Skip to main content
Log in

Identitarian passions: the overwhelming power of the human recognition need

  • Research Article
  • Published:
International Review of Economics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

According to Plato, thymòs—a notion denoting the human need for recognition—triggers off the most powerful and overwhelming human passions. Indeed, any action originated and nurtured by thymòtic passions places its own raison d’être in itself. The acts motivated by thymòs can either improve or (even) worsen someone’s wellness: they do not entail any pay-off in the present or future, and their nature is not influenced nor mitigated by monetary incentives. Moreover, it follows that since identity is based on the others’ recognition (both individuals and social groups), then indulging with thymòtic passions and building up someone’s own identity are exactly the same process. Indeed, thymòtic passions are identitarian passions. This paper argues the relevance of the thymòtic approach. We do propose a conceptual framework that we reckon is useful and innovative in order to study and interpret these peculiar forms of human action. We also point out the social and “environmental” conditions that stimulate their appearance.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The notion of thymòs—namely, the identitarian need for recognition that human beings feel in order to place themselves within society—goes back to Plato, who in the IV book of his The Republic described the soul as composed by three different elements: the first component is rational (loghistikón) and lies in the head; the second part, to be found in the internal organs, is featured with concupiscence (epithymeticón); the third and last element resides in the heart and is depicted as spirited and irascible (thymoidés). According to Plato, the main part of the human behaviour can be explained by referring to the combination of the first two elements described above: the epithymeticón and the loghistikón—the organs and the head. The former leads human beings to temptation: therefore, they act in order to get what they desire. The latter works as a rational guide, in order to facilitate the research of what human beings desire as a consequence of their concupiscence. However, human beings are also and mostly busy in seeking the identification and recognition of their personal and social value, along with that of people, things, ideas and principle to which they assign importance (See Galimberti 1999: 592–593). In other words, thymòs is the expression of the short-tempered soul. Its etymology derives from the verb thyo—to fumigate, a word that shares the same root with the latin word fumus—expressing a lack of recognition and identification (See Bodei 2010: 9 and 115). Thymòs is further characterised by two crucial facets: someone’s search for distinction from the others as well as for his/her primacy over the others. This paper does not concentrate on these two particular aspects. Nevertheless, we will bring to the reader’s attention one of the most debated and criticised books of the last two decades—Francis Fukuyama’s The End of History and the Last Man (1992)—who owes very much to this philosophic background.

  2. The inverted commas are here used in order to stress the still very much important and relevant legacy of Edward Said’s Orientalism (Said 1978; See also Chakrabarty 2004:65). In our perspective, “The West” is a metaphor with a proper and complex historical genealogy (not a “natural” category), only useful to describe and link societies and nation states to a particular kind of political economy and self-representation strategies, who are not marked, however, by geographic homogeneity. Therefore, under the category “West” one may find European states, the USA, Canada, Japan and Australia, and some others.

  3. The notion of social drama drives us to the domain of social anthropology, and in particular to Victor Turner’s studies (1982, 1986). In a nutshell, social drama refers to a unit of disharmonic social process produced by dynamics of social conflicts, namely social crisis. Social drama is a process made of four constant phases, which the Author calls breach, crisis, redress and schism. The notion is intimately connected to that of ritual (and in particular to the rites of passage, with their structural and anti-structural, or liminal, stages), and serves as one of the main basis for the theory of performance elaborated by Richard Schechner (1985, 2004) Indeed, we can observe from the very beginning that “social drama” clearly represents a metaphor that the Author takes from the world of theatre. In fact, Turner recognises that he took cue from the Greek drama, where “one witnesses the helplessness of the human individual before the Fates”. In this case, he is saying that the Fates is the social process, and that conflicts in society are rarely only personal affairs, but that they almost always involve social relationships.

  4. In the contemporary literature, the word “passion” is often replaced by the word “emotion”, as our readers can also notice by looking at some of the quotations in the text. Both “passion” and “emotion” refer to the concept of “affective status”. However, we reckon it is important to underline the relevant discrepancy between the two terms: while the notion of “emotion” stands for a passing, transient feeling, “passion” represents a violent, persistent state, which sometimes cannot even totally been controlled or dominated. Passion is chronic, powerful, complex, longstanding, capable of polarizing someone’s attention towards a unique objective (See Cattarinussi 2006: 17). Therefore, we invite the reader to consider the term “emotion”, when it comes across in the text, as just a synonymous of “passion” as conceptualised here.

  5. We are clearly making use of the language of the game theory. In particular, the strategic games are normally represented through the construction of charts containing all the choices one can consider in a given situation. These options, or choices, are called matrices of the payoffs associated to any combination of the possible strategies available to the actors involved.

  6. What happens between Odysseus and the sailors may be interpreted as a self-confirming equilibrium, in the way explained by Fudenberg and Levine (1993). In it, the players, differently from what happens in the equilibrium described by Nash, do not have a complete comprehension of the game they are playing, and can have wrong beliefs regarding the strategies followed by other players. The theoretical point is that mistakes are coherent with one’s experience; in particular, with the observation of one’s choices. The sailors observe several of Odysseus rational choices, while Odysseus observes several choices of obedience by the sailors. But what matters is that it’s created between them a stable equilibrium, corroborated by reciprocal experience. Until this is proven valid, the sailors will believe that Odysseus choice in front of the Sirens is rational, while Odysseus is led to believe the sailors will obey him. Because of this balance, Odysseus will hear the Sirens, and everyone will survive.

  7. We do not use the concept of “performance” without specific purpose. Odysseus behaviour is theatrical, indeed. Performance recalls the notion of social drama, which itself recalls the concept of rite of passage. The latter is characterised by three stages, the second of which is called liminal, or anti-structural, since all normal, daily social rules are interrupted, broken, suspended. Therefore, by this performance—his being fastened as if he was not the Captain—Odysseus is experiencing a rite of passage, a dramatic moment that will change his fate.

  8. This also recalls the topic of the uncertainty of the value, a question that we will address in Sect. 5.

  9. We reckon unnecessary to produce an exhaustive catalogue of what is to be considered as “thymotic passion”. However, a hypothetical list should absolutely include three couples, at least: amor fou and hate; respect and shame; pride and outrage.

  10. This definition includes elaborations such as that of psychological games, or games with belief-dependent motivations, in which the players’ utilities “may also directly depend on the beliefs (about choices, beliefs, or information) they hold” (Attanasi and Nagel 2008, p. 205).

  11. Similar reactions are hardly understood, if considered outside the logic of recognition need from the counterpart. Our only purpose is underlining that an adequate attention to similar reactions can drive to an innovative analysis about how markets and organizations function.

  12. As underlined by Hirshleifer (1993, p. 186), the loss of control is a feature of passions we cannot abstract from. This means “hot” passions (like thymós) are morally intractable phenomena, because usually their potential (which is constructive as well as disruptive) does not bear limits nor does it respect proportions; a codification of the legitimate reasons and of the means allowed to morally practice, let’s assume, anger, Eros, fear or imagination, would be a wishful thinking. Moral rationality is thus extraneous to our argument.

  13. See Bauman (2000). In the field of anthropological studies, we invite the reader to consider Appadurai (1996).

  14. In the scientific literature of psychology and neuroscience, the use by decision-makers of heuristics instead of optimization is a widespread idea that goes back at least to Newell and Simon (1976). Nevertheless, authors like Kahneman and Gigerenzer, mentioned in the text, express very different opinions regarding the nature and role of heuristics. In a nutshell, while Kahneman reckons they never approach the optimal strategy, but rather they weakly replace it when it absconds, Gigerenzer thinks many of them are tools of the ecologic rationality’s satisfacing operation.

  15. Two of the main recent philosophical conceptualisations on the topics of this paper are written by Apel (1984) and Sloterdijk (2010).

References

  • Akerlof GA, Kranton RE (2010) Identity economics. How our identities shape our work, wages, and well-being. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Apel K-O (1984) Understanding and explanation. The MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Appadurai A (1996) Modernity at large. University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis

    Google Scholar 

  • Arendt H (1958) The human condition. The University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Atran S, Axelrod R (2008) Reframing sacred values. Negot J: 221–246

  • Atran S, Axelrod R, Davis R (2007) Sacred barriers to conflict resolution. Science 317. 24 August

  • Attanasi G, Nagel R (2008) A survey of psychological games: theoretical findings and experimental evidence. In: Innocenti A, Sbriglia P (eds) Games, Rationality and Behaviour. Palgrave McMillan, Houndmills, pp 204–232

    Google Scholar 

  • Bauman Z (2000) Liquid modernity. Polity, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Bellelli G, Schiena R (2008) Decisioni ed emozioni. Bologna, Il Mulino

    Google Scholar 

  • Berger PL, Luckmann T (1966) The social construction of reality. Anchor Books, Garden City

    Google Scholar 

  • Berlin I (1958) Two concepts of liberty. In: Berlin I (ed) Liberty. Oxford University Press, Oxford, p 2002

    Google Scholar 

  • Blau PM (1964) Exchange and power in social life. Wiley, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Bodei R (2010) Ira La passione furente. Il Mulino, Bologna

    Google Scholar 

  • Bruni L (2006) Civil happiness. Routledge, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Cattarinussi B (2006) Sentimenti, passioni, emozioni, II edn. Angeli, Milan

    Google Scholar 

  • de Montaigne M (1580–1595) Essays. Penguin Books, London, 1958

  • Elster J (1979) Ulysses and the sirens. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Elster J (1983) Sour grapes. Studies in the subversion of rationality. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Erikson EH (1968) Identity: youth and crisis. Norton, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Evans J (2008) Dual-processing accounts of reasoning, judgment, and social cognition. Ann Rev Psychol 59:255–278

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fehr E, Fischbacher U (2002) Why social preferences matter. Econ J 112:C3–C33

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fehr E, Gächter S (1998) Reciprocity and economics. Eur Econ Rev 42:845–859

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fishburn PC (1974) Lexicographic orders, utilities and decision rules: a survey. Manag Sci 20:1442–1471

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frank RH (1988) Passions within reason: the strategic role of the emotions. Norton, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Fudenberg D, Levine DK (1993) Self-confirming equilibrium. Econometrica 61:523–545

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fukuyama F (1992) The end of history and the last man. Penguin, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Galiani F (1750) On money. University Microfilm International, Ann Arbor, 1977

  • Galimberti U (1999) Psiche e techne. Feltrinelli, Milan

    Google Scholar 

  • Gigerenzer G, Gaissmaier W (2011) Heuristic decision making. Annu Rev Psychol 62:451–482

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gneezy U, Meier S, Rey-Biel P (2011) When and why incentives (Don’t) work to modify behavior. J Econ Perspect 25(4):191–210

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goffman E (1956) The Presentation of Self in Everyday Life. University of Edinburgh (Social Sciences Research Centre, Monograph no. 2)

  • Hanoch Y (2002) ‘Neither an angel nor an ant’: emotion a san aid to bounded rationality. J Econ Psychol 23:1–25

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hirschman AO (1977) The passions and the interests: political arguments for capitalism before its triumph. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Hirshleifer J (1993) The affections and the passions: their economic logic. Ration Soc 5(2):185–202

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Holmes S (1995) Passions and constraint: on the theory of liberal democracy. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Hume D (1739) A treatise on human nature. Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2007

  • Kahneman D (2011) Thinking, fast and slow. Allen Lane, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Keynes JM (1930) Economic possibilities for our grandchildren. In Keynes JM (eds) Essays in persuasion. Classic House Books, New York, 2009

  • Mandeville B (1714) The fable of the bees. Penguin Books, London, 1989

  • Marshall A (1890) Principles of economics. VIII ed. Macmillan, London, 1920

  • Mauss M (1923–1924) Essai sur le don. Forme et raison de l’échange dans les sociétés archaïques. L’Année Sociologique 1: 30–186

  • Mead GH (1913) The social self. J Philos Psychol Sci Methods 10(1913):374–380

    Google Scholar 

  • Newell A, Simon HA (1976) Computer science as empirical enquiry. Commun ACM 19:113–126

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nozick R (1989) The examined life. Simon & Schuster, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Offer A (2013) Regard. In: Bruni L, Zamagni S (eds) Handbook on the economics of philanthropy, reciprocity and social enterprise. Edward Elgar Publishers, Aldershot, pp 285–294

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Parfit D (1984) Reasons and persons. Clarendon, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Pinker S (1997) How the mind works. W. W. Norton, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Pizzorno A (1983) La politica assoluta e altri saggi. Feltrinelli, Milan

    Google Scholar 

  • Pizzorno A (2000) Risposte e proposte. In: Della Porta D, Greco M, Szakolczai A (eds) Identità, riconoscimento. scambio, Laterza, Roma-Bari, pp 197–245

    Google Scholar 

  • Pizzorno A (2007) Il velo della diversità, Studi su razionalità e riconoscimento. Feltrinelli, Milan

    Google Scholar 

  • Romani F (1995) La società leggera. Marsilio, Padova

    Google Scholar 

  • Rorty R (1980) Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature. Blackwell, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Schechner R (1985) Between theatre and anthropology. University of Pennsylvania Press, Pennsylvania

    Google Scholar 

  • Schechner R (2004) Performance theory. Routledge, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Schelling T (1984) Choice and consequence. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Sen AK (2006) Identity and violence: the illusion of destiny. Norton, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Shackle G (1953) The logic of surprise. Economica 20(78):112–117

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shakespeare W (1598–1599) In: King Henry V. Wordsworth Classics, Hertfordshire, 1992

  • Simmel G (1908) Sociology. Brill, London, 2009

  • Sloterdijk P (2010) Rage and time. Columbia University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Slovic P, Peters E (2006) Risk perception and affect. Curr Dir Psychol Sci 15(6):322–325

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith A (1759) The theory of moral sentiments. Cosimo, New York, 2007

  • Sparti D (2002) Epistemologia delle scienze sociali. Il Mulino, Bologna

    Google Scholar 

  • Tajfel H, Billig MG, Bundy RP, Flament C (1971) Social categorization and intergroup behavior. Eur J Soc Psychol 1(2):149–178

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Todorov T (1995) La vie commune. Essai d’anthropologie générale. Éditions du Seuil, Paris

    Google Scholar 

  • Trivers R (2011) Deceit and self-deception: fooling yourself the better to fool others. Basic Books, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Turner V (1957) Schism and continuity in an African society: a study of Ndembu village life. Manchester University Press, Manchester

    Google Scholar 

  • Turner V (1969) The ritual process: structure and anti-structure. Aldine Publishing Co, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Turner V (1982) From ritual to theatre: the human seriousness of play. PAJ Publications, NY

    Google Scholar 

  • Turner JC (1987) A self-categorization theory. In: Turner JC, Hogg MA, Oakes PJ, Reicher SD, Wetherell MS (eds) Rediscovering the social group: a self-categorization theory. Blackwell, Oxford, pp 42–67

    Google Scholar 

  • Turner WV (1986) Dewey, Dilthey and Drama: an essay in the antrhpology of experience. In: Turner V, Brumer ME (eds) The anthropology of experience. University of Illinois Press

  • Tversky A (1972) Elimination by aspects: a theory of choice. Psychol Rev 79:281–299

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Veblen TB (1899) The theory of the leisure class. Macmillan, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein L (1953) Philosophical investigations. Blackwell, London, 2009

  • Zedong M (1936) The red book of guerrilla warfare, chapter 6, El Paso Norte Press, El Paso, 2010

Download references

Acknowledgments

We would like to thank Angelo Antoci, Simone Bertoli, Gianluca Bonaiuti, Luigino Bruni, Luca Corazzini, Vittorioemanuele Ferrante, Pierluigi Sacco and Roberto Ricciuti for their comments and suggestions. Any imperfection is ours.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Nicolò Bellanca.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Bellanca, N., Pichillo, G. Identitarian passions: the overwhelming power of the human recognition need. Int Rev Econ 61, 13–38 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s12232-014-0194-8

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s12232-014-0194-8

Keywords

JEL Classification

Navigation