Skip to main content

Myths of Simulation

  • Conference paper
  • First Online:

Abstract

Certain myths have emerged about computer technology in general, such as the almighty electronic brain that outperforms humans in every discipline or legends about the capability of artificial intelligence. Some of these myths find echoes in the field of computer simulation, like simulation being pure number-crunching on supercomputers. This article reflects on myths about computer simulation and tries to oppose them. At the beginning of the paper, simulation is defined. Then, some central myths about computer simulation will are identified from a general computer science perspective. The first central myth is that simulation is a virtual experiment. This view is contradicted by the argument, that computer simulation is located in between theory and experiment. Furthermore, access to reality is possible indirectly via representation. The second myth is that simulation is said to be exact. This myth can be falsified by examining technical and conceptual limitations of computer technology. Moreover, arguments are presented as to why ideal exactness is neither possible nor necessary. A third myth emerges from the general overstatement of computer technology: Everything can be simulated. It will be shown that simulation can only solve problems that can be formalized and calculated—and can only produce results that are within the scope of the models they are based on.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    For myths and critique on artificial intelligence, see Dreyfus (1992).

  2. 2.

    It seems that nowadays, myths are no longer relevant, due to the technical and scientific progress. However, this does not mean that science and logic are protected from falling back into myths, when logic and science are set as the absolute methods to gain knowledge in an epistemological process. Moreover, this means that enlightenment does not necessarily imply progress. Horkheimer and Adorno discuss this in Horkheimer and Adorno (1972).

  3. 3.

    As Paul Humphreys (2009) states, humans are not able to oversee and reproduce the simulation process (and especially the calculations on the lower levels of computation) since it is too complex and the processing speed is too high. Consequently, computer simulation must be seen as a black box with lots of abstraction that a human is not able to retrace.

  4. 4.

    The example Winsberg gives of a physicist studying “the interaction of a pair of fluids at supersonic speeds”, relies on the following background knowledge: The theory of fluids and the physicist’s intuition regarding the physical assumptions are arguments for the external validity of the study. As a third, the tricks physicists apply to make the simulations work, which are in turn derived from the historicity of the simulation process, stand for the specific model building principle.

  5. 5.

    Quantum computing could change all of this since it is able to break down complexity classes so that problems with an exponential time complexity could become feasible. However, this is out of the scope of this paper. Furthermore, if-then argumentations lead to speculative discussions that are no longer scientific or productive, such as in the discussions on nanotechnology (Nordmann 2007).

  6. 6.

    One could now argue that machine learning could change the whole picture. Nevertheless, in terms of the algorithms, there is still strong transparency: All the steps of a computer program are determined, but the opaqueness of the paths of the steps as well as of the results, is increased so that they become not traceable. However, a closer look at machine learning is beyond the scope of this paper.

References

  • Arnold, Eckhart. 2015. How Models Fail - A Critical Look at the History of Computer Simulations of the Evolution of Cooperation. In Collective Agency and Cooperation in Natural and Artificial Systems. Explanation, Implementation and Simulation, Philosophical Studies Series, ed. Catrin Misselhorn, 261–279. Springer. doi:10.1007/978-3-319-15515-9.

  • Beisbart, Claus. 2012. How can computer simulations produce new knowledge? European Journal for Philosophy of Science 2 (3): 395–434.

    Article  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Blumenberg, Hans. 1979. Arbeit am Mythos. Suhrkamp: Frankfurt a. M.

    Google Scholar 

  • Di Paolo, Ezequiel A., Jason Noble, and Seth Bullock. 2000. Simulation models as opaque thought experiments. In The Seventh International Conference on Artificial Life, ed. Mark A. Bedau, John S. McCaskill, Norman Packard, and Steen Rasmussen, 497–506. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dreyfus, Hubert L. 1992. What Computers Still Can’t Do: A Critique of Artificial Reason. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • El Skaf, Rawad and Cyrille Imbert. 2013. Unfolding in the empirical sciences: experiments, thought experiments and computer simulations. Synthese 190:3451–3474.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frenkel, Daan. 2012. Simulations: The dark side. Proceedings of the International School of Physics “Enrico Fermi” 184:195–227. doi:10.3254/978-1-61499-278-3-195.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldberg, David. 1991. What Every Computer Scientist Should Know About Floating-Point Arithmetic. ACM Computing Surveys 23 (1): 5–48. doi:10.1145/103162.103163.

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Goldin, Dina, and Peter Wegner. 2005. The Church-Turing Thesis: Breaking the Myth. In New Computational Paradigms. LNCS 3526, ed. Barry Cooper, Benedikt Löwe, and Leen Torenvliet, 152–168. Berlin und Heidelberg: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grim, Patrick, Robert Rosenberger, Adam Rosenfeld, Brian Anderson, and Robb E. Eason. 2013. How simulations fail. Synthese: 190 (12): 2367–2390.

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Hartmann, Stephan. 1996. The World as a Process: Simulations in the Natural and Social Sciences. In Modelling and Simulation in the Social Sciences from the Philosophy of Science Point of View, ed. R. Hegselmann, Ulrich Mueller, and Klaus G. Troitzsch, 77–100. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Hatna, Erez, and Itzhak Benenson. 2012. The Schelling Model of Ethnic Residential Dynamics: Beyond the Integrated - Segregated Dichotomy of Patterns. Journal of Artificial Societies and Social Simulation 15 (1): 6. doi:10.18564/jasss.1873.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hatton, Les, and Andy Roberts. 1994. How accurate is scientific software? IEEE Transactions on Software Engineering. 20 (10): 785–797. doi:10.1109/32.328993.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hofstadter, Douglas H. 1980. Gödel, Escher, Bach: An Eternal Golden Braid. A Metaphoric Fugue on Minds and Machines in the Spirit of Lewis Carrol. Harmondsworth: Penguin Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Honer, Oliver. 2011. Sind wir alle Sophisten? Überzeugen und Wahrheit im verwobenen Spiel von Mythos und Logos. In Tagungsband der Nachwuchstagungen für Junge Philosophie in Darmstadt. Brüche, Brücken, Ambivalenzen (2009), Die Wiederverzauberung der Welt? (2010), ed. Suzana Alpsancar and Kai Denker, 239–264. Marburg: Tectum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horkheimer, Max, and Theodor W. Adorno. 1972. Dialectic of enlightenment. New York: Herder and Herder.

    Google Scholar 

  • Human Brain Project. https://www.humanbrainproject.eu/. Accessed 18 Mar 2016.

  • Humphreys, Paul. 2009. The philosophical novelty of computer simulation methods. Synthese 169 (3): 615–626.

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Kaminski, Andreas, Björn Schembera, Michael Resch, and Uwe Küster. 2016. Simulation als List. In List und Tod. Jahrbuch Technikphilosophie, ed. Alfred Nordmann, Andreas Kaminski, Christoph Hubig, Gerhard Gamm, and Petra Gehring, 93–121. Zürich und Berlin: Diaphanes.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lenhard, Johannes. 2011. Epistemologie der Iteration. Gedankenexperimente und Simulationsexperimente. Deutsche Zeitschrift für Philosophie, 59 (1): 131–145.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Markram, Henry. 2009. A brain in a supercomputer. TED Talk 2009. https://www.ted.com/talks/henry\_markram\_supercomputing\_the\_brain\_s\_secrets. Accessed 28 Apr 2016.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moor, James H. 1978. Three Myths of Computer Science. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 29 (3): 213–222.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morrison, Margaret. 2015. Reconstructing Reality: Models, Mathematics, and Simulations. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Nordmann, Alfred. 2007. If and Then: A Critique of Speculative NanoEthics. NanoEthics 1 (1): 31–46.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pagliery, Jose and Hope King. 2016. Computers will overtake us when they learn to love, says futurist Ray Kurzweil. CNN Money, March 8. http://money.cnn.com/2016/03/08/technology/ray-kurzweil-artificial-intelligence/. Accessed 8 July 2016.

  • Michael Resch, (2013) What’s the Result? - Thoughts of a Center Director on Simulation. In Computer Simulations and the Changing Face of Scientific Experimentation, ed. Juan M. Durán and Eckhart Arnold, 233–246. Newcastle: Cambridge Scholars Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schelling, Thomas C. 1971. Dynamic Models of Segregation. Journal of Mathematical Sociology 1:143–186.

    Article  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Theil, Stefan. 2015. Why the Human Brain Project Went Wrong–and How to Fix It. Scientific American. http://www.scientificamerican.com/article/why-the-human-brain-project-went-wrong-and-how-to-fix-it/. Accessed 29 Apr 2016.

  • Turing, Alan M. 1939. Systems of Logic Based on Ordinals. PhD, diss., Princeton University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Turing, Alan M. 1950. Computing Machinery and Intelligence. Mind LIX s(236): 433–460. doi:10.1093/mind/LIX.236.433.

  • Winsberg, Eric. 2003. Simulated Experiments: Methodology for a Virtual World. Philosophy of Science 70 (1): 105–125. doi:10.1086/367872.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Winsberg, Eric. 2009. A tale of two methods. Synthese 169 (3): 575–592. doi:10.1007/s11229-008-9437-0.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 1997. Philosophical investigations, ed. G. E. M. Anscombe and R. Rhees. Trans. G. E. M. Anscombe, P. M. S. Hacker and Joachim. Schulte. Oxford, UK: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I thank Dr. Andreas Kaminski for encouraging me to do this paper and philosophical advice. I’d also like to thank Dr. Juan Manuel Durán for helpful comments and remarks on the draft. Moreover I want to thank Wanda Spahn for proofreading.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Björn Schembera .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 Springer International Publishing AG

About this paper

Cite this paper

Schembera, B. (2017). Myths of Simulation. In: Resch, M., Kaminski, A., Gehring, P. (eds) The Science and Art of Simulation I . Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-55762-5_5

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics