Skip to main content
Log in

Respecting foreign peoples: the limits of moral obligations

  • Article
  • Published:
Journal of International Relations and Development Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Recent history clearly confirms John Rawls’ claim that peoples’ fundamental interest in self-respect makes them insist on ‘receiving from other peoples a proper respect and recognition of their equality’. Even before the US president Barack Obama promised numerous nations new relationships based ‘on mutual respect’, many foreign leaders had already begun to insist on being ‘duly respected’ by the United States and other (mostly Western) countries. What is unclear, however, is how far such moral claims actually extend, especially as far as peoples’ ‘trials during their history and … their culture with its accomplishments’ (Rawls) are concerned. When can peoples justifiably complain about ‘inadequate respect’? When does international morality, understood as practical reasoning in the Kantian tradition, command a change in foreign attitudes and behaviour? This article focuses on the range of universal norms that should regulate the allocation of esteem and attention in an increasingly integrated world. It shows that cultural diversity among peoples all but excludes substantive criteria for specifying ‘due respect’, thus leaving mostly formal criteria, such as consistency and reciprocity, for identifying uncontroversial cases of disrespect.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. As Louise Richardson (2006) points out, the experience of humiliation plays a crucial and pervasive role in terrorist motivations. See also Sen et al. (2007: 20–24) and Parekh (2008: 166).

  2. Of course, there is no automatic moral obligation to respect other states’ legal rights. When national governments violate grossly the human rights of their citizens, disregard for a state’s sovereign rights could be compatible with respecting the moral rights of its people (Walzer 1977: Chapter 6) or might even be ‘called for’, as Rawls (1999: § 13.3) claims. Usually, however, violation of a state’s international rights also entails disrespect for its people.

  3. That is, to use Wendt’s (2003: 511) distinction, I shall address problems of thick rather than thin recognition. See also Honneth’s (1996) parallel distinction between social esteem and equal treatment in law, and Taylor’s (1995c: 232) between the politics of difference and the politics of equal recognition.

  4. Rawls’ focus on obligations between peoples (rather than between persons) has drawn a lot of criticism for its alleged neglect of participatory rights within ‘decent hierarchical peoples’ and its indifference to global distributional justice (Beitz 2000; Pogge 2001; Chartier 2004). Yet, it seems quite appropriate for an investigation of international duties concerning status recognition. When debating the relative accomplishments and importance of their nations, persons encounter each other (actually or virtually) as undifferentiated members of organised groups, as Mexicans and Russians, rather than as individuals with unique traits or histories; they are treated primarily as nationals, they identify with their nation (particularly when it appears to have been slighted), and they take pride in its political culture and institutions (Heins 2010). Accordingly, they expect their political representatives to protect the autonomy of their national culture (Tamir 1993) and its international standing (Honneth 2012: 30–31). And they feel more easily offended when foreign officials seem to disregard their nation rather than ‘mere’ private citizens. In short, in these encounters (and particularly in the indirect ones reported by mass media), persons feel and act as members of peoples.

  5. Deliberate insults aim at putting someone down. Their very purpose consists in attacking an actor’s self-respect.

  6. In the American ‘canon debate’ of the early 1990s, most proponents of ‘PC’ argued that all cultures deserve equal respect while their opponents (at least implicitly) claimed a higher status for Western arts, philosophy, and science (Berman 1992). My point here will be that the promotion of respect among peoples actually rules out any efforts to campaign for a universal view as to who deserves what degree of thick recognition. I do not take issue with the view that many peoples (and especially Western ones) should show greater interest in the achievements of other civilisations — far from it.

  7. See the discussions in Bird (2004), Dillon (2007), Hill (1998) and Hudson (1980).

  8. See also Dillon (2007) and Hill (1998). Compared with the prevailing conceptualisations of ‘recognition’, the semantic extension of ‘respect’, as it will be used here, is both narrower and wider: it is narrower in that it is strongly linked to one’s sense of entitlement. Hence, it covers only consideration (we feel) others must show. Recognition — as understood by Honneth (1996) and Taylor (1995c) — goes beyond that point by extending to other, wholly subjective forms of positive evaluation, such as love. It seems self-evident that we always ‘owe’ respect to other humans (Darwall 2006: Chapter 6), whereas sometimes we have greater moral discretion when it comes to recognising other people. On the other hand, the extension of ‘respect’ is broader, as it also covers non-evaluative forms of consideration, which confirm one’s sense of importance and which are so relevant for social status. By including these dimensions, the concept can also be used for explaining conflicts that arise in situations where actors feel ignored, not being taken seriously, or being taken for granted.

  9. The pain associated with experiences of social rejection even seems to have a firm biological basis in the human brain (Eisenberger et al. 2003).

  10. One might object that, before discussing the moral requirements of a respectful order, the international community first needs to agree on a shared concept of respect that includes an agreed list of actor attributes, which must be given adequate consideration. However, for the limited purpose of this article, it must suffice to assume (a) that both human beings and the groups they form care for status (Frank 1985: Chapters 1–2; Wright 1994: Chapter 12), (b) that they want to see it recognised by other groups, and (c) that they base their status claims (in part, at least) on their achievements, virtues, and overall importance. These assumptions do not appear very controversial. In fact, leading scholars concur that sensitivity to disrespect is among the very few emotional dispositions that are universal among humans (Haidt and Joseph 2004: 58). Thus, it is hardly surprising that a very heterogeneous expert group like the Commonwealth Commission on Respect and Understanding (Sen et al. 2007) apparently just took it for granted that human communities everywhere care for respect along such lines. Of course, as it will be pointed out below, there can be great cultural variations with regard to the specific nature of status-relevant achievements or virtues. On intercultural similarities and differences concerning respectful behaviour see Appiah (2005: 265–7) and Shwalb and Shwalb (2006).

  11. Of course, disparaging statements about other peoples might be even more problematic to the extent they also compromise the latter’s ‘soft power’ (Nye) in the eyes of the international audience. This, in turn, could bring about an unfair drawback in contests over scarce resources. However, since it is so difficult to produce clear evidence for such disadvantages, the following discussion will not take up this point.

  12. In fact, for my purpose here, this simplifying assumption hardly stretches reality because domestic sub-groups will mostly see their own interpretation as the ‘authentic’ interpretation of their people’s essence. Hence, Indians will feel equally offended by alleged arrogance towards India, even though they might disagree on what it means to be Indian. Similarly, Shia and Sunnis in Iraq will often feel equally insulted by foreign denigrations of ‘Islam’.

  13. Such a contractualist strategy for identifying moral obligations is required to grant equal respect to all members of a moral community when they deliberate on the contents of universally binding norms (Scanlon 1998: Chapter 5; Darwall 2006: Chapter 2; Forst 2007: 301; Rostbøll 2009). In this vein, former Iranian president Khatami (2005: 76) has called upon UNESCO to promote the search for ‘a set of a priori and comprehensive general axioms’ to guide an equitable dialogue among civilisations. Liberal contractualism thus appears to be the most appropriate epistemic approach as it does not automatically privilege one cultural perspective over any other.

  14. In this section, I will only address recognition for accomplishments or achievements. I shall not discuss explicitly the respect for efforts and virtues because my arguments concerning accomplishments seem to apply to these two aspects just as well.

  15. Taylor is somewhat more ambiguous on that point. Although he seems to subscribe to the norm that we owe all cultures the presumption of equal worth, he insists that there is no right to demand ‘actual judgments of equal worth applied to the customs and creations of these different cultures’ (Taylor 1995c: 253, 308).

  16. Similar disagreements may arise in the proper evaluation of a people’s ‘negative achievements’, such as national fiascos or crimes.

  17. A recent opinion survey reports that three quarters of the Chinese public consider their nation’s culture superior to America’s while one half of the US population claims the exact opposite (Carnegie Endowment for International Peace 2013: 12).

  18. See also (Parekh 2006: 70–72) who underscores Herder’s claim that in light of divergent needs and concepts of happiness each culture can only be understood in its own historic context and thus ought to be judged according to its own standards.

  19. Of course, things get even more complicated once we consider the multicultural composition of many contemporary peoples. As a matter of fact, different cultural groups within a given nation may apply different standards when judging the achievements of another people. Even in this case, each spokesperson should be required to be consistent in her judgements about foreign peoples.

  20. Unawareness of another people’s achievements could also bring about a lop-sided view. However, this error of judgement needs to be distinguished from the application of double standards, for it results from a lack of factual knowledge rather than from unjustified discrimination. This has to be distinguished from deliberate efforts to distort the record of another people. Clearly, the latter are to be considered as disrespectful behaviour.

  21. Thus, Jacques (2009: Chapter 8) and Said (1978) claim that Chinese and Western assertions of cultural superiority are partly based on racial prejudice.

  22. A possible example might be the former European disregard for the aesthetic qualities of Asian temples, inasmuch as this lack of appreciation was based on the notion that buildings constructed by heathens could never match Christian architecture. In a similar vein, Sen (2006: 75–79, 147–8) charges colonial Britons with diminishing Indian achievements in mathematics and public reasoning. On the other hand, complaints about Western disrespect for China’s economic accomplishments seem inappropriate (see ‘Introduction’). As Nobel Prizes are clearly meant to recognise personal scientific accomplishments rather than national economic achievements, the Swedish Academy cannot be accused of applying double standards in this case.

  23. Western disregard for traditional Chinese medical knowledge and Arab mathematics might be a good illustration. On the one hand, lower recognition for these scientific achievements could be justified with the argument that they do not conform to (Western) standards of systematic scientific enquiry. On the other hand, many Chinese discoveries and Arab insights conform to the relevant higher-order standard, insofar as they actually improve the condition of patients or our calculation abilities. Hence, one could argue that these achievements deserve just as much credit as the equally useful Western medical insights, which were brought to light by other epistemic procedures. On Western disrespect for ‘unrigorous’ Arab mathematics see Rashid (1994: App. 1).

  24. In this vein, Galeotti (2010) and Rostbøll (2009) have argued quite convincingly that Danish authorities can hardly be blamed for not interfering with the publication of the Muhammad cartoons, but are to be criticised for their arrogant refusal to listen to complaints from the Muslim community. For a similar view see Lægaard (2010: 115).

  25. Of course, this is not to say that publishing the cartoons was a wise, friendly, or useful act. But that is a different story.

  26. Libya in the 1980s, the Wilhelminian Germany, and the contemporary Venezuela may be good examples.

  27. Sometimes, getting no attention at all and not being talked about in public is also experienced as an implicit rejection of a collective’s lifestyle and values (Raz 1994: Chapters 6). To the extent that this perception is shared by peoples, disrespect for achievements and for social importance may go hand in hand.

  28. Even in the ‘monocultural’ regional systems of past centuries, political representatives often strongly disagreed on the relevant criteria (Luard 1976: Chapter 9; Schweller 1999: 42–48; Lebow 2008).

  29. However, it may be influenced by criteria such as culture or religion, which sometimes can provide legitimate reasons for a special interest in a particular people.

  30. This also follows from the obligation to respect other peoples’ needs.

  31. Unfortunately, this moral obligation may come into conflict with other imperatives, such as the requirement for quick and effective action. Thus, it is hardly surprising that during the Asian crisis of 1997, Indonesians, Koreans, and Thais were deeply offended by the almost dictatorial manner in which small IMF teams imposed dramatic changes on long-standing national economic policies (Higgott 2000).

  32. As Sen (2006: 146) has pointed out, ‘[t]he task of ruling a foreign country is not an easy one when its subjects are seen as equal’. Hence, disregard for a foreign culture comes close to a precondition for imposing imperial domination.

References

  • Ames, Roger T. (1997) ‘Continuing the Conversation on Chinese Human Rights’, Ethics & International Affairs 11 (1): 177–205.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, Benedict (1983) Imagined Communities: Reflections on the Origin and Spread of Nationalism, London; New York: Verso.

    Google Scholar 

  • Appiah, Kwame Anthony (2005) The Ethics of Identity, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Appiah, Kwame Anthony (2007) Cosmopolitanism: Ethics in a World of Strangers, New York: WW Norton & Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Batabyal, Rakesh (2010) ‘India’, in Hakan Altinay, ed., Does Fairness Matter in Global Governance?, 20–22, Washington DC: Brookings Institution.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beitz, Charles R. (1999) Political Theory and International Relations, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beitz, Charles R. (2000) ‘Rawls’s Law of Peoples’, Ethics 110 (4): 669–96.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berman, Paul (1992) Debating PC: The Controversy over Political Correctness on College Campuses, New York: Dell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Binderup, Lars (2007) ‘Global Freedom of Speech’, TRAMES 11 (4): 403–18.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bird, Colin (2004) ‘Status, Identity, and Respect’, Political Theory 32 (2): 207–32.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blum, Lawrence (1998) ‘Recognition, Value, and Equality: A Critique of Charles Taylor’s and Nancy Fraser’s Accounts of Multiculturalism’, Constellations 5 (1): 51–68.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bowden, Brett (2004) ‘The Ideal of Civilisation: Its Origins and Socio-Political Character’, Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 7 (1): 25–50.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bowden, Brett (2005) ‘The Colonial Origins of International Law: European Expansion and the Classical Standard of Civilization’, Journal of the History of International Law 7 (1): 1–23.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brown, Chris (2000) ‘Cultural Diversity and International Political Theory: From the Requirement to “Mutual Respect”?’ Review of International Studies 26 (2): 199–213.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carnegie Endowment for International Peace (2013) U.S.-China Security Perceptions Survey: Findings and Implications, Washington DC: Carnegie Endowment.

  • Chartier, Gary (2004) ‘Peoples or Persons: Revising Rawls on Global Justice’, Boston College International & Comparative Law Review 27 (1): 1–97.

    Google Scholar 

  • Darwall, Stephen L. (1977) ‘Two Kinds of Respect’, Ethics 88 (1): 36–49.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Darwall, Stephen L. (2006) The Second-Person Standpoint: Morality, Respect, and Accountability, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dillon, Robin S. (2007) ‘Respect: A Philosophical Perspective’, Gruppendynamik und Organisationsberatung 38 (2): 201–12.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Druckman, Daniel (1994) ‘Nationalism, Patriotism, and Group Loyalty: A Social Psychological Perspective’, Mershon International Studies Review 38 (1): 43–68.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eisenberger, Naomi I., Matthew D. Lieberman and Kipling D. Williams (2003) ‘Does Rejection Hurt? An fMRI Study of Social Exclusion’, Science 302 (5643): 290–92.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Forst, Rainer (2007) ‘A Critical Theory of Multicultural Toleration’, in Anthony Simon Laden and David Owen, eds., Multiculturalism and Political Theory, 292–311, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frank, Robert H. (1985) Choosing the Right Pond: Human Behavior and the Quest for Status, New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fraser, Nancy and Axel Honneth (2003) Redistribution or Recognition? A Political-Philosophical Exchange, London; New York: Verso.

    Google Scholar 

  • Galeotti, Anna Elisabetta (2010) ‘Multicultural Claims and Equal Respect’, Philosophy & Social Criticism 36 (3–4): 441–50.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gong, Gerrit W. (1984) The Standard of ‘Civilization’ in International Society, Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gries, P. H. (2004) China’s New Nationalism: Pride, Politics, and Diplomacy, Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haidt, Jonathan and Craig Joseph (2004) ‘Intuitive Ethics: How Innately Prepared Intuitions Generate Culturally Variable Virtues’, Daedalus 133 (4): 55–66.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hansen, Randall (2006) ‘The Danish Cartoon Controversy: A Defence of Liberal Freedom’, International Migration 45 (4): 7–16.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heins, Volker (2008) ‘Realizing Honneth: Redistribution, Recognition, and Global Justice’, Journal of Global Ethics 4 (2): 141–53.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heins, Volker (2010) ‘Of Persons and Peoples: Internationalizing the Critical Theory of Recognition’, Contemporary Political Theory 9 (2): 149–70.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heins, Volker (2011) Beyond Friend and Foe: The Politics of Critical Theory, Leiden and Boston, MA: Brill.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Heins, Volker (2012) ‘The Global Politics of Recognition’, in Shane O’Neill and Nicholas H. Smith, eds, Recognition Theory as Social Research: Investigating the Dynamics of Social Conflict, 213–30, Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Higgott, Richard (2000) ‘The International Relations of the Asian Economic Crisis: A Study in the Politics of Resentment’, in Richard Robison, Mark Beeson, Kanishka Jayasuriya and Hyuk-Rae Kim, eds, Politics and Markets in the Wake of the Asian Crisis, 263–85, London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hill, Thomas E. (1998) ‘Respect for Persons’, in Edward Craig, ed., Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy, London; New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Honneth, Axel (1996) The Struggle for Recognition: The Moral Grammar of Social Conflicts, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Honneth, Axel (2012) ‘Recognition between States: On the Moral Substrate of International Relations’, in Thomas Lindemann and Erik Ringmar, eds, The International Politics of Recognition, 25–38, Boulder: Paradigm Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hudson, Stephen D. (1980) ‘The Nature of Respect’, Social Theory and Practice 6 (1): 69–90.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Huntington, Samuel P. (1996) The Clash of Civilizations and the Remaking of World Order, New York: Simon &Schuster.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hurrell, Andrew (2007) On Global Order: Power, Values, and the Constitution of International Society, New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Inoue, Tatsuo (1999) ‘Liberal Democracy and Asian Orientalism’, in Joanne R. Bauer and Daniel A. Bell, eds, The East Asian Challenge for Human Rights, 27–59, New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jacques, Martin (2009) When China Rules the World: The Rise of the Middle Kingdom and the End of the Western World, London: Allen Lane.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, Immanuel (1788/2002) Critique of Practical Reason. Hackett Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelman, Herbert C. (1997) ‘Nationalism, Patriotism, and National Identity: Social-Psychological Dimensions’, in Daniel Bar-Tal and Ervin Staub, eds, Patriotism in the Lives of Individuals and Nations, 165–89, Chicago: Nelson-Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Khatami, Mohammed (2005) ‘Dialogue among Civilizations and Cultures’, in Akbar Ahmed and Brian Forst, eds, After Terror: Promoting Dialogue among Civilizations, 72–78, Cambridge: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kymlicka, Will (2001) Politics in the Vernacular: Nationalism, Multiculturalism, and Citizenship, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lægaard, Sune (2010) ‘Normative Significance of Transnationalism? The Case of the Danish Cartoons Controversy’, Ethics & Global Politics 3 (2): 101–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lebow, Richard Ned (2008) A Cultural Theory of International Relations, Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lindekilde, Lasse, Per Mouritsen and Ricard Zapata-Barrero (2009) ‘The Muhammad Cartoons Controversy in Comparative Perspective’, Ethnicities 9 (3): 291–313.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lindemann, Thomas (2010) Causes of War: The Struggle for Recognition, Wivenhoe Park: ECPR Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lindemann, Thomas and Erik Ringmar, eds (2012) The International Politics of Recognition, Boulder: Paradigm Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Luard, Evan (1976) Types of International Society, New York: Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Malone, David M. (2011) Does the Elephant Dance: Contemporary Indian Foreign Policy, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Margalit, Avishai (1996) The Decent Society, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Margalit, Avishai and Joseph Raz (1990) ‘National Self-determination’, Journal of Philosophy 87 (9): 439–61.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mead, George Herbert (1934) Mind, Self, and Society: From the Standpoint of a Social Behaviorist, Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Miller, Dale T. (2001) ‘Disrespect and the Experience of Injustice’, Annual Review of Psychology 52 (1): 527–53.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mishra, Pankaj (2012) From the Ruins of Empire: The Revolt against the West and the Remaking of Asia, London: Allen Lane.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moisi, Dominique (2009) The Geopolitics of Emotion: How Cultures of Fear, Humiliation, and Hope are Reshaping the World, New York: Doubleday Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nayar, Balder Raj and Thazha V. Paul (2004) India in the World Order: Searching for Major-Power Status, Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Olesen, Thomas (2009) ‘The Muhammad Cartoons Conflict and Transnational Activism’, Ethnicities 9 (3): 409–26.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Onuma, Yasuaki (1999) ‘Toward an Intercivilizational Approach to Human Rights’, in Joanne R. Bauer and Daniel A. Bell, eds, The East Asian Challenge for Human Rights, 103–23, New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Organisation of the Islamic Conference (1990) Cairo Declaration of Human Rights in Islam. Organisation of the Islamic Conference, http://www.oic-oci.org/english/article/human.htm (accessed July 6, 2014).

  • Parekh, Bhikhu C. (2006) Rethinking Multiculturalism: Cultural Diversity and Political Theory, 2nd edn. Houndmills: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parekh, Bhikhu C. (2008) A New Politics of Identity: Political Principles for an Interdependent World, Houndmills: Palgrave.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pew Global Attitudes Project (2006) The Great Divide: How Westerners and Muslims View Each Other. Pew Global Attitudes Project, http://www.pewglobal.org/files/pdf/253.pdf (accessed July 6, 2014).

  • Pogge, Thomas W. (2001) ‘Rawls on International Justice’, Philosophical Quarterly 51 (203): 246–53.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pogge, Thomas (2007) Freedom from Poverty as a Human Right: Who Owes What to the Very Poor? New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pogge, Thomas (2008) World Poverty and Human Rights: Cosmopolitan Responsibilities and Reforms, Cambridge: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Qingguo, Jia (2005) ‘Disrespect and Distrust: The External Origins of Contemporary Chinese Nationalism’, Journal of Contemporary China 14 (42): 11–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rashid, Rushdi (1994) The Development of Arabic Mathematics: Between Arithmetic and Algebra, Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, John (1971) A Theory of Justice, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, John (1999) The Law of Peoples, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raz, Joseph (1994) Ethics in the Public Domain: Essays in the Morality of Law and Politics, Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Richardson, Louise (2006) What Terrorists Want: Understanding the Enemy, Containing the Threat, New York: Random House.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ross, Lee (1977) ‘The Intuitive Psychologist and His Shortcomings: Distortions in the Attribution Process’, in Leonard Berkowitz, ed., Advances in Experimental Social Psychology, 173–220, New York: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rostbøll, Christian F. (2009) ‘Autonomy, Respect, and Arrogance in the Danish Cartoon Controversy’, Political Theory 37 (5): 623–48.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Said, Edward W. (1978) Orientalism: Western Conceptions of the Orient, New York: Pantheon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Said, Edward W. (1994) Culture and Imperialism, London: Vintage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scanlon, Thomas (1998) What we Owe to Each Other, Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schweller, Randall L. (1999) ‘Realism and the Present Great Power System: Growth and Positional Conflict over Scarce Resources’, in Ethan B. Kapstein and Michael Mastanduno, eds, Unipolar Politics: Realism and State Strategies after the Cold War, 28–67, New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sen, Amartya K. (2006) The Argumentative Indian: Writings on Indian History, Culture and Identity, New York: Picador.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sen, Amartya K., John Alderdice, Kwame Anthony Appiah, Adrienne Clarkson, Noeleen Heyzer, Kamal Hossain, Elaine Sihoatani Howard, Wangari Muta Maathai, Ralston Nettleford, Joan Rwabyomere and Lucy Turnbull (2007) Civil Paths to Peace, London: Commonwealth Secretariat.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shambaugh, David (2013) China Goes Global: The Partial Power, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shwalb, David W. and Barbara J. Shwalb, eds, (2006) ‘Respect and Disrespect: Cultural and Developmental Origins’, in New Directions for Child and Adolescent Development, San Francisco: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Singer, Peter (2004) One World: The Ethics of Globalization, New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, Eliot R. and Diane M. Mackie (2008) ‘Intergroup Emotions’, in Michael Lewis, ed., Handbook of Emotions, 428–39, New York: Guilford Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tajfel, Henry and John C. Turner (1979) ‘An Integrative Theory of Intergroup Conflict’, in William G. Austin and Stephen Worchel, eds, The Social Psychology of Intergroup Relations, 33–47, Monterey, CA: Brooks/Cole.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tamir, Yael (1993) Liberal Nationalism, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, Charles, ed. (1995a) ‘Comparison, History, Truth’, in Philosophical Arguments, 146–64, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, Charles (1995b) Philosophical Arguments, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, Charles, ed. (1995c) ‘The Politics of Recognition’, in Philosophical Arguments, 225–56, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, Charles (2002) ‘Understanding the Other: A Gadamerian View on Conceptual Schemes’, in Jeff Malpas, Ulrich Arnswald and Jens Kertscher, eds, Gadamer’s Century: Essays in Honor of Hans-Georg Gadamer, 279–97, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tully, James (2004) ‘Recognition and Dialogue: The Emergence of a New Field’, Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 7 (3): 84–106.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Walzer, Michael (1977) Just and Unjust Wars: A Moral Argument with Historical Illustrations, New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walzer, Michael (1990) ‘Nation and Universe’, in Grethe B. Peterson, ed., The Tanner Lectures on Human Values, 508–56, Salt Lake City: University of Utah Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weber, Max (1968) Economy and Society, New York: Bedminster.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wendt, Alexander (2003) ‘Why a World State is Inevitable’, European Journal of International Relations 9 (4): 491–542.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wolf, Reinhard (2011) ‘Respect and Disrespect in International Politics: The Significance of Status Recognition’, International Theory 3 (1): 105–142.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • World Economic Forum (2008) Islam and the West, Geneva: World Economic Forum.

  • Wright, Robert (1994) The Moral Animal, New York: Vintage Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yan, Xuetong (2001) ‘The Rise of China in Chinese Eyes’, Journal of Contemporary China 10 (26): 33–39.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zakaria, Fareed (2008) The Post-American World, New York: Norton.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

The author would like to thank one of the reviewers for the insight that disregarding a people’s international importance is more risky than disrespecting its achievements.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Wolf, R. Respecting foreign peoples: the limits of moral obligations. J Int Relat Dev 19, 1–25 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1057/jird.2014.10

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1057/jird.2014.10

Keywords

Navigation