Skip to main content
Log in

Reduced normal forms are not extensive forms

  • Research Article
  • Published:
Economic Theory Bulletin Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Fundamental results in the theory of extensive form games have singled out the reduced normal form as the key representation of a game in terms of strategic equivalence. In a precise sense, the reduced normal form contains all strategically relevant information. This note shows that a difficulty with the concept has been overlooked so far: given a reduced normal form alone, it may be impossible to reconstruct the game’s extensive form representation.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. This is especially important for research programs adopting the position that implicit or self-referential equilibrium concepts should be formalized in a framework which clearly specifies the details, order, and dependence of the possible actions and interactions of all involved agents. This is because the latter necessarily results in an extensive form game, which may in principle be susceptible to inessential transformations. An example of such a research program is given by Glycopantis et al. (2001, 2003, 2005, 2009). This also extends to the Nash program (Nash 1953) about giving non-cooperative foundations to cooperative games, because those often lead to extensive form games. A case in point are bargaining games where the extensive form explicitly specifies the bargaining protocol (e.g., Rubinstein 1982; Britz et al. 2010; Glycopantis 2020).

  2. Many of the stronger set-valued refinement concepts always contain a proper equilibrium, e.g., M-stable sets (Mertens 1989, 1991) or equilibrium components with non-zero index (Ritzberger 1994). As far as these sets are contained in connected components of Nash equilibria, they, therefore, guarantee that the probability distribution on plays associated with the solution set generically satisfies backwards induction, since for generic extensive form games the probability distributions on plays are constant across every connected component of Nash equilibria (see Kreps and Wilson 1982).

  3. This concept is slightly weaker than its preference-dependent analogue, precisely because for the latter coincidental payoff ties can render two strategies equivalent.

  4. Such a preference-free extensive form representation amounts to insisting on robustness of the players’ preference ordering over plays against (sufficiently small) payoff perturbations.

  5. For instance, a generic cell-based payoff perturbation of the reduced normal form game can only originate from a trivial extensive form game were all players play simultaneously, while a perturbation of the preferences defined on plays leaves the link between the original extensive form game and its reduced normal form unaffected.

  6. This at least applies if all plays end after finitely many moves. An infinitely repeated game cast in extensive form provides an example of a game tree without terminal nodes. Plays, on the other hand, are still well defined objects. See Alós-Ferrer and Ritzberger (2016).

  7. We assume here non-trivial decisions, where a player active at a node has at least two choices. Some formalisms allow for trivial decision where one player has one and only one choice. Allowing for those does not change the argument.

  8. We are grateful to a referee for inspiring this clarification.

References

  • Alós-Ferrer, C., Ritzberger, K.: The Theory of Extensive Form Games, Monographs of the Game Theory Society. Springer, Berlin (2016)

    Google Scholar 

  • Basu, K., Weibull, J.W.: Strategy subsets closed under rational behavior. Econ. Lett. 36, 141–146 (1991)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Battigalli, P., Leonetti, P., Maccheroni, F.: Behavioral equivalence of extensive game structures. Games Econ. Behav. 121, 533–547 (2020)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bernheim, D.B.: Rationalizable strategic behavior. Econometrica 52, 1007–1028 (1984)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Britz, V., Herings, P.J.J., Predtetchinski, A.: Non-cooperative support for the asymmetric nash bargaining solution. J. Econ. Theory 145, 1951–1967 (2010)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Elmes, S., Reny, P.J.: On the strategic equivalence of extensive form games. J. Econ. Theory 62, 1–23 (1994)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Glycopantis, D.: Two-person bargaining with lexicographic preferences. Econ. Theory Bull. 8, 13–23 (2020)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Glycopantis, D., Muir, A., Yannelis, N.C.: An extensive form interpretation of the private core. Econ. Theory 18, 293–319 (2001)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Glycopantis, D., Muir, A., Yannelis, N.C.: On extensive form implementation of contracts in differential information economies. Econ. Theory 21, 495–526 (2003)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Glycopantis, D., Muir, A., Yannelis, N.C.: Non-implementation of rational expectations as a perfect Bayesian equilibrium. Econ. Theory 26, 765–791 (2005)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Glycopantis, D., Muir, A., Yannelis, N.C.: On non-revealing rational expectations equilibrium. Econ. Theory 38, 351–369 (2009)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hillas, J.: On the definition of the strategic stability of equilibria. Econometrica 58, 1365–1390 (1990)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kohlberg, E., Mertens, J.F.: On the strategic stability of equilibria. Econometrica 54(5), 1003–1037 (1986)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kreps, D., Wilson, R.: Sequential equilibria. Econometrica 50, 863–894 (1982)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mailath, G.J., Samuelson, L.S., Swinkels, J.S.: Extensive form reasoning in normal form games. Econometrica 61(2), 273–302 (1993)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mertens, J.F.: Stable equilibria—a reformulation, part I: definition and basic properties. Math. Oper. Res. 14, 575–624 (1989)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mertens, J.F.: Stable equilibria—a reformulation, part II: discussion of the definition and further results. Math. Oper. Res. 16, 694–753 (1991)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Myerson, R.B.: Refinements of the nash equilibrium concept. Int. J. Game Theory 7(2), 73–80 (1978)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Myerson, R.B., Weibull, J.: Tenable strategy blocks and settled equilibria. Econometrica 83(3), 943–976 (2015)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nash, J.F.: Equilibrium points in N-person games. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. 36, 48–49 (1950)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nash, J.F.: Non-cooperative games. Ann. Math. 54, 286–295 (1951)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nash, J.F.: Two person cooperative games. Econometrica 21, 128–140 (1953)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pearce, D.G.: Rationalizable strategic behavior and the problem of perfection. Econometrica 52, 1029–1050 (1984)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Perea, A.: Rationality in extensive form games, theory and decision library, series C, vol. 29. Kluwer Academic Publishers, Boston (2001)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ritzberger, K.: The theory of normal form games from the differentiable viewpoint. Int. J. Game Theory 23, 201–236 (1994)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ritzberger, K.: Foundations of non-cooperative game theory. Oxford University Press, Oxford (2002)

    Google Scholar 

  • Rubinstein, A.: Perfect equilibrium in a bargaining model. Econometrica 50, 97–109 (1982)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Selten, R.: Spieltheoretische Behandlung eines Oligopolmodells mit Nachfrageträgheit. Zeitschrift für die gesamte Staatswissenschaft 121, 301–324 and 667–689 (1965)

    Google Scholar 

  • Selten, R.: Reexamination of the perfectness concept for equilibrium points in extensive games. Int. J. Game Theory 4, 25–55 (1975)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, F.B.: Equivalence of games in extensive form. RAND Res. Memo. 759 (1952)

  • van Damme, E.: A relation between perfect equilibria in extensive form games and proper equilibria in normal form games. Int. J. Game Theory 13, 1–13 (1984)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vermeulen, A.J., Jansen, M.J.M.: The reduced form of a game. Eur. J. Oper. Res. 106(1), 204–211 (1998)

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

We thank two anonymous reviewers for helpful comments.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Carlos Alós-Ferrer.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Alós-Ferrer, C., Ritzberger, K. Reduced normal forms are not extensive forms. Econ Theory Bull 8, 281–288 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s40505-020-00183-8

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s40505-020-00183-8

Keywords

JEL Classification

Navigation