Skip to main content
Log in

A Pluralist Approach to Extension: The Role of Materiality in Scientific Practice for the Reference of Natural Kind Terms

  • Thematic Issue Article: Natural Kinds: New Dawn?
  • Published:
Biological Theory Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This article argues for a different outlook on the concept of extension, especially for the reference of general terms in scientific practice. Scientific realist interpretations of the two predominant theories of meaning, namely Descriptivism and Causal Theory, contend that a stable cluster of descriptions or an initial baptism fixes the extension of a general term such as a natural kind term. This view in which the meaning of general terms is presented as monosemantic and the referents as stable, homogeneous, and unchangeable, however, does not reflect the various practices involved in the investigation of research materials and the related application of general terms in scientific practice. By drawing on the taxonomic diversity, particularly of structure-based classifications in chemical databases, this article illustrates the limited utility of such a concept of extension. Research materials often exhibit a plurality of material dimensions that, within different research contexts, allow for various and often equally significant taxonomic demarcations. In light of this, the extension of a general term cannot be uniquely determined by a supposedly independent nature of the referent but is relative to the model context under which the materials are investigated. This significance and plurality of the model context, I claim, needs to be mirrored in an account of meaning that is supposed to reflect scientific reality. On this account, the aim of this article is to present an alternative perspective on the concept of extension to accommodate the diverse material practices that determine the application of general terms in science.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. An anonymous referee suggested considering Causal Descriptivism in this criticism. Causal Descriptivism, I believe, will face the same problem for the concept of extension that I criticize in the other two accounts if it is rigidly conceived as unchangeable, homogeneous, and stable.

  2. https://scifinder.cas.org/scifinder/login.jsf?TYPE=33554433&REALMOID=06-b7b15cf0-642b-1005-963a-830c809fff21&GUID=&SMAUTHREASON=0&METHOD=GET&SMAGENTNAME=-SM-VSR14pTQX5XGubkDwkogX2Mmb%2bsNTuTuF7B1Flcl1uUn9xeADa8ECKxgk%2bA2MJVP&TARGET=-SM-http%3a%2f%2fscifinder%2ecas%2eorg%3a443%2fscifinder%2f.

  3. https://www.reaxys.com/info/.

  4. http://www.thieme-chemistry.com/thieme-chemistry/sos/prod/user/index.html.

  5. http://thomsonreuters.com/products_services/science/science_products/a-z/biosis/.

  6. http://www.ebi.ac.uk/chebi/downloadsForward.do; http://biolod.org/database/ria244i/CHEBI_Chemical_entities_of_biological_interest.

  7. Objections to “analgesic” as a natural kind term might be answered with reference to Putnam (1977), for whom “acid” constituted a natural kind term.

  8. Ohloff’s rule (1971) defines ambergris odorants by the presence of a decalin structure, i.e., a bicyclic compound, and the requirement that the atom groups in the positions 2, 4, and 1 (marked by a dotted line opposite 2) be axial

  9. For a more historic analysis of the interaction of different material cultures in the disciplinary development of 18th-century chemistry see Klein and Lefèvre (2007).

  10. Philosophical skepticism to treat odorants as natural kinds is nicely met by fragrance chemists’ desire to classify odors into natural kinds, explicitly using this term with reference to the discussion about classification in the philosophy of science. See Harper et al. (1968).

References

  • Barnes B (1982) On the extensions of concepts and the growth of knowledge. Sociol Rev 30:23–44

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bloor D (2005) Toward a sociology of epistemic things. Perspect Sci 13:285–312

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright N (1999) The dappled world: a study of the boundaries of science. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

  • de Vries H (1909) The mutation theory: experiments and observations on the origin of species in the vegetable kingdom. Open Court, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Devitt M (2008) Resurrecting biological essentialism. Philos Sci 75:344–382

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dupré J (1995) The disorder of things: metaphysical foundations of the disunity of science. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Dupré J (2001) In defence of classification. Stud Hist Phil Biol Biomed Sci 32(2):203–219

    Google Scholar 

  • Dupré J (2002) Humans and other animals. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Eco U (1979) A theory of semiotics. Indiana University Press, Bloomington

    Google Scholar 

  • Eco U (1983) Semiotics and the philosophy of language. Indiana University Press, Bloomington

    Google Scholar 

  • Ellis BD (2001) Scientific essentialism. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Ellis BD (2002) The philosophy of nature: a guide to the new essentialism. McGill University Press, Queens

    Google Scholar 

  • Ereshefsky M (2001) The poverty of the Linnaean hierarchy: a philosophical study of biological taxonomy. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Ereshefsky M (2007a) Species, taxonomy, and systematics. In: Gabbav DM, Thaggard P, Woods J (eds) Philosophy of biology. Elsevier, Amsterdam, pp 403–428

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Ereshefsky M (2007b) Foundational issues concerning taxa and taxon names. Syst Biol 56:295–301

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feyerabend PK (1962) Explanation, reduction, and empiricism. In: Feigl H, Maxwell G (eds) Scientific explanation, space, and time. University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis, pp 28–97

    Google Scholar 

  • Giere RN (2006) Scientific Perspectivism. Science and Its Conceptual Foundations Series. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

  • Hacking I (1983) Representing and intervening: introductory topics in the philosophy of natural science. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Harper R, Bate-Smith EC, Land DG (1968) Odor description and odor classification: a multidisciplinary examination. Churchill, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Hastings J, Magka D, Batchelor C, Duan L, Stevens R, Ennis M, Steinbeck C (2012) Structrue-based classification and ontology in chemistry. J Cheminform 4(8). doi:10.1186/1758-2946-4-8

  • Hjelmslev L (1961) Prolegomena to a theory of language. University of Wisconsin Press, Madison

    Google Scholar 

  • Hull DL (1965) The effect of essentialism on taxonomy—two thousand years of stasis (I). Brit J Philos Sci 15:314–326

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hull DL (1990) Science as a process: an evolutionary account of the social and conceptual development of science. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher P (1984) Species. Philos Sci 51:308–333

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher P (1993) The advancement of science. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Klein U, Lefèvre W (2007) Materials in eighteenth-century science: a historical ontology. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Kripke S (1980) Naming and necessity. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn TS (1962) The structure of scientific revolutions. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Ladyman J (2009) Structural realism versus standard scientific realism: the case of phlogiston and dephlogisticated air. Synthese 180:87–101

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • LaPorte J (2004) Natural kinds and conceptual change. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Morgan M, Morrison M (1999) Models As mediators: perspectives on natural and social science. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Needham P (2002) The discovery that water is H2O. Int Stud Philos Sci 16:205–226

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nersessian N (1984) Faraday to Einstein: constructing meaning in scientific theories. Martinus Nijhoff Publishers, Dordrecht

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ohloff G (1971) Relationship between odor sensation and stereochemistry of decalin ring compounds. In: Ohloff G, Thomas AF (eds) Gustation and olfaction. Academic Press, New York, pp 118–183

    Google Scholar 

  • Ohloff G, Pickenhagen W, Kraft P (2011) Scent and chemistry: the molecular world of odors. Wiley-VCH, Zurich

    Google Scholar 

  • Psillos S (2012) Causal descriptivism and the reference of theoretical terms. In: Raftopoulos A, Machamer P (eds) Perception, realism, and the problem of reference. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 212–238

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Putnam H (1975) The meaning of “meaning”. Minnesota Studies in the philosophy of science. Lang Mind Knowl 7:131–193

  • Putnam H (1977) Is semantics possible? In: Schwartz P (ed) Naming, necessity and natural kinds. Cornell University Press, Ithaca, NY, pp 102–118

    Google Scholar 

  • Radder H (ed) (2003) The philosophy of scientific experimentation. Pittsburgh University Press, Pittsburgh

    Google Scholar 

  • Rheinberger H-J (1997) Toward a history of epistemic things: synthesizing proteins in the test tube. Stanford University Press, Stanford

    Google Scholar 

  • Rheinberger H-J (2005) A reply to David Bloor: Toward a sociology of epistemic things. Perspect Sci 13:406–410

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Riggs PJ (1996) Natural kinds, laws of nature and scientific methodology. Kluwer, Dordrecht

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Searle JR (1958) Proper names. Mind 67:166–173

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Searle JR (1983) Intentionality: an essay in the philosophy of mind. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Temmerman R (2000) Towards new ways of terminology description: the sociocognitive approach. Benjamins, Amsterdam

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Fraassen B (1980) The scientific image. Oxford, University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Ann-Sophie Barwich.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Barwich, AS. A Pluralist Approach to Extension: The Role of Materiality in Scientific Practice for the Reference of Natural Kind Terms. Biol Theory 7, 100–108 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s13752-012-0083-x

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s13752-012-0083-x

Keywords

Navigation