The ability to thrive in complex social situations is essential for humans. To survive and prosper, it is crucial to understand others’ minds, but it is quite puzzling how the access to others can be—to some extent—direct and not necessarily mediated by conceptual reasoning. Recent progress in cognitive and behavioral neuroscience has considerably modified the traditional view of the functional role of the cortical motor system, furnishing a potential answer to such an enigmatic point. Thus, motor areas not only control the elementary physical features of movement (e.g., force, direction, and amplitude), but can also play a role in more complex abilities that contribute to the management of human behaviors (Fig. 1.1). For the sake of simplicity and in accord with recent theoretical models (Casartelli & Molteni, 2014; Gallese, 2007; Sinigaglia & Rizzolatti, 2011), we use the term “motor cognition” to refer to the idea that the cortical motor system can play roles in both (i) understanding and (ii) shaping human behavior. Notably, we focus, respectively, on the functional roles of cortical motor areas in social cognition (i.e., motor action/intention understanding; Fig. 1.2a) and in the establishment of automatized/compulsive behaviors (Fig. 1.2b).

Fig. 1
figure 1

The term “motor cognition” (1.1) is used when referring to the role of motor areas in understanding (1.2a) and shaping (1.2b) behaviors. The clinical implications for autism spectrum disorder (1.3a) and drug addiction (1.3b) are considered

From a clinical perspective, these different aspects of motor cognition represent a challenge in several domains. A growing number of neurophysiological, neuroimaging, and behavioral studies support the idea that we can have direct, pre-cognitive, and motor understanding of others’ behavior. In turn, impairments or anomalies in this motor action/intention understanding may help explain socio-communicative difficulties in individuals with autism spectrum disorder (ASD) (Fig. 1.3a). Interestingly, the functional properties of motor cognition mechanisms may also be relevant for automatized/compulsive behaviors in the most severe phase of drug addiction. This innovative “motor approach” to drug-seeking and drug-taking behavior may promote new perspectives for therapeutic intervention that can bridge the gap—at least speculatively—between a basic neuroscience approach concerning the motor system and clinical implications in drug addiction (Fig. 1.3b).

In this work, we first present a brief overview of the literature on motor cognition underlying the way in which this “motor” perspective provides innovative insights into understanding and shaping (one’s own and others’) behaviors. Then, we briefly consider the case of ASD, in which anomalies/impairments of neural mechanisms underlying motor action/intention understanding have been linked to socio-communicative difficulties. Finally, we focus on drug addiction by considering the potential role of motor cognition mechanisms in shaping automatized/compulsive behaviors in addicts.

Motor cognition: to understand and to shape behaviors in a motor way

Since pioneering studies on nonhuman primates (Call & Tomasello, 2008; Premack &, Woodruff 1978), it has been hypothesized that social interactions in humans are grounded on the ability to attribute propositional attitudes such as beliefs and desires to others. For decades, most authors have considered the notion of theory of mind (ToM) or mindreading the predominant—or even the exclusive—way to access others’ minds (Baron-Cohen, 1995; Baron-Cohen, Leslie, & Frith, 1985; Boucher, 2012; Leslie, Friedman, & German, 2004). However, the putative neural correlates of the so-called “mentalizing system” remain controversial in the literature (Fishman, Keown, Lincoln, Pineda, & Muller, 2014; Mainieri, Heim, Straube, Binkofski, & Kircher, 2013; Mitchell, 2008; for a meta-analysis, see Schurz, Radua, Aichhorn, Richlan, & Perner, 2014). Plausibly, these controversies may be due to the ambiguities of defining in operational terms the notion of ToM, and to the misleading idea that ToM is a unitary process (Bloom & German, 2000; Schaafsma, Pfaff, Spunt, & Adolphs, 2015). To overcome the idea that social cognition involves “social metacognition” exclusively (Gallese, 2007), a new approach has been proposed: a multilevel action understanding model that claims that we can understand others’ actions through different, non-mutually exclusive, and non-competitive ways (Casartelli & Molteni, 2014; de Waal & Ferrari, 2010). Thus, not only metacognitive, inferential, and propositional processes (i.e., high-level social cognition) can support others’ understanding, but pre-cognitive, “direct”, and “motor” access to others is also possible (i.e., motor social cognition or—more simply—motor cognition; Gallese, 2007; Rizzolatti & Sinigaglia, 2010) (Fig. 2). Even if it goes beyond the aims of this article, a further and more basic level of social cognition can be drawn—that is, primary social cognition (Jessen & Grossmann, 2014; Whalen et al., 2004). This level concerns the pre-cognitive and pre-motor understanding of elementary social information that is processed by—for example—visual and auditory perceptual processes or attentional mechanisms (for recent reviews, see Peelle & Sommers, 2015; Petersen & Posner, 2012; Vuilleumier, 2015). For example, biological motion processing is an emblematic hallmark of primary social cognition. For our ancestors it was crucial to promptly distinguish between the movement of a living organism (e.g., a potential prey or predator) and a nonbiological movement (e.g., a falling branch). Today, biological motion perception continues to be important for successful daily-life activities, social behavior, and nonverbal communication (Pavlova, 2012). For these reasons, the brain has a highly conserved predisposition to detect biological motion. This is also an early ability ontogenetically speaking, given that preference in recognizing biological motion has been reported in newborns as young as 2 days old (Simion, Regolin, & Bulf, 2008).

Fig. 2
figure 2

Different, noncompetitive and non-mutually-exclusive levels of social cognition (the gray boxes and color lines are the parts specifically considered in this study)

A growing number of studies support the notion that motor cognition is a critical aspect of understanding others. Indeed, the idea that the purposiveness of action can be explained in pre-cognitive, direct, and motor terms has been supported by single-neuron studies in nonhuman primates (Bonini et al., 2010; Fogassi et al., 2005), as well as by neurophysiological (Berchio et al., 2014; Natale et al., 2014), neuroimaging (Buccino et al., 2004; Gazzola & Keysers, 2009; Iacoboni et al., 2005), and behavioral (Bello et al., 2014; Fabbri-Destro, Cattaneo, Boria, & Rizzolatti, 2009) studies in humans (for theoretical perspectives, see Butterfill & Sinigaglia, 2014; Sinigaglia, 2013; for reviews, see Ferrari, Bonini, & Fogassi, 2009; Kilner & Lemon, 2013; Rizzolatti, Cattaneo, Fabbri-Destro, & Rozzi, 2014). Thus, during basic social interactions we do not always need high-level propositional processes to understand others’ behaviors: If your friend takes an espresso holding the handle, you directly know that he or she is going to drink it, whereas if he or she takes it grasping the body of the cup, you directly understand that he or she is passing the cup to you. Motor cues (i.e., the type of grasping) are crucial signs that guide our interaction with others, given that they are immediate and pre-cognitive cues. It has been hypothesized that the ability of the motor system to understand others’ actions/intentions may be mediated—at least partially—by the parieto-frontal mirror circuit (which includes the inferior parietal lobule, the ventral premotor cortex [vPM], plus the caudal part of the inferior frontal gyrus; for a review, see Rizzolatti et al., 2014). Mirror neurons (MNs) were originally discovered in the ventral premotor cortex (area F5) ( di Pellegrino, Fadiga, Fogassi, Gallese, & Rizzolatti, 1992; Rizzolatti, Fadiga, Gallese, & Fogassi, 1996) and later found in the inferior parietal lobule (particularly in area PFG) and the anterior intraparietal area (AIP) of the macaque brain (Fogassi et al., 2005; Rizzolatti & Sinigaglia, 2010). They represent the neural substrate of a fundamental mechanism able to transform “external” sensory (e.g., visual or auditory) information into the appropriate “internal” motor representation. Single-neuron recording studies in nonhuman primates have indicated that the parieto-frontal MNs discharge when one performs a specific action and when one observes another individual performing the same action (Bonini et al., 2010; Fogassi et al., 2005). A previous study indicated that the majority of grasping MNs in area F5 discharged irrespective of whether grasping was achieved using the right or the left hand, or a precision, whole-hand, or even oral grip (Rochat et al., 2010; Umiltà et al., 2008). Using “normal pliers” (i.e., opening and then closing the fingers to grasp) and “reverse pliers” (i.e., closing and then opening the fingers to grasp), Umiltà et al. (2008) showed that MNs discharged according to the motor goal (i.e., the meaning, to grasp), regardless of the type of pliers. Intriguingly, MNs in area F5 also discharge when monkeys hear the corresponding action-related sounds (Kohler et al., 2002). Thus, MNs code the meaning of an action (e.g., to break a peanut) independently from whether this action is performed (e.g., the monkey breaks a peanut), heard (e.g., the monkey hears the breaking peanut noise), or seen (e.g., the monkey observes the experimenter breaking a peanut) (Rizzolatti & Sinigaglia, 2010). The fact that some neurons in the cortical motor areas are able to encode the abstract meaning (e.g., to grasp) with such a degree of generality has radically modified the traditional view of the motor system as a mere controller/executor of body displacements. It seems that the motor system also relies—to some extent—upon a “teleological” and “social-oriented” structure. Two recent studies in macaque monkeys further support this view. When someone refrains from doing a specific action, he or she might be requested to “internally” represent what one is not doing. Bonini, Maranesi, Livi, Fogassi, and Rizzolatti (2014b) found that the neural pattern underlying the representation of unperformed actions partially reflects the one associated with overtly executed or observed actions. More simply, some F5 grasping neurons discharged both when the monkey grasps an object (“action” condition) and when it refrains from doing this (“inaction” condition) ( Bonini et al., 2014b). Furthermore, Caggiano et al. (2012) showed that the visual response of (a part of) F5 MNs is modulated by the value that the monkey associates with the grasped object. These findings clearly indicate that F5 MNs are not “neutral” to context, showing a preference for specific (more rewarding) objects.

Compelling neurophysiological and brain-imaging experiments also provide indirect evidence for the presence of similar motor understanding mechanisms in humans (Berchio et al., 2014; Cattaneo et al., 2007; Cattaneo, Sandrini, & Schwarzbach, 2010; Gazzola et al., 2007; Iacoboni et al., 2005; McGarry, Russo, Schalles, & Pineda, 2012; Ortigue, Sinigaglia, Rizzolatti, & Grafton, 2010; Peeters et al., 2009; Senna, Bolognini, & Maravita, 2014; Théoret et al., 2005; for a review, see Rizzolatti et al., 2014). Taken together, these data suggest that also in humans the cortical motor system does not exclusively encode the kinematics of actions but also—and more intriguingly—its meaning. From an evolutionary perspective, the importance of these mechanisms for social life is impressive. The ontogeny of motor action/intention understanding, and more generally the ontogeny of motor cognition in humans, is a fascinating but still controversial issue. A number of studies support a predisposition of the motor system toward the processing of socially relevant information, even before birth (Castiello et al., 2010; Zoia et al., 2007). Recently, two different views have been compared: The so-called “genetic account” suggests that heritable genetic factors and predisposition explain the “mirrorness” of MNs; on the other hand, the “associative account” supports the major role of sensorimotor experience (R. Cook, Bird, Catmur, Press, & Heyes, 2014). Even if these views have sometimes been described as mutually exclusive, a less rigid “epigenetic approach” that considers the sensorimotor learning phenomena to be related to individual characteristics and context seems more convincing (Ferrari, Tramacere, Simpson, & Iriki, 2013; Kilner & Lemon, 2013). Thus, the presence of extremely early, or even innate, mechanisms that are able to encode basic forms of others’ direct/motor recognition does not exclude the possibility that learning processes based on sensorimotor experiences may occur.

The hypothesis that sensorimotor learning may assume a crucial role in the motor system’s ability to understand (or to resonate to; see the notion of “motor resonance” in Gallese, Gernsbacher, Heyes, Hickok, & Iacoboni, 2011) others’ actions is supported by a number of experimental studies. Our motor skills significantly affect the way in which we perceive others’ actions; the observation of others’ actions can activate one’s own motor representations (i.e., “action observation–action execution” matching) only if the observer shares the actor’s motor repertoire. Interestingly, such ability is a gradual acquisition and can be modulated by practice, as has been suggested by studies on professional athletes (Aglioti, Cesari, Romani, & Urgesi, 2008; Lahav, Saltzman, & Schlaug, 2007; Tomeo, Cesari, Aglioti, & Urgesi, 2013). Furthermore, recent studies have shown that when we observe someone else acting on an object and we already have first-person experience of this action, our own motor representation of the observed action leads us to implement a goal-specific eye movement program identical to that of the actor (Ambrosini, Costantini, & Sinigaglia, 2011; Ambrosini et al., 2013; Falck-Ytter, Gredeback, & von Hofsten, 2006). Interestingly, the ventral premotor cortex—a region putatively included in the parieto-frontal mirror network—seems to play a crucial role in this ability (Costantini, Ambrosini, Cardellicchio, & Sinigaglia, 2013). In an elegant experiment, 14- to 16-month-old infants observed action video during EEG recording. Stronger beta- and mu-desynchronizations (the mu rhythm is a rhythm belonging to the alpha frequency band considered an electrophysiological marker of the mirror mechanism in humans) were found for observation of crawling compared to walking videos. The size of this effect was strongly related to the infant’s own crawling experience. Considering that 14- to 16-month-old infants have well-established first-person experience with crawling but limited experience with walking, such data support the hypothesis presented above, that motor resonance may be modulated by first-person motor experience (van Elk, van Schie, Hunnius, Vesper, & Bekkering, 2008). A number of behavioral, electrophysiological, and brain-imaging studies converge on this interpretation (Calvo-Merino, Grèzes, Glaser, Passingham, & Haggard, 2006; Cross, Hamilton, & Grafton, 2006; Kanakogi & Itakura, 2011; Turati et al., 2013; for a review, see Hunnius & Bekkering, 2014).

To underline the role of motor cognition in the direct action/intention understanding does not exclude that other levels (i.e., primary social cognition and high-level social cognition) play roles in social functioning. On the contrary, these levels have to be considered as noncompetitive and non-mutually-exclusive (Fig. 2). Motor-based understanding represents a parsimonious way to tackle social interactions, even though it is not the only one.

Motor cognition in ASD: motor anomalies impacting on social functioning

A growing body of studies have focused on different levels of social cognition in ASD. This is not surprising, due to the fact that the capability to promptly understand others is a crucial aspect for survival that emerges early in development, and considering difficulties in social interaction as one of the core features of ASD. With an estimated prevalence of about 1 %, ASD is a serious concern for families, clinicians, and generally for caregivers (Lai, Lombardo, & Baron-Cohen, 2014). To date, clinical diagnosis of ASD is based on behavioral symptoms that include restricted and repetitive patterns of conduct, interests, or activities, and difficulties in (verbal and/or nonverbal) communication/interactions (American Psychiatric Association, 2013; hereafter, DSM 5). Recent changes in diagnostic criteria (Halfon & Kuo, 2013; Maenner et al., 2014) have had a significant impact on both clinical and research practice, encouraging the study of quantitative markers (sometimes defined also as “biomarkers”) that may help support standard behavioral diagnosis. In this context, the term “quantitative” indicates the combination of behavioral/psychophysical (Foss-Feig et al., 2010; Ronconi et al., 2013), neurophysiological (Cattaneo et al., 2007; Vlamings, Jonkman, van Daalen, van der Gaag, & Kemner, 2010), and neuroimaging (Haar, Berman, Behrmann, & Dinstein, 2014; Lynch et al., 2013) markers that—in the last decade—have considerably improved our knowledge on the pathophysiology of ASD (for reviews from different perspectives, see Ecker, Bookheimer, & Murphy, 2015; Kujala, Lepistö, & Näätänen, 2013; Sacrey, Armstrong, Bryson, & Zwaigenbaum, 2014; Simmons et al., 2009). Among other areas, studies of the motor cognition anomalies/impairments in ASD represent an intriguing challenge for future research.Footnote 1 Thus, in this section we consider which, if any, difficulties in social interactions in ASD may be attributed (at least partially) to motor cognition mechanisms.

A time-honored clinical tradition has reported general difficulties in the motor domain in ASD. These difficulties have been related to gross and fine motor coordination (Crippa, Forti, Perego, & Molteni, 2013; Mostofsky et al., 2006), motor control (J. L. Cook, Blakemore, & Press, 2013; Staples & Reid, 2010), and locomotor practice (Nobile et al., 2011; for a review, see Gowen & Hamilton, 2013). These difficulties do not directly impact on social abilities. However, as we described above, specific motor mechanisms may also play a role in social functioning (i.e., motor cognition). An intriguing challenge in the field of ASD would be represented by addressing the possibility that anomalies in motor cognition mechanisms might help explain social interaction difficulties. A recent body of studies furnishes support to such a hypothesis (for a review, see Gallese, Rochat, & Berchio, 2013). The putative activity of the MNs mechanism in typically developing (TD) and ASD individuals was tested using transcranial magnetic stimulation (TMS) and subsequent electromyography (EMG) recordings while subjects observed transitive hand gestures (Enticott et al., 2012; Théoret et al., 2005). Regression analyses showed reduced corticospinal excitability during the observation of transitive hand actions in the ASD group (Enticott et al., 2012). Adapting the experimental design adopted by Fogassi et al. (2005) in humans, Cattaneo et al. (2007) tested with EMG the ability to directly (in a motor way) understand action and intentionality in children with ASD. First, this study aimed to verify whether the chained organization of the parietal and premotor cortex observed in monkeys (Bonini et al., 2010; Fogassi et al., 2005) may have an equivalent in humans. In monkeys, a specific motor act (e.g., grasping) is encoded by F5 and by inferior parietal cortices (area PFG) MNs in markedly different ways (i.e., stronger or weaker activation) when this act is part of actions with different goals (e.g., grasping for eating vs. grasping for placing) (Bonini et al., 2010; Fogassi et al., 2005). Since they are MNs, the encodings are identical for both executed and observed actions. Taken together, these data lead to the hypothesis that this mirror mechanism is able to encode the intentionality of an action (i.e., to eat vs. to place) in a motor way. EMG recording in TD children (Cattaneo et al., 2007), and even in 6-month-old infants (Natale et al., 2014; Turati et al., 2013), supports the existence of a similar motor action/intention understanding mechanism in humans (Rizzolatti & Sinigaglia, 2010). The epistemological valence of such a mechanism for motor cognition is intriguing and exciting (Casartelli & Molteni, 2014; Sinigaglia, 2013). In contrast to TD children, ASD children seem unable to encode the meaning of action (i.e., the motor intentionality, to eat vs. to place) in a motor way (Cattaneo et al., 2007). These findings are also supported by behavioral studies focused on motor-planning abilities (Fabbri-Destro et al., 2009; Forti et al., 2011) and motor intention understanding (Boria et al., 2009; Sparaci, Stefanini, D’Elia, Vicari, & Rizzolatti, 2014). Overall, these studies indicate that ASD children have difficulties encoding the goal of action in a motor way, limiting the children’s abilities to directly understand action/intentionality without any cognitive or high-level mediation. This does not mean that children with ASD do not understand action/intentionality tout court, but it looks as if they cannot profitably take advantage of all levels of social cognition (see Fig. 2) with the same efficiency as TD individuals.

Interestingly, the idea that the motor system may play a significant role in explaining ASD social difficulties is also supported by a recent study by Rochat et al. (2013) that made use of the notion of “vitality forms” (Stern, 2005, 2010), adapting it for experimental contexts (see also Di Cesare, Di Dio, Marchi, & Rizzolatti, 2015; Di Cesare et al., 2014). When one sees an individual grasping a cup, one does not focus exclusively on the type of act (i.e., to grasp) and on its meaning (i.e., to grasp for drinking vs. to grasp for placing). Aside from goal and motor intention, one is also inclined to observe the style of this action (e.g., rude or gentle). Indeed, the style of an action enables one to understand the attitude of the agent—that is, to some extent, the agent’s affective/communicative state (e.g., angry or kind). Thus, the notion of vitality forms refers to the specific action dynamics (“motor prosody”) that allow observers to infer an agent’s state (Casartelli & Molteni, 2014). The capability to express and understand vitality forms represents a critical social skill that—if impaired—may have cascade effects on social functioning. In their experiment, Rochat et al. (2013) demonstrated that the ASD group made significantly more errors in recognizing the style of action (i.e., its vitality form; the “how task”) than the TD group, whereas no statistically significant differences between groups were reported in recognition of the action goal (e.g., to throw a ball vs. to pass a mug; the “what task”). Neuroimaging studies have shown that the dorsocentral sector of the insula is involved in the recognition (Di Cesare et al., 2014), motor planning (imagery), and execution (Di Cesare et al., 2015) of vitality forms. These results are intriguing in light of previous findings on the general functional organization of the insula in both human and nonhuman primates (Jezzini, Caruana, Stoianov, Gallese, & Rizzolatti, 2012; Kurth, Zilles, Fox, Laird, & Eickhoff, 2010). Furthermore, the implication of dorsocentral insula in both the execution and recognition of vitality form raises questions about the mirror properties of this region. This hypothesis would be consistent with functional magnetic resonance imaging (fMRI) findings that have reported similar activations in the anterior section of the insula for the expression and recognition of disgust (Wicker et al., 2003). An additional intriguing point concerns the potential existence of an insulocortical circuit responsible for transmitting vitality form to the cortical circuit controlling motor actions, as was hypothesized by Di Cesare et al. (2014) in line with both nonhuman and human studies (Borra et al., 2008; Borra, Gerbella, Rozzi, & Luppino, 2011; Gerbella, Belmalih, Borra, Rozzi, & Luppino, 2011; Rizzolatti et al., 2014).

Taken together, these data strongly support the view that anomalies in the neural circuits supporting motor cognition may have cascade effects on social functioning, contributing to the explanation of social-communicative difficulties in ASD.

Drug use, drug abuse, and drug dependence: a “motor” approach to drug cue reactivity

A further domain in which the potential role of the cortical motor system has been widely underestimated is the automatized/compulsive behavior in the most severe phases of substance abuse disorders (DSM 5; McLellan, Cacciola, Alterman, Rikoon, & Carise, 2006). More specifically, the role of motor cognition in shaping automatized/compulsive addictive behaviors has been almost neglected in the last decades. Considering that it contributes to approximately 12 % of deaths worldwide (World Health Organization, 2002, 2012), drug addiction clearly represents an enormous socio-medical burden for caregivers, as well as a critical challenge for researchers. The pathophysiology of this disorder must be thoroughly understood in order to improve the efficacy of clinical interventions.

A classical view in the literature claims that the chronic exposure to substances of abuse (e.g., nicotine, cocaine, heroin, etc.) results in a cluster of physiological, psychological, and behavioral symptoms; the addict seeks the substance despite the evident consumption-related problems, and such conduct is reinforcing both in positive and negative ways (Belin, Mar, Dalley, Robbins, & Everitt, 2008; Dalley, Everitt, & Robbins, 2011; for a review, see Everitt & Robbins, 2013). The idea that drug addiction is merely a willpower-related disorder or a way of managing psychological distress (Müller & Schumann, 2011; Pickard, 2011) is not only inappropriate from a neurobiological point of view (Ersche et al., 2013; Naqvi, Rudrauf, Damasio, & Bechara, 2007; Nutt, King, Saulsbury, & Blakemore, 2007; for a review, see Everitt et al., 2008), but is also dangerously misleading for the treatment of drug addicts (Chiu, Lohrenz, & Montague, 2008). Recently, a fierce debate on this point has been reported in the literature (Diana, 2011; Levy, 2013). Without minimizing the obvious role of the degree, amount, and duration of drug exposure and the roles of genetics (Crabbe, Phillips, & Belknap, 2010; Moeller et al., 2013), environmental/developmental factors (Bardo, Neisewander, & Kelly, 2013; Doremus-Fitwater, Varlinskaya, & Spear, 2010), and “gene-to-environment” interactions (Cabib, Orsini, Le Moal, & Piazza, 2000; Caspi & Moffitt, 2006), most recent frameworks basically suggest that individual vulnerabilities to substances of abuse may also be related to underlying neuro biological factors (George, Koob, & Vendruscolo, 2014; Piazza & Deroche-Gamonet, 2013; Volkow, Wang, Fowler, & Tomasi, 2012; for a critical debate, see also the comments in Psychopharmacology, 231(19), 2014). Although the distinction between nonpathological and pathological drug users based on behavioral symptoms is a matter of debate, anecdotal and scientific reports agree on the idea that drug use does not necessarily result in drug abuse and drug dependence; rather it has been hypothesized that drug use is on a continuum that can lead to drug addiction (Koob et al., 2004). A classical model distinguished between three consecutive but independent phases (i.e., one phase is necessary but not sufficient to progress toward the next one) with increasing severity: (i) “social use” of the substance, (ii) “regulated relapse,” and (iii) “compulsive relapse” (Kalivas & O’Brien, 2008). This model focuses on relapse, but it seems compatible with more recent ones that distinguish between (1) recreational, sporadic drug use (see also drug use); (2) intensified, sustained, escalated drug use (see also drug abuse); and (3) loss of control of drug intake and full addiction (see also drug addiction) (for a concise overview of the debate, see George et al., 2014). The least severe phase concerns an occasional use of the substance somehow compatible with daily duties and activities; during this phase, the drug user retains the ability to plan and evaluate long-term outcomes. The second phase is more severe, even if the person is generally able to make socially appropriate choices (e.g., the individual is able to make the “right” choice between helping her or his son with homework or taking the substance); during this phase, the individual begins to experience the need to consume the substance regardless of the social, contextual, and contingent situation. In the most severe phase, the exposure to various environmental cues or salient stressors may induce the person to ignore the recognized priorities (e.g., helping with homework) in order to seek and take the substance. In the literature, this phase is often described as an automatized, compulsive, and almost “deterministic” state resulting in the impossibility to evaluate alternatives (i.e., pathological drug intake, behavioral “crystallization”; Piazza & Deroche-Gamonet, 2013). An alternative (but not diverging) view describes this third and most serious phase as a sort of strong, disabling, pervading, and recurring propensity to “act” for seeking and taking the substance. From a conceptual point of view, this is not a trivial distinction. Thus, an almost “deterministic” model seems to implicate that you do not have any alternative options, whereas the latter description tries to stress that in drug dependence the individual is continuously led to face the choice (i.e., to take or not take the substance), with a gradually impaired decision-making process that leads to the “wrong” choice (i.e., lapse into drug-seeking and drug-taking behavior). This loss of decision-making ability contributes to the high vulnerability to relapse, even after prolonged abstinence (Belin et al., 2008); relapse may be explained both by an increased desire to consume the substance (mediated by sensitized dopaminergic transmission in the accumbens; Evans et al., 2006; Wanat, Willuhn, Clark, & Phillips, 2009) and by a decreased functionality of the prefrontal cortex, which involves an impaired ability to control behaviors (Goldstein et al., 2004; Goldstein & Volkow, 2002, 2011). Obviously, these three phases are clearly separated only from a theoretical point of view; indeed, the transition to addiction is a gradual and shifting (and reversible) phenomenon involving individual neurobiological and environmental vulnerabilities (Fig. 3).

Fig. 3
figure 3

Drug use, drug abuse, and drug dependence: three consecutive but independent phases with increasing severity. Low-order cue reactivity (CR) plays a potential role in drug-seeking and drug-taking behavior (gray boxes and color lines are the parts specifically considered in this study)

A well-characterized non-drug factor associated with addiction is drug “cue reactivity” (CR)—that is, an individual, adaptive response to salient information (or cues) presented in the internal or external environment (Chiamulera, 2005; Drummond, 2000; Niaura et al., 1988). Consistent evidence has shown that salient cues are able to trigger a vast and personalized array of physiological, psychological, and behavioral responses similar to those experienced during substance use (Beaver et al., 2011; Hogarth, Dickinson, & Duka, 2010; Vollstädt-Klein et al., 2011). Drug CR is one of the major factors involved in the relapse into drug-seeking and drug-taking behavior, and therefore it is an important issue for the development of innovative clinical and rehabilitative approaches. In the literature, one of the most debated distinctions in drug CR is the “high-order CR” and “low-order CR” dichotomy (Tiffany, 1990; for a review, see Tiffany & Wray, 2012). The high-order CR phenomenon is mediated by the ventral striatum (i.e., non-automatic, conscious, sequential, and slow phenomena; David et al., 2005), as opposed to the low-order CR phenomenon, mediated by the dorsal striatum (i.e., automatic, non-conscious, parallel, and fast phenomena; McClernon, Kozink, Lutz, & Rose, 2009; for reviews, see Barker & Taylor, 2014; Everitt & Robbins, 2005; Wilson, Sayette, & Fiez, 2004). This view hypothesizes that the progression from use to abuse and then dependence may be characterized as the transition from voluntary to habitual and progressively compulsive drug use. From a neurobiological perspective, such a transition would reflect a dynamic shift in the neural loci of control over behavior (i.e., from the ventral to dorsal striatum, in combination with a progressive decrease in prefrontal cortical control; Everitt & Robbins, 2013; Garavan et al., 2000; Volkow et al., 2006; Vollstädt-Klein et al., 2011). Although the role of motor processes in the neurobiology of addiction has been widely underestimated or even neglected in past decades (Yalachkov, Kaiser, & Naumer, 2010), more recently it has been hypothesized that motor mechanisms play a role in the low-order CR phenomenon (Brody et al., 2002; Kosten et al., 2006; Smolka et al., 2006; Wagner, Dal Cin, Sargent, Kelley, & Heatherton, 2011; Yalachkov, Kaiser, & Naumer, 2009) (see Fig. 3).

To consider addiction as an “all-or-none” condition (i.e., either present or not in a person at a given time) is at odds with most of the current models, which consider addiction as being a continuum (Koob & Le Moal, 1997; Robinson & Berridge, 2003). Data on the modulation of motor circuits in low-order CR (i.e., motor low-order CR) further support this nondichotomy view. A positron emission tomography study revealed a strong positive association between the intensity of craving in a heavy smoker group and the relative metabolism in the superior right sensorimotor cortex (including the precentral and postcentral gyrus) (Brody et al., 2002). An fMRI study by Smolka et al. (2006) showed that higher scores of nicotine dependence were associated with a higher fMRI blood-oxygenation-level dependent (BOLD) response to smoking cues in different regions, including premotor cortex, supplementary motor area, and left primary motor cortex. By using an orientation affordance paradigm (i.e., a stimulus–response compatibility paradigm; see Riggio et al., 2008; Tucker & Ellis, 1998; Vainio, Ellis, & Tucker, 2007), Yalachkov et al. (2009) found that smokers (but not nonsmokers) showed an automatized responsiveness to smoking paraphernalia similar to that for everyday objects (Yalachkov et al., 2009). Furthermore, from a neural point of view, smokers had higher fMRI activations than nonsmokers not only in regions classically known to be involved in addiction (i.e., left ventral and dorsal striatum, dorsolateral prefrontal cortex, insula, uncus, medial frontal gyrus, right posterior subcallosal gyrus, and bilateral parahippocampal gyrus), but also in a second, “motor” network involving bilateral premotor cortex, left superior parietal lobule, and right lateral cerebellum (Yalachkov et al., 2009; for a review, see Yalachkov, Kaiser, & Naumer, 2010). These findings seem to suggest that smoking cues in smokers can automatically activate the neural regions encoding the motor representation of “tool use” skills and action meaning (i.e., areas related to motor cognition mechanisms). Intriguingly, in smokers, behavioral performance correlated both with the individual degree of nicotine dependence and with fMRI cue reactivity in some of the regions that encode motor cognition (Yalachkov et al., 2009). This result seems also to be consistent with other studies (McClernon et al., 2009; Park et al., 2007; Smolka et al., 2006). From this perspective, automatized responses to drug-related cues in drug dependence would also be modulated (i.e., strengthened) by direct, pre-reflexive, non-propositional motor responses. In drug users, drug cues may contribute to triggering drug-seeking/drug-taking behaviors by activating brain networks that encode the corresponding drug-related motor repertoire (Jasinska, Stein, Kaiser, Naumer, & Yalachkov, 2014). In other words, motor cognition mechanisms may play a role in shaping highly compulsive addictive behaviors.Footnote 2

Interestingly, these motor responses are facilitated only when the individual has specific sensorimotor expertise acquired by repetitive activation of similar motor patterns. Smokers are “facilitated” (from both a behavioral and a neural perspective) in using smoking paraphernalia, and this could be a “facilitating factor” for smoking. Put more simply: If you are accustomed to doing it, you will be (from a motor point of view) willing to redo it, and you will be (from a motor point of view) driven to do it again and again. Considering that our brain is able to modulate the neural responses to a specific tool proportionally to the degree of expertise in managing that tool, it is not surprising that—as we outlined above—a nicotine addict responds to smoking paraphernalia as automatically as to everyday objects (Yalachkov et al., 2009). As we previously described, studies on the ontogeny of motor cognition and on professional athletes support this view (Aglioti et al., 2008; Gallese, Rochat, Cossu, & Sinigaglia, 2009; Lahav et al., 2007; Tomeo et al., 2013). In this sense, a tennis ball for a tennis player may be considered like a smoking-related tool for nicotine addicts. More interestingly, with regard to clinical aims, nicotine addicts’ (motor) propensity to activate action schemata related to smoking behavior could—potentially—facilitate relapse in nicotine-seeking and/or nicotine-taking behaviors. Thus, this motor mechanism plays a role in shaping (and reinforcing) behaviors (see also Motor cognition: to understand and to shape behaviors in a motor way above). Like professional athletes in their corresponding sport, nicotine addicts may be “facilitated” in returning to and assuming the substance also by motor circuits that—to some extent—“know” (and, in turn, facilitate) motor behaviors that have been performed repetitively. Plausibly, a similar mechanism may be observed not only for nicotine but also for different abuse substances, even if further experimental data will be necessary to support this hypothesis. Therefore, motor low-order CR—by increasing the force of that strong disabling, pervading, and recurring propensity to seek and take the substance—would contribute to the characterization of the most severe phase of addiction (i.e., drug dependence; “compulsive relapse”, Kalivas & O’Brien, 2008; “loss of control of drug intake and full addiction” in Piazza & Deroche-Gamonet, 2013) (Fig. 3).

An interesting point for further research may concern the modulation of such motor low-order CR; for example, recent works in nonhuman (Caggiano, Fogassi, Rizzolatti, Thier, & Casile, 2009) and human (Costantini, Ambrosini, Tieri, Sinigaglia, & Committeri, 2010) primates has shown that our perception of space is not purely metrical, but is also modulated by our ability/potentiality to act in this space (Bonini, Maranesi, Livi, Fogassi, & Rizzolatti, 2014a; Gallese & Sinigaglia, 2010, 2011). If our motor system is able to perceive the reachability or nonreachability of an object (i.e., using a spatial alignment effect paradigm, when an object is effectively reachable, we have shorter reaction times; Costantini et al., 2010), then we could speculate that this factor may also modulate motor low-order CR. Future research should also focus on the modulation of CR phenomena by multisensory integration (Yalachkov, Kaiser, Görres, Seehaus, & Naumer, 2013); an fMRI study has indicated that both nicotine addicts and nonsmokers show visuo-haptic integration in the left lateral occipital complex for common daily objects, whereas only smokers show it during the presentation of smoking paraphernalia (Yalachkov, Kaiser, Görres, Seehaus, & Naumer, 2012). Taken together, these elements suggest that drug CR is a complex phenomenon that may be significantly modulated by both high-order and low-order mechanisms (Tiffany, 1990). In turn, low-order CR involves not only a dynamic shift in the neural loci of control over behavior (i.e., from the ventral to the dorsal striatum, in combination with a progressive decrease in prefrontal cortical control), but also suggests the possibility that the motor circuits implicated in motor cognition (notably, those involved in shaping behaviors in light of motor expertise) could play a role.

It could be claimed that these studies would not be of relevance for daily clinical practice (for a similar debate, see Maj, 2011). However, a single perspective cannot tackle such a multilayered phenomenon as human behavior, whereas it may be useful to “decompose” (Schaafsma et al., 2015) complexity starting from more basic neurobiological, neurophysiological, and neurocognitive components. Worth noting is that the DSM-5 strategy, driven by recent advances in genetics and neuroscience—in contrast to the descriptive and phenomenological approach of the DSM IV—is consistent with such a view (Regier, Kuhl, & Kupfer, 2013).

Concluding remarks

Motor cognition represents an innovative and promising perspective for speculative studies and clinical research (Fig. 1). Clinically, a deeper investigation of the neural mechanisms mediating motor-based action/intention understanding (Fig. 2) and low-order motor CR (Fig. 3) seems to be a promising way to tackle a range of neurodevelopmental and drug-related disorders. In ASD, early motor cognition anomalies resulting in basic motor-understanding difficulties could be one of the crucial neurocognitive markers for ASD detection (Becchio, Pierno, Mari, Lusher, & Castiello, 2007; Cattaneo et al., 2007; Fabbri-Destro et al., 2009; Parma, Bulgheroni, Tirindelli, & Castiello, 2013; Rochat et al., 2013), and potentially they could be tested even in infancy, before the onset of unequivocal behavioral symptoms (for reviews from non-motor perspectives, see Jones, Gliga, Bedford, Charman, & Johnson, 2014; Keehn, Müller, & Townsend, 2013; Klin, Shultz, & Jones, 2015). Furthermore, considering that ASD is a lifelong condition that usually requires permanent assistance, motor cognition anomalies may assume a pivotal role for setting (early) rehabilitative protocols to improve social functioning (Pineda, Carrasco, Datko, Pillen, & Schalles, 2014; Rogers et al., 2014; Zwaigenbaum, Bryson, & Garon, 2013). Speculatively, the idea that the motor system plays a crucial role not only for controlling the elementary physical features of movement (e.g., force, direction, and amplitude), but also for higher functions (i.e., to understand and to shape behavior; see the introduction), radically changes the way in which we conceive others’ behavior and our own (Gallese, 2007; Sinigaglia, 2013; Sinigaglia & Rizzolatti, 2011). Moreover—even if clinical studies testing (i.e., proving or falsifying) such a hypothesis are necessary—it seems plausible that the plasticity of the cortical motor system may be considered in order to tackle the automatized and compulsive drug-seeking/drug-taking behaviors in substance abuse disorders (Smolka et al., 2006; Wagner et al., 2011; Yalachkov et al., 2009; for a review, see Yalachkov et al., 2010). The transition from use to abuse, and then to addiction, is a critical concept for rehabilitation. Understanding deeply the pathophysiology of this transition may be crucial to addressing drug-taking- and drug-seeking-related problems.

We do not intend to replace the “myth” of “gene talk” (Kendler 2005; Kitcher, 1996) with a new “neuromania” (Legrenzi & Umiltà, 2011) or a “motor system myth” (Keysers, 2015); we clearly understand the risk of overestimating new neuroscience data, both in clinical and in broader domains (Casartelli & Chiamulera, 2013a, b). However, the only way to shed light on multifactorial disorders such as ASD and drug addiction will be the investigation of their multiple factors. Potential implications of the motor system in higher functions such as action/intention understanding and automatized/compulsive behaviors cannot be neglected, even if they have to be attentively considered and interpreted in light of the neurobiological complexity of ASD and drug addiction. Obviously, we cannot neglect that the ultimate purpose of these studies should be oriented to clinical practice and, in a broader sense, to the patient’s care. The motor way described in this article may be an exemplary (speculative, but evidence-based) approach for considering the complexity of neuropsychiatric disorders from different and hopefully useful perspectives. In the future, clinical approaches and therapeutic protocols should attentively consider these findings in order to evaluate their potential clinical impacts in diagnosis and treatment.