Skip to main content
Log in

Generalized Darwinism and Evolutionary Economics: From Ontology to Theory

  • Thematic Issue Article: How Evolutionary is Evolutionary Economics?
  • Published:
Biological Theory Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Despite growing interest in evolutionary economics since the 1980s, a unified theoretical approach has so far been lacking. Methodological and ontological discussions within evolutionary economics have attempted to understand and help rectify this failure, but have revealed in turn further differences of perspective. One aim of this article is to show how different approaches relate to different levels of abstraction. A second purpose is to show that generalized Darwinism is some way from the most abstract level, and illustrates how it may be used to move towards more specific theoretical applications. Nevertheless, there is a long way to go before these become more evident.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. This essay makes use of some material from Hodgson and Knudsen (2010a, b).

  2. At an even higher level of abstraction, evolutionary approaches become indistinguishable–they can be described as processes of adaptive change involving systematic change in the distribution of some population property.

  3. Witt (2004, p. 131) also stresses the “continuity hypothesis” according to which natural evolution has “shaped the ground, and still defines the constraints, for man-made, or cultural, evolution.” But this leaves open the question of how severe those constraints are. In such general terms it would find few critics.

  4. At higher levels of abstraction our account has parallels with that of Godfrey-Smith (2009). But our purposes are slightly different. While Godfrey-Smith is concerned with the highest level of abstraction in population systems, we are also concerned (see below) with particular mechanisms, which are not strictly universal, concerning how complexity is generated in these systems.

  5. Information here is defined very broadly, in the Shannon–Weaver sense of conditional dispositions or coding that can be transmitted to other entities and cause a response. That is, the transmission of information can be analyzed as an instance of general probability theory (Khinchin 1957).

  6. The gene was elusive to Darwin, but he anticipated its function. Throughout Origin and other writings, Darwin describes how inherited modifications are preserved in “instincts” and “germ cells.” “Germ” is mentioned in Darwin’s Notebook B and E, and instincts are mentioned in almost all his notebooks. In his theory of “pangenesis,” Darwin (1868) conjectured that information is preserved and inherited via “gemmules” given off by cells in the bloodstream.

  7. The genotype–phenotype terminology was introduced in 1911 by the Danish biologist Wilhelm Johannsen. He also coined the term “gene” in 1909, intending it to serve the same purpose as Darwin’s “pangen” (Keller and Lloyd 1992).

  8. The problems concerning its biological application are sufficiently severe to lead a minority of philosophers of biology to drop these concepts (Griesemer 1994, 1999; Griffiths and Gray 1994, 1997; Wimsatt 1999). We criticize some of their arguments in Hodgson and Knudsen (2010a, b).

  9. Nelson and Nelson (2003, p. 1646) and Nelson (2007) have expressed doubts regarding the replicator-interactor distinction in the social domain. Previously, by contrast, Nelson and Winter (1982, pp. 134–136, 160–161) described organizational routines as genes. Dosi and Nelson (1994, p. 155) foreshadowed the development of generalized Darwinism and identified four principal building blocks of any evolutionary theory: “(i) a fundamental unit of selection (the genes); (ii) a mechanism linking the genotypic level with the entities (the phenotypes) which actually undergo environmental selection, (iii) some processes of interaction, yielding the selection dynamics; and, finally, (iv) some mechanisms generating variations in the population.”

  10. See Morison (1966, pp. 17–44) for a striking illustration of routines in a military context.

  11. Like “routine” and “habit,” “custom” suffers from some ambiguity in general parlance, referring both to the observed behaviors and to the dispositions that give rise to such behaviors. If custom were behavior then the characteristic would logically disappear when the behavior ceased. Yet just as we retain habits, and organizations retain routines, then groups retain customs, even when they are not exercised: they do not have to be re-created anew after every period of inactivity.

References

  • Acemoglu D (2006) A simple model of inefficient institutions. Scand J Econ 108(4):515–546

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Aldrich HE, Hodgson GM, Hull DL, Knudsen K, Mokyr J, Vanberg VJ (2008) In defence of generalized Darwinism. J Evol Econ 18:577–596

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Amable B (2000) Institutional complementarity and diversity of social systems of innovation and production. Rev Int Polit Econ 7:645–687

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Amable B (2003) The diversity of modern capitalism. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Aoki M (2001) Toward a comparative institutional analysis. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Arrow KJ (1962) Economic welfare and the allocation of resources to invention. In: Nelson RR (ed) The rate and direction of inventive activity: economic and social factors. Princeton University Press, Princeton, pp 609–625

    Google Scholar 

  • Boyer R (2005) Coherence, diversity, and the evolution of capitalisms: the institutional complementarity hypothesis. Evol Instit Econ Rev 2:43–80

    Google Scholar 

  • Brandon RN (1996) Concepts and methods in evolutionary biology. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Campbell DT (1965) Variation, selection and retention in sociocultural evolution. In: Barringer HR, Blanksten GI, Mack RW (eds) Social change in developing areas: a reinterpretation of evolutionary theory. Schenkman, Cambridge, MA, pp 19–49

    Google Scholar 

  • Darnell JE, Doolittle WF (1986) Speculations on the early course of evolution. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 83:1271–1275

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Darwin CR (1859) On the origin of species by means of natural selection, or the preservation of favoured races in the struggle for life, 1st edn. Murray, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Darwin CR (1868) The variation of animals and plants under domestication (2 Vols.), 1st edn. Murray and Orange Judd, London, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Darwin CR (1871) The descent of man, and selection in relation to sex (2 Vols.), 1st edn. Murray, London

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dawkins R (1982) The extended phenotype: the gene as the unit of selection. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Dawkins R (1983) Universal Darwinism. In: Bendall DS (ed) Evolution from molecules to man. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 403–425

    Google Scholar 

  • Dosi G, Nelson RR (1994) An introduction to evolutionary theories in economics. J Evol Econ 4:153–172

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dosi G, Metcalfe S, Stanley J (1991) On some notions of irreversibility in economics. In: Saviotti PP, Metcalfe S, Stanley J (eds) Evolutionary theories of economic and technological change: present status and future prospects. Harwood, Reading, pp 133–159

    Google Scholar 

  • Dupré J (ed) (1987) The latest on the best: essays on evolution and optimality. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Edgerton RB (1992) Sick societies: challenging the myth of primitive harmony. Free Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Eigen M (1994) The origin of genetic information. Origins Life Evol B 24:241–262

    Google Scholar 

  • Eigen M, Williams GC, Schuster P, Ruthild W-O (1981) The origin of genetic information. Sci Am 244(4):78–94

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gagliardi F (2009) Financial development and the growth of cooperative firms. Small Bus Econ 32:439–464

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith P (2000) The replicator in retrospect. Biol Philos 15:403–423

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith P (2006) Local interaction, multilevel selection, and evolutionary transitions. Biol Theory 1:372–380

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith P (2009) Darwinian populations and natural selection. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Gould SJ (1977) Ontogeny and phylogeny. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Gould SJ (1980) The panda’s thumb: more reflections in natural history. Norton, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Gould SJ (2002) The structure of evolutionary theory. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Griesemer JR (1994) Tools for talking: human nature, Weismannism, and the interpretation of genetic information. In: Cranor C (ed) Are genes us? The social consequences of the new genetics. Rutgers University Press, New Brunswick, NJ, pp 69–88

    Google Scholar 

  • Griesemer JR (1999) Materials for the study of evolutionary transition. Biol Philos 14:127–142

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths PE, Gray RD (1994) Developmental systems and evolutionary explanation. J Philos 91:277–304

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths PE, Gray RD (1997) Replicator II: judgment day. Biol Philos 12:471–490

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hall PA, Soskice D (2001) Varieties of capitalism: the institutional foundations of comparative advantage. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hayek FA (1988) The fatal conceit: the errors of socialism. In: Bartley WW III (ed) The collected works of Friedrich August Hayek, Vol I. Routledge, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Hodgson GM (1988) Economics and institutions: a manifesto for a modern institutional economics. Polity, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Hodgson GM (1993) Economics and evolution: bringing life back into economics. Polity, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Hodgson GM (2001) How economics forgot history: The problem of historical specificity in social science. Routledge, London and New York

  • Hodgson GM (2008) Markets. In: New Palgrave dictionary of economics. 2nd edn. Macmillan, Basingstoke

  • Hodgson GM (2011) Organizational evolution versus the cult of change. Corp Financ Rev 16(1):5–10

    Google Scholar 

  • Hodgson GM, Knudsen T (2006) Why we need a generalized Darwinism, and why a generalized Darwinism is not enough. J Econ Behav Organ 61:1–19

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hodgson GM, Knudsen T (2010a) Generative replication and the evolution of complexity. J Econ Behav Organ 75:12–24

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hodgson GM, Knudsen Thorbjørn (2010b) Darwin’s conjecture: the search for general principles of social and economic evolution. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Hull DL (1988) Science as a process: an evolutionary account of the social and conceptual development of science. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Hull DL (2001) Science and selection. Essays on biological evolution and the philosophy of science. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Hull DL, Langman RE, Glenn SS (2001) A general account of selection: biology, immunology, and behaviour. Behav Brain Sci 24:511–573

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Joyce GF (2002) The antiquity of RNA-based evolution. Nature 418:214–221

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Keesing R (1974) Theories of culture. Annu Rev Anthropol l3:73–97

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Keller AG (1915) Societal evolution: a study of the evolutionary basis of the science of society. Macmillan, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Keller EF, Lloyd EA (eds) (1992) Keywords in evolutionary biology. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Kennedy P (1988) The rise and fall of the great powers: economic change and military conflict from 1500 to 2000. Unwin Hyman, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Kenworthy L (2006) Institutional coherence and macroeconomic performance. Socio-Econ Rev 4:69–91

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Khinchin AI (1957) Mathematical foundations of information theory. Dover, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher P (1981) Explanatory unification. Philos Sci 48:507–531

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kroeber AL, Kluckhohn C (1963) Culture: a critical review of concepts and definitions. Random House, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Loasby BJ (1998) The organisation of capabilities. J Econ Behav Organ 35(2):139–160

    Google Scholar 

  • Maddison A (1991) Dynamic forces in capitalist development: a long-run comparative view. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Maynard Smith J, Szathmáry E (1995) The major transitions in evolution. Freeman, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Miller JG (1978) Living systems. McGraw-Hill, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Mirowski P, Sent E-M (eds) (2002) Science bought and sold: essays on the economics of science. Chicago University Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Morison EE (1966) Men, machines, and modern times. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Nelson RR (1959) The simple economics of basic scientific research. J Polit Econ 67:297–306

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nelson RR (1981) Assessing private enterprise: an exegesis of tangled doctrine. Bell J Econ 12:93–111

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nelson RR (2003) On the complexities and limits of market organization. Rev Int Polit Econ 10:697–710

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nelson RR (2007) Comment on: “Dismantling Lamarckism: why descriptions of socio-economic evolution as Lamarckian are misleading, by Hodgson and Knudsen.” J Evol Econ 17:349–352

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nelson K, Nelson RR (2003) The cumulative advance of human know-how. Philos Trans R Soc Lond A 361:1635–1653

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nelson RR, Winter SG (1982) An evolutionary theory of economic change. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • North DC (1990) Institutions, institutional change and economic performance. Cambridge University Press, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Okasha S (2005) Multilevel selection and the major transitions in evolution. Philos Sci 72:1013–1025

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pagano U (1991) Property rights, asset specificity, and the division of labour under alternative capitalist relations. Cambridge J Econ 15(3):315–342

    Google Scholar 

  • Pagano U (2001) The origin of organisational species. In: Nicita A, Pagano U (eds) The evolution of economic diversity. Routledge, London, pp 21–48

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper KR (1960) The poverty of historicism. Routledge and Kegan Paul, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Price GR (1995) The nature of selection. J Theor Biol 175:389–396

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reber AS (1993) Implicit learning and tacit knowledge: an essay on the cognitive unconscious. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Saviotti PP (1996) Technological evolution, variety and the economy. Edward Elgar, Aldershot

    Google Scholar 

  • Schumpeter JA (1934) The theory of economic development: an inquiry into profits, capital, credit, interest, and the business cycle. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro R (2006) Small molecule interactions were central to the origin of life. Quart Rev Biol 81:105–125

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Silva ST, Teixeira AAC (2009) On the divergence of evolutionary research paths in the past 50 years: a comprehensive bibliometric account. J Evol Econ 19:605–642

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Simon HA (1957) Models of man: social and rational. Wiley, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Sober E (1984) The nature of selection: evolutionary theory in philosophical focus. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny K, Smith KC, Dickison M (1996) The extended replicator. Biol Philos 11:377–403

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stoelhorst JW (2008) The explanatory logic and ontological commitments of generalized Darwinism. J Econ Methodology 15:343–363

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tylor EB (1871) Primitive culture: researches into the development of mythology, philosophy, religion, language, art, and custom. 2 Vols. Murray, London

  • Van Parijs P (1981) Evolutionary explanations in the social sciences: an emerging paradigm. Tavistock, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Veblen TB (1899) The theory of the leisure class: an economic study in the evolution of institutions. Macmillan, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Veblen TB (1914) The instinct of workmanship, and the state of the industrial arts. Macmillan, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Veblen TB (1919) The place of science in modern civilization and other essays. Huebsch, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • von Neumann J (1966) In: Burks AW (ed) Theory of self-reproducing automata. University of Illinois Press, Urbana

    Google Scholar 

  • Whitehead AN (1929) Process and reality: an essay in cosmology. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Wimsatt WC (1986) Developmental constraints, generative entrenchment, and the innate-acquired distinction. In: Bechtel W (ed) Integrating scientific disciplines. Nijhoff, Dordrecht, pp 185–208

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Wimsatt WC (1999) Genes, memes, and cultural heredity. Biol Philos 14:279–310

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Winter SG (1986) Comments on Lucas and Arrow. J Bus 59:427–434

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Witt U (ed) (1992) Explaining process and change: approaches to evolutionary economics. University of Michigan Press, Ann Arbor, MI

    Google Scholar 

  • Witt U (1997) Self-organisation and economics—what is new? Struct Change Econ Dynam 8:489–507

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Witt U (2004) On the proper interpretations of “evolution” in economics and its implications for production theory. J Econ Methodology 11:125–146

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Witt U (2008) What is specific about evolutionary economics? J Evol Econ 18:547–575

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Geoffrey M. Hodgson.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Hodgson, G.M., Knudsen, T. Generalized Darwinism and Evolutionary Economics: From Ontology to Theory. Biol Theory 6, 326–337 (2011). https://doi.org/10.1007/s13752-012-0043-5

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s13752-012-0043-5

Keywords

JEL classifications

Navigation