Skip to main content
Log in

Evolution, Development, and Human Social Cognition

  • Published:
Review of Philosophy and Psychology Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Explaining the causal origins of what are taken to be uniquely human capacities for understanding the mind in the first years of life is a primary goal of social cognitive development research, which concerns so called “theory of mind” or “mindreading” skills. We review and discuss particular examples of this research in the context of its underlying evolutionary conceptual framework known as the neo-Darwinian modern synthesis. It is increasingly recognized that the modern synthesis is limited in its neglect of developmental issues. A recent convergence of work from diverse sources, including but not limited to evolutionary developmental biology (evo-devo) and developmental systems approaches, demonstrate the need for a developmental expansion of modern evolutionary theory. We attempt to show that not only are nativist explanations of early human social cognition vulnerable to the criticisms of this developmental shift in thinking, but that these criticisms also problematize the dominant and more mainstream theories in early social cognitive development research. We conclude by discussing the importance of developmental analysis in understanding the ontogeny of cognitive capacities in individuals as well as species.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. And in psychology more generally under the banner of Evolutionary Psychology.

  2. By genocentric we mean an approach that assumes genes contain developmental information and therefore which ignores or minimizes developmental processes. In our view, genocentrism is a holdover from the population genetic model.

  3. Although we use the term “evo-devo”, it should not be taken to indicate that biology’s attempt to integrate the issues of evolution and development has led to the emergence of a homogeneous discipline. How population-genetics and developmental models will be integrated, and what form this discipline will take (i.e. evo-devo, devo-evo, devgen-popgen, and eco-evo-devo) is still debated (Gilbert 2003; Müller 2007). Evo-devo is the dominant form of this merger. Though many evo-devo researchers still take the gene to be sole unit of heritance, it is believed that the merger of evolutionary biology and developmental biology will lead to emergent properties not present in either discipline currently (Hall 2000), and will likely have important implications for psychology as well.

  4. Although there are appropriate uses for isolation procedures (e.g. Gottlieb 1976; West and King 1977; Zulley 2000), they do not lead to the obvious separation between the intrinsic and extrinsic factors involved in development in the way described below.

  5. Developmental analysis involves the careful study of a multitude of factors over time. Cross-sectional studies provide a “snap-shot” of development and cannot provide the same information about stability and change over time that data longitudinal methods offer. The most notable problem is the assumption that one can “reverse-engineer” developmental processes from cross-sectional studies when these data can only be appropriately acquired through longitudinal methods.

  6. Tinbergen (1963) proposed that biological study of behaviour could be best approached through focusing on four main questions concerning the proximate cause, adaptive function, development (ontogeny) and evolutionary history (phylogeny) of the behaviour under study.

  7. However, given the approach we have taken in this article, we clearly do not endorse the innatist presuppositions present in classical ethology (see Lehrman 1953).

References

  • Alberch, P. 1991. From genes to phenotype: Dynamical systems and evolvability. Genetica 84: 5–11.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baillargeon, R., R.M. Scott, and Z. He. 2010. False-belief understanding in infants. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 14: 110–118.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baron-Cohen, S. 1995. Mindblindness: An essay on autism and theory of mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baron-Cohen, S., and J. Swettenham. 1996. The relationship between SAM and ToMM: Two hypotheses. In Theories of theories of mind, ed. P. Carruthers and P.K. Smith, 158–168. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Bateson, P. 1996. Design for a life. In The lifespan development of individuals: Behavioral, neurobiological, and psychosocial perspectives, ed. D. Magnusson, 1–20. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bateson, P., and M. Mameli. 2007. The innate and the acquired: Useful clusters or a residual distinction from folk biology? Developmental Psychobiology 49: 818–831.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boesch, C. 2007. What makes us human (Homo sapiens)? The challenge of cognitive cross- species comparison. Journal of Comparative Psychology 121: 227–240.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boesch, C. 2008. Taking development and ecology seriously when comparing cognition: Reply to Tomasello and Call (2008). Journal of Comparative Psychology 122: 453–455.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boyd, R., P.J. Richerson, and J. Henrich. 2011. The cultural niche: Why social learning is essential for human adaptation. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America 108: 10918–10925.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brauer, J., J. Kaminski, J. Riedel, J. Call, and M. Tomasello. 2006. Making inferences about the location of hidden food: Social dog, causal ape. Journal of Comparative Psychology 120: 38–47.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buss, D.M. 1995. Evolutionary psychology: A new paradigm for psychological science. Psychological Inquiry 6: 1–30.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Butterworth, G. 1991. The ontogeny and phylogeny of joint visual attention. In Natural theories of mind, ed. A. Whiten, 223–232. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Call, J., and M. Tomasello. 1996. The effect of humans on the cognitive development of apes. In Reaching into thoughts: The minds of the great apes, ed. A.E. Russon, K.A. Bard, and S.T. Parker, 371–403. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Call, J., and M. Tomasello. 2008a. Assessing the validity of ape-human comparisons: A reply to Boesch (2007). Journal of Comparative Psychology 122: 449–452.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Call, J., and M. Tomasello. 2008b. Does the chimpanzee have a theory of mind? 30 years later. Trends in Cognitive Science 12: 187–192.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Callebaut, W., G.B. Müller, and S.A. Newman. 2007. The organismic systems approach: Evo-devo and the streamlining of the naturalistic agenda. In Integrating evolution and development: From theory to practice, ed. R. Sansom and R.N. Brandon, 25–92. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carpenter, M., Nagell, K., & Tomasello, M. 1998. Social cognition, joint attention, and communicative competence from 9 to 15 months of age. Monographs of the Society for Research in Child Development 63(4): i+iii+v–vi+1–174.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carroll, S.B. 2005. Endless forms most beautiful: The new science of evo devo. New York: Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carruthers, P. 1996. Simulation and self-knowledge: A defence of theory-theory. In Theories of theories of mind, ed. P. Carruthers and P.K. Smith, 22–38. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Carruthers, P., and P.K. Smith. 1996a. Theories of theories of mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Carruthers, P., and P.K. Smith. 1996b. Introduction. In Theories of theories of mind, ed. P. Carruthers and P.K. Smith, 1–8. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Carstairs-McCarthy, A. 2007. Language evolution: What linguists can contribute. Lingua 117: 503–509.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Confer, J.C., J.A. Easton, D.S. Fleischman, C.D. Goetz, D.M.G. Lewis, C. Perilloux, and D.M. Buss. 2010. Evolutionary psychology: Controversies, questions, prospects, and limitations. American Psychologist 65: 110–126.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cosmides, L., J. Tooby, and J.H. Barkow. 1992. Introduction: Evolutionary psychology and conceptual integration. In The adapted mind: Evolutionary psychology and the generation of culture, ed. J.H. Barkow, L. Cosmides, and J. Tooby, 3–15. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Crawford, C.B. 1989. The theory of evolution: Of what value to psychology? Journal of Comparative Psychology 103: 4–22.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Crick, F. 1970. Central dogma of molecular biology. Nature 227: 561–563.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • de Waal, F.B.M., C. Boesch, V. Horner, and A. Whiten. 2008. Comparing social skills of children and apes. Science 319: 569.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Di Sciullo, A.M., M. Piattelli-Palmarini, K. Wexler, R.C. Berwick, C. Boeckx, L. Jenkins, et al. 2010. The biological nature of human language. Biolinguistics 4: 4–34.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dupré, J. 2001. Human nature and the limits of science. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Finlay, B. 2007. Endless minds most beautiful. Developmental Science 10: 30–34.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fitch, W.T., M.D. Hauser, and N. Chomsky. 2005. The evolution of the language faculty: Clarifications and implications. Cognition 97: 179–210.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert, S.F. 2001. Ecological developmental biology: Developmental biology meets the real world. Developmental Biology 233: 1–12.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert, S.F. 2003. Evo-devo, devo-evo, and devgen-popgen. Biology and Philosophy 18: 347–352.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert, S.F., and D. Epel. 2009. Ecological developmental biology: Integrating epigenetics, medicine, and evolution. Sunderland: Sinauer Associates.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert, S.F., J.M. Opitz, and R.A. Raff. 1996. Resynthesizing evolutionary and developmental biology. Developmental Biology 173: 357–372.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gopnik, A. 1996. Theories and modules; creation myths, developmental realities, and Neurath’s boat. In Theories of theories of mind, ed. P. Carruthers and P.K. Smith, 169–183. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Gottlieb, G. 1976. Conceptions of prenatal development: Behavioral embryology. Psychological Review 83: 215–234.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gottlieb, G. 1996. A systems view of psychobiological development. In The lifespan development of individuals: Behavioral, neurobiological, and psychosocial perspectives, ed. D. Magnusson, 76–103. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gottlieb, G. 2000. Environmental and behavioral influences on gene activity. Current Directions in Psychological Science 9: 93–97.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gottlieb, G. 2002. Individual development and evolution: The genesis of novel behaviour. Mahwah: Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gottlieb, G. 2007. Probabilistic epigenesis. Developmental Science 10: 1–11.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gray, R.D. 1992. Death of the gene: Developmental systems strike back. In Trees of life, ed. P.E. Griffiths, 165–210. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Griesemer, J. 2000. Development, culture, and the units of inheritance. Philosophy of Science 67(supplement): S348–S368.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths, P.E. 2002. What is innateness? The Monist 85: 70–85.

    Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths, P.E. 2007. Evo-devo meets the mind: Toward a developmental evolutionary psychology. In Integrating evolution and development: From theory to practice, ed. R. Sansom and R.N. Brandon, 195–225. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths, P.E., and R.D. Gray. 1994. Developmental systems and evolutionary explanation. Journal of Philosophy 91: 277–304.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths, P.E., and R.D. Knight. 1998. What is the developmentalist challenge? Philosophy of Science 65: 253–258.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths, P.E., and E.M. Neumann-Held. 1999. The many faces of the gene. Bioscience 49: 656–662.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths, P.E., and K. Stotz. 2000. How the mind grows: A developmental perspective on the biology of cognition. Synthese 122: 29–51.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hall, B.K. 2000. Guest editorial: Evo-devo or devo-evo - does it matter? Evolution & Development 2: 177–178.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hamburger, V. 1980. Embryology and the modern synthesis in evolutionary theory. In The evolutionary synthesis: Perspectives on the unification of biology, ed. E. Mayr and W.B. Provine, 97–112. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Henrich, J., S.J. Heine, and A. Norenzayan. 2010. The weirdest people in the world? The Behavioral and Brain Sciences 33: 61–135.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Herrmann, E., J. Call, M.V. Hernández-Lloreda, B. Hare, and M. Tomasello. 2007. Humans have evolved specialized skills of social cognition: The cultural intelligence hypothesis. Science 317: 1360–1366.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Herrmann, E., J. Call, M.V. Hernández-Lloreda, B. Hare, and M. Tomasello. 2008. Response to de Waal et al. Science 319: 570.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ioannidis, S. 2008. How development changes evolution: Conceptual and historical issues in evolutionary developmental biology. Biology and Philosophy 23: 567–578.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jablonka, E., and M. Lamb. 2002. Creating bridges or rifts? Developmental systems theory and evolutionary developmental biology. BioEssays 24: 290–291.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jablonka, E., and M.J. Lamb. 2005. Evolution in four dimensions. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jablonka, E., and M. Lamb. 2007. The expanded evolutionary synthesis—a response to Godfrey-Smith, Haig, and West-Eberhard. Biology and Philosophy 22: 453–472.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jablonka, E., and G. Raz. 2009. Transgenerational epigenetic inheritance: Prevalence, mechanisms, and implications for the study of heredity and evolution. The Quarterly Review of Biology 84: 131–176.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Johnston, T.D. 1987. The persistence of dichotomies in the study of behavioral development. Developmental Review 7: 149–182.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Johnston, T.D., and L. Edwards. 2002. Genes, interactions, and the development of behavior. Psychological Review 109: 26–34.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Johnston, T.D., and G. Gottlieb. 1990. Neophenogenesis: A developmental theory of phenotypic evolution. Journal of Theoretical Biology 147: 471–495.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laland, K.N., Odling-Smee, and S.F. Gilbert. 2008. Evodevo and niche construction: Building bridges. The Journal of Experimental Zoology 310B: 549–566.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leavens, D.A., W.D. Hopkins, and R.K. Thomas. 2004. Referential communications by chimpanzees (Pan troglodytes). Journal of Comparative Psychology 118: 48–57.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leavens, D.A., W.D. Hopkins, and K.A. Bard. 2008. The heterochronic origins of explicit reference. In The shared mind: Perspectives on intersubjectivity, ed. J. Zlatev, T.P. Racine, C. Sinha, and E. Itkonen, 187–214. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leavens, D.A., and T.P. Racine. 2009. Joint attention in apes and humans: Are humans unique? Journal of Consciousness Studies 16: 240–267.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lehrman, D.S. 1953. A critique of Konrad Lorenz’s theory of instinctive behavior. The Quarterly Review of Biology 28: 337–363.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lehrman, D.S. 1970. Semantic and conceptual issues in the nature-nurture problem. In Development and evolution of behavior, ed. L.R. Aronson, E. Tobach, D.S. Lehrman, and J.S. Rosenblatt, 17–52. San Francisco: Freeman.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leslie, A.M. 1987. Pretense and representation: The origins of “theory of mind”. Psychological Review 94: 412–426.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leslie, A.M. 1989. Some implications of pretense for mechanisms underlying the child’s theory of mind. In Developing theories of mind, ed. J.W. Astington, P.L. Harris, and D.R. Olson, 19–46. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leslie, A.M. 1991. The theory of mind impairment in autism: Evidence for a modular mechanism of development? In Natural theories of mind, ed. A. Whiten, 19–46. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leslie, A.M. 1994. Pretending and believing: Issues in the theory of ToMM. Cognition 50: 211–238.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewontin, R.C. 1983. Gene, organism, and environment. In Evolution: From molecules to man, ed. D.S. Bedall, 273–285. Cambridge: University of Cambridge Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lickliter, R. 2000. An ecological approach to behavioral development: Insights from comparative psychology. Ecological Psychology 12: 319–334.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lickliter, R. 2008. The growth of developmental thought: Implications for a new evolutionary psychology. New Ideas in Psychology 26: 353–369.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lickliter, R., and T.D. Berry. 1990. The phylogeny fallacy: Developmental psychology’s misapplication of evolutionary theory. Developmental Review 10: 348–364.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lickliter, R., A.B. Dyer, and T. McBride. 1993. Perceptual consequences of early social experience in precocial birds. Behavioural Processes 30: 185–200.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lickliter, R., and H. Honeycutt. 2003. Developmental dynamics: Toward a biologically plausible evolutionary psychology. Psychological Bulletin 129: 819–835.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Liebal, K., T. Behne, M. Carpenter, and M. Tomasello. 2009. Infants use shared experience to interpret pointing gestures. Developmental Science 12: 264–271.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Liszkowski, U., M. Carpenter, and M. Tomasello. 2007. Reference and attitude in infant pointing. Journal of Child Language 34: 1–20.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Love, A.C., and R.A. Raff. 2003. Knowing your ancestors: Themes in the history of evo-devo. Evolution & Development 5: 327–330.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mameli, M., and P. Bateson. 2006. Innateness and the sciences. Biology and Philosophy 21: 155–188.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mayr, E. 1961. Cause and effect in biology. Science 134: 1501–1506.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Meltzoff, A.N., and A. Gopnik. 1993. The role of imitation in understanding persons and developing a theory of mind. In Understanding other minds: Perspectives from autism, ed. S. Baron-Cohen, H. Tager-Flusberg, and D.J. Cohen, 335–366. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meltzoff, A.N., and M.K. Moore. 1998. Infant intersubjectivity: Broadening the dialogue to include imitation, identity and intention. In Intersubjective communication and emotion in early ontogeny, ed. S. Brȧten, 47–62. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moore, D.S. 2002. The dependent gene. New York: Times Books/Henry Holt.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moss, L. 1992. A kernel of truth? On the reality of the genetic program. In Proceedings of the Philosophy of Science Association 1991: Vol. 1, ed. D. Hull, A. Fine, and M. Forbes, 335–348. East Lansing: The Philosophy of Science Association.

    Google Scholar 

  • Müller, G.B. 2007. Evo-devo: Extending the evolutionary synthesis. Nature Reviews Genetics 8(12): 943–949.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Müller, G.B., and S.A. Newman. 2003. Origination of organismal form: The forgotten cause in evolutionary theory. In Origination of organismal form: Beyond the gene in developmental and evolutionary biology, ed. G.B. Muller and S.A. Newman, 3–10. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Niyogi, P., and R.C. Berwick. 1996. Evolutionary consequences of language learning. Linguistics & Philosophy 20: 697–719.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Noble, D. 2010. Biophysics and systems biology. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society A 368: 1125–1139.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Noble, D. 2011. Neo-Darwinism, the modern synthesis and selfish genes: Are they of use in physiology? The Journal of Physiology 589: 1007–1015.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Odling-Smee, F.J., K.N. Laland, and M.W. Feldman. 1996. Niche construction. The American Naturalist 147: 641–648.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Odling-Smee, F.J., K.N. Laland, and M.W. Feldman. 2003. Niche construction: The neglected process in evolution. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oyama, S. 1985. The ontogeny of information: Developmental systems and evolution. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oyama, S. 2000. Causal democracy and causal contributions in developmental systems theory. Philosophy of Science 67(supplement): S332–S347.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Oyama, S., P.E. Griffiths, and R.D. Gray. 2001. Cycles of contingency: Developmental systems & evolution. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Penn, D.C., K.J. Holyoak, and D.J. Povinelli. 2008. Darwin’s mistake: Explaining the discontinuity between human and nonhuman minds. The Behavioral and Brain Sciences 31: 109–178.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pigliucci, M. 2009. An extended synthesis for evolutionary biology. Annals of the New York Academy of Science 1168: 218–228.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pigliucci, M., and G.B. Müller. 2010. Evolution: The extended synthesis. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ploeger, A., H.L.J. van der Maas, and M.E.J. Raijmakers. 2008. Is evolutionary psychology a meta-theory for psychology? A discussion of four major issues in psychology from an evolutionary developmental perspective. Psychological Inquiry 19: 1–18.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Racine, T.P. 2012. Getting beyond rich and lean views of joint attention. In Joint attention: Developments in philosophy of mind, developmental and comparative psychology and cognitive science, ed. A. Seemann, 21–42. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Racine, T.P., D.A. Leavens, N. Susswein, and T.J. Wereha. 2008. Conceptual and methodological issues in the investigation of primate intersubjectivity. In Enacting intersubjectivity: A cognitive and social perspective to the study of interactions, ed. F. Morganti, A. Carassa, and G. Riva, 65–79. Amsterdam: Ios Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Racine, T.P., T.J. Wereha, and D.A. Leavens. 2012. To what extent nonhuman primates are intersubjective and why. In Moving ourselves, moving others: Motion and emotion in intersubjectivity, consciousness and language, ed. A. Foolen, U. Lüdtke, T.P. Racine, and J. Zlatev. Amsterdam: Benjamins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reid, R.G.B. 2007. Biological emergences: Evolution by natural experiment. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Robert, J.S. 2002. How developmental is evolutionary developmental biology? Biology and Philosophy 17: 591–611.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Robert, J.S. 2003. Developmental systems and animal behaviour. Biology and Philosophy 18: 477–489.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Robert, J.S. 2004. Embryology, epigenesis, and evolution: Taking development seriously. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sansom, R., and R.N. Brandon. 2007. In Integrating evolution and development: From theory to practice, ed. R. Sansom and R.N. Brandon. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sapp, J. 1987. Beyond the gene: Cytoplasmic inheritance and the struggle for authority in genetics. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shishkin, M.A. 1992. Evolution as a maintenance of ontogenetic stability. Acta Zoologica Fennica 191: 37–42.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, L.B. 1999. Do infants possess innate knowledge structures? The con side. Developmental Science 2: 133–144.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Spencer, J.P., M.S. Blumberg, B. McMurray, S.R. Robinson, L.K. Samuelson, and J.B. Tomblin. 2009. Short arms and talking eggs: Why we should no longer abide the nativist-empiricist debate. Child Development Perspectives 2: 79–87.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny, K. 2000a. Development, evolution, and adaptation. Philosophy of Science 67(supplement): S369–S387.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny, K. 2000b. The “genetic program” program: A commentary on Maynard Smith on information in biology. Philosophy of Science 67: 195–201.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny, K. 2012. The evolved apprentice: How evolution made humans unique. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny, K., and P.S. Kitcher. 1988. The return of the gene. Journal of Philosophy 85: 339–361.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Susswein, N., and T.P. Racine. 2008. Sharing mental states: Causal and definitional issues in intersubjectivity. In The shared mind: Perspectives on intersubjectivity, ed. J. Zlatev, T.P. Racine, C. Sinha, and E. Itkonen, 141–162. Amsterdam: Benjamins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, A.H., D. Elliffe, G.R. Hunt, and R.D. Gray. 2010. Complex cognition and behavioural innovation in New Caledonian crows. Proceedings of the Royal Society B 277: 2637–2643.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, A.H., and R.D. Gray. 2009. Animal cognition: Aesop’s fable flies from fiction to fact. Current Biology 19: R731–R732.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tinbergen, N. 1963. On aims and methods of ethology. Zeitschirift für Tierpsychologie 20: 410–413.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tomasello, M. 1995a. Joint attention as social cognition. In Joint attention: Its origins and role in development, ed. C. Moore and P.J. Dunham, 103–130. Hillsdale: Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tomasello, M. 1995b. Language is not an instinct. Cognitive Development 10: 131–156.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tomasello, M. 1999a. The cultural origins of human cognition. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tomasello, M. 1999b. The human adaptation for culture. Annual Review of Anthropology 28: 509–529.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tomasello, M. 2003. Constructing a language: A usage-based theory of language acquisition. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tomasello, M. 2008. Origins of human communication. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tomasello, M. 2009. Why we cooperate. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tomasello, M., and J. Call. 2008. Assessing the validity of ape-human comparisons: A reply to Boesch (2007). Journal of Comparative Psychology 122: 449–452.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tomasello, M., J. Call, and B. Hare. 2003. Chimpanzees understand psychological states-the question is which ones and to what extent. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 7: 153–156.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tomasello, M., and M. Carpenter. 2007. Shared intentionality. Developmental Science 10: 121–125.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tomasello, M., M. Carpenter, J. Call, T. Behne, and H. Moll. 2005. Understanding and sharing intentions: The origins of cultural cognition. The Behavioral and Brain Sciences 28: 675–735.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tomasello, M., M. Carpenter, and U. Liszkowski. 2007. A new look at infant pointing. Child Development 78: 705–722.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Trevarthen, C., and K.J. Aitken. 2001. Infant intersubjectivity: Research, theory, and clinical applications. Journal of Child Psychology and Psychiatry 42: 3–48.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wagner, G.P. 2000. What is the promise of developmental evolution? Part I: Why is developmental biology necessary to explain evolutionary innovations? Journal of Experimental Zoology (Molecular & Developmental Evolution) 288: 95–98.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wereha, T.J., and T.P. Racine. 2009a. Belief in evolved belief systems: Artifact of a limited evolutionary model? The Behavioral and Brain Sciences 32: 537–538.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wereha, T.J., and T.P. Racine. 2009b. Evolutionary psychology at a crossroads? Journal of Research in Character Education 6: 95–99.

    Google Scholar 

  • West, M.J., and A.P. King. 1977. Species identification in the North American cowbird: Appropriate responses to abnormal song. Science 195: 1002–1004.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • West-Eberhard, M.J. 2003. Developmental plasticity and evolution. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • West-Eberhard, M.J. 2005. Developmental plasticity and the origin of species differences. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences USA 102: 6543–6549.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, O.E. 2000. Sociobiology: The new synthesis, twenty-fifth anniversaryth ed. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zulley, J. 2000. The influence of isolation on psychological and physiological variables. Aviation, Space, and Environmental Medicine 71(supplement): A44–A47.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Preparation of this article was supported by a Doctoral Scholarship and a Standard Research Grant from the Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council of Canada (SSHRC) awarded to the authors, respectively. We thank the four anonymous reviewers who provided generous feedback on a previous version of this article. We would also like to thank Paul Egré for his comments on our manuscript and his assistance throughout the review process.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Tyler J. Wereha.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Wereha, T.J., Racine, T.P. Evolution, Development, and Human Social Cognition. Rev.Phil.Psych. 3, 559–579 (2012). https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-012-0115-2

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-012-0115-2

Keywords

Navigation