indeed it neither sets out to do so nor can. But as a description of a terrible moral (even if not ethical) problem is has no peer. See R. Selzer, Down from Troy: A Doctor comes of Age (NY: Chivers, North America), 1992.

    Google Scholar 

  2. P. Carrick, Medical Ethics in Antiquity (Boston: D. Reidel Publishers), 1985.

    Google Scholar 

  3. In the first century, early Christianity forbade all killing whether as capital punishment, in war or even in self-defense. This posed a great problem for the Roman Empire. On the one hand, they could not ignore an ever-growing segment of their population. On the other hand, they could not condone capital punishment or give citizenship to persons who refused to serve in the army. The first church-state accord resulted. The church permitted killing those who were fighting an unjust war and those who had broken a just law. The definition of what was “just” and what “unjust” was left up to the state. Curiously enough, killing in self-defense remained proscribed until about the time of St. Augustine. An excellent description of this “doctrine of innocence” can be found in J. Rachels, The End of Life. (NY: Oxford University Press, 1986), pp. 11–13

    Google Scholar 

  4. See Sir Thomas More, Utopia, trans. and ed. by R.M. Adams (NY: Norton), 1975. One of the best and earliest discussions of this book can be found in K. Kautsky, Thomas More and His Utopia, trans. by R. Ames (NY: Russell & Russell), 1959. Another excellent source is G.M. Logan, The Meaning of More’s Utopia (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press), 1983

    Google Scholar 

  5. Euthanasia as conceived by the Nazis was neither a “good death” nor a death brought about so as to benefit (or to prevent harm to) the person killed. While this program was carried on in semi-secrecy, the propaganda made for abandoning persons termed “nutzlose Fresser” (“useless eaters”) was clearly visible to all. The extermination of the Jews was not termed “euthanasia:” the euphemism ”euthanasia” was too evidently a euphemism to allow its use even at that late date. It is frightening to realize that the tentative lists of persons believed to be “genetically unfit” and proper subjects at least for sterilization, was later used when it came to the Nazi “euthanasia” program. For example, “the feeble-minded, the pauper class, the criminal class, the epileptics, the insane, the constitutionally weak, or the asthenic class, those predisposed to specific diseases or the diathetic class, the deformed, those having defective sense organs, as the blind and the deaf“) was a list first suggested by an American, Bleeker Van Wagenen, at a conference in at the University of London in 1912 in his “Preliminary Report of the Committee of the Eugenics Section of the American Breeders’ Association to Study and to Report on the Best Practical Means for Cutting off the Defective Germ Plasm in the Human Population,” Problems in Eugenics, Ed. by W.C. Adelphi (NY: The Eugenics Education Society), 1912. The most definitive work on this subject is E. Klee, Euthanasie im NS-Staat (Frankfurt a/M, Deutschland: Fischer Tachenbuch Verlag), 1991, As background, the following also can be recommended: L. Alexander, “Medical Science under Dictatorship,” New England Journal of Medicine, 1949; 241: 39–47; R.J. Lifton: The Nazi Doctors. (NY: Basic Books), 1986 and K. Moe, ’should the Nazi Research Data Be Cited?” Hastings Center Report, 1984; 14(6): 5–7.

    Google Scholar 

  6. E.H. Loewy, “Drunks, Livers and Values: Should Social Value Judgments Enter into Transplant Decisions?” Journal of Clinical Gastroenterology, 1987; 9: 436–441.

    Google Scholar 

  7. I Kant, Foundations of the Metaphysics of Morals, trans. by Lewis White Beck (Indianapolis, IN: Macmillan Publishing, 1986), p. 47.

    Google Scholar 

  8. The point that patient’s in hospitals today rarely die when nothing to prolong their life can be done, is a point evident to all who have worked as nurses, physicians or ethics consultants in a hospital. The point is made in two papers: E.H. Loewy, “Futility and its Wider Implications,” Archives of Internal Medicine, 1993; 153: 429–431 and E.H. Loewy, “Futility and the Goals of Medicine,” European Philosophy of Medicine and Health Care, 1993; 1(2) 15–27.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  9. T.E. Quill, “Palliative Options of Last Resort: A Comparison of Voluntarily Stopping Eating and Drinking, Terminal Sedation, Physician assisted Suicide and Voluntary Active Euthanasia,” Journal ofthe American Medical Association, 1997; 278(23): 2099–2104.

    Google Scholar 

  10. There is a fairly substantial literature on the problem of self-delusion. See: M.W. Martin, Self-Deception and Morality, (Lawrence, Kansas: University Press of Kansas), 1986.

    Google Scholar 

  11. E.H. Loewy: Moral Strangers. Moral Acquaintances and Moral Friends: Interconnect-edness and its Conditions (Albany, NY: State University of New York Press), 1997.

    Google Scholar 

  12. J. Rachels, The End of Life (NY: Oxford University Press), 1986.

    Google Scholar 

  13. W. Gaylin, et al., “Doctors Must Not Kill,” Journal of the American Medical Association, 1988; 259: 2139–2140.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  14. D.W. Amundsen, “The Physician’s Obligation to Prolong Life: A Medical Duty Without Classical Roots.” Hastings Center Report, 1978; 8(4): 23–31

    Google Scholar 

  15. E.D. Pellegrino, “Toward a Reconstruction of Medical Morality: The Primacy of the Act of Profession and the Fact of Illness,” Journal of Medicine & Philosophy, 1979; 4(1): 32–56.

    Google Scholar 

  16. L.R. Churchill, “Bioethical Reductionism and Our Sense of the Human,” Man & Medicine, 1980; 5: 229–247.

    Google Scholar 

  17. See A.E. Chin, et al., “Legalized Physician-assisted Suicide in Oregon-the First Year’s Experience,” New England Journal of Medicine, 1999; 340(7): 577–57; the details can be found on the Internet under http://www.ohd.or.state.or.us/cdpe/chs/pas/ar-index.htm (1998).

    Article  Google Scholar 

  18. R. Pear, “House Backs Ban on Using Medicine to Aid in Suicide,” New York Times, 28. October 1999, Vol. CXLlX(51,689); p. 1, 29.

    Google Scholar 

  19. J. Hardwig, “Is there a Duty to Die?” Hastings Center Report, 1997; 27(2): 34–42.

    Google Scholar 

  20. There are a number of papers that speak to this issue. Among others, see D. Ozar, “AIDS, Risk and the Obligation of Health Professionals,” Biomedical Ethics Review, ed. by J. Humber and R. Almeder (NY: Humana Press) 1989 and E.H. Loewy, “AIDS and the Human Community,” Social Science and Medicine, 1988; 27(4): 297–304.

    Google Scholar 

  21. E.H. Loewy, “Healing and Killing, Harming and not Harming: Physician Participation in Euthanasia and Capital Punishment,” Journal of Clinical Ethics, 1992; 3(1): 29–34.

    Google Scholar 

  22. J. Hardwig, “What about the Family?” Hastings Center Report, 1990; 19(2): 5–10.

    Google Scholar 

  23. T. Kushner, “Having a Life versus Being Alive,” Journal of Medical Ethics, 1984; 1: 5–8.

    Google Scholar 

  24. There is a vast literature dealing with this point. For a general review, which includes discussion about the implication of the churches in both preparing the soil for and failing to resist the Nazi atrocities see, for example, J. Weiss, Ideology of Death: Why the Holocaust Happened in Germany (Chicago: Ivan R. Dee, Publishers), 1996 and R. Hilberg, The Destruction of the European Jews (NY: Holmer and Meier Publishers), 1985. For the role of physicians in the holocaust, see A. Mitscherlich and F. Mielke, Medizin ohne Menschlickkeit: Dokumente des Nürnbergers Arzteprozesses (Frankfurt a/M: Fischer Tachenbuch), 1986 and H. Friedlander, The Origins of Nazi Genocide: From Euthanasia to the Final Solution (Chapel Hill, NC: University of North Carolina Press), 1997.

    Google Scholar 

  25. M. Burleigh, Death and Deliverance: “Euthanasia ” in Germany, 1900–1945 (NY: Cambridge University Press), 1994.

    Google Scholar 

  26. E.H. Loewy and R.S. Loewy, “Lebensunwertes Leben and the Obligation to Die: Does the Obligation to Die Rest on a Misunderstanding of Community?” Health Care Analysis, 1999; 7: 23–36

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2002 Kluwer Academic Publishers

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

(2002). Suicide, Assisted Suicide and Euthanasia. In: The Ethics of Terminal Care. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/0-306-46836-0_6

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/0-306-46836-0_6

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-0-306-46435-5

  • Online ISBN: 978-0-306-46836-0

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics