Skip to main content
Log in

A Reason To Be Free

Operationalizing ‘Free Action’

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Neuroethics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Recent Libet-style experiments are of limited relevance to the debate about free action and free will, and should be understood as investigations of arbitrary actions or guesses. In Libet-style experiments, the concept of 'free action' is commonly taken to refer to a 'self-initiated voluntary act', where the self prompts an action without being prompted. However, this idea is based on the problematic assumption that the conscious self needs to be free from every constraint in order to be actually free. We maintain that a fundamental condition for free action is the presence of reasons to act responsibly. By analyzing a recent neuroscientific experiment, we indicate how its results could be interpreted as indicating how free action operationalization is inappropriately focusing on arbitrary actions. Hence, the way free action has been experimentally studied may have had a misleading influence on the debate about free will.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Although the concept of “cue” is used often, its relationship with the concept of “cause” and “reason” is not completely clear. To our understanding, in the current context “cue” has an epistemic connotation, a cue provides information that is used (e.g. taken as a reason) for potential action.

  2. It has to be noticed that conceptual issues have been raised about the scientific validity of appealing to internal cues in general. An extensive review of the debate would be beyond the scope of this paper. Those interested in deepening this topic may check [7, 9, 11, 12].

  3. We do not wish to imply that the authors agree on all issues, rather to illustrate the various ways of emphasizing the relation between free will, free action and responsibility.

  4. There is one potential confusion we would like to forestall here. One could still meaningfully attribute responsibility in this case in the following way: If one believes that X and therefore one does Y, that could be wrong (blameworthy) in the sense that never in the case of X one should do Y, regardless of whether or not X is actually the case. This, however, is a type of responsibility (what would you do if X applies) that we are not discussing here. We are addressing responsibility for action, not for hypothetical action.

  5. In Bode’s experiment, this freedom is represented by subjects' liberty not to comply with experimenters' requests.

References

  1. Libet, Benjamin, Elwood W. Wright, and Curtis A. Gleason. 1982. Readiness-potentials preceding unrestricted “spontaneous” vs. pre-planned voluntary acts. Electroencephalography and Clinical Neurophysiology 54: 322–335.

  2. Soon, Chun Siong, Marcel Brass, Hans-Jochen Heinze, and John-Dylan Haynes. 2008. Unconscious determinants of free decisions in the human brain. Nature Neuroscience 11: 543–545. doi:10.1038/nn.2112.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  3. Fried Itzhak, Roy Mukamel, and Gabriel Kreiman. 2011. Internally generated preactivation of single neurons in human medial frontal cortex predicts volition. Neuron 69: 548–562. doi:10.1016/j.neuron.2010.11.045.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  4. Pockett, Susan, and Suzanne C. Purdy. 2010. Are voluntary movements initiated preconsciously? The relationships between readiness potentials, urges, and decisions. In Conscious Will and Responsibility, eds. Walter Sinnot-Armstrong, Lynn Nadel, 34–46. New York: Oxford University Press, Inc. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780195381641.003.0005.

  5. Schlegel, Alexander, Prescott Alexander, Walter Sinnott-Armstrong, Adina Roskies, Peter U. Tse, and Thalia Wheatley. 2013. Barking up the wrong free: readiness potentials reflect processes independent of conscious will. Experimental Brain Research 5(3-4): 193–208. doi:10.1080/17588928.2014.934215.

  6. Nachev, Parashkev, and Peter Hacker. 2014. The neural antecedents to voluntary action: a conceptual analysis. Cognitive Neuroscience 5(3–4): 193–208. doi:10.1080/17588928.2014.934215.

  7. Nachev, Parashkev, and Masud Husain. 2010. Action and the fallacy of the “internal”: Comment on Passingham et al. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 14: 192–193. doi:10.1016/j.tics.2010.03.002.

  8. Roskies Adina L. 2010. How does neuroscience affect our conception of volition?. Annual Review of Neuroscience 33: 109–130. doi:10.1146/annurev-neuro-060909-153151.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  9. Passingham, Richard E., Sara L. Bengtsson, and Hakwan C. Lau. 2010. Medial frontal cortex: from self-generated action to reflection on one’s own performance. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 14: 16–21. doi:10.1016/j.tics.2009.11.001.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  10. Schüür, Friederike, and Patrick Haggard. 2011. What are self-generated actions?. Consciousness and Cognition 20: 1697–1704. doi:10.1016/j.concog.2011.09.006.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  11. Nachev, Parashkev. 2010. Free choice and voluntary action. Psyche 16: 87–98. http://philpapers.org/rec/NACFC.

  12. Passingham, Richard E, Sara L Bengtsson, and Hakwan C Lau. 2010. Is it fallacious to talk of selfgenerated action?: Response to Nachev and Husain. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 14: 193–194. doi:10.1016/j.tics.2010.03.004.

  13. Passingham, Richard E, and Hakwan C Lau. 2006. Free Choice and the Human Brain. In Does Consciousness Cause Behavior?, eds. Susan Pockett, William Banks, and Shaun Gallagher, 52–72. Cambridge-London: The MIT Press. doi:10.7551/mitpress/9780262162371.003.0005.

  14. Bode, Stefan, Carsten Bogler, and John-Dylan Haynes. 2013. Similar neural mechanisms for perceptual guesses and free decisions. NeuroImage 65 Elsevier Inc.: 456–465. doi:10.1016/j.neuroimage.2012.09.064.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  15. Wolf, Susan. 1990. Freedom within reason. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Mita, Akihisa, Hajime Mushiake, Keisetsu Shima, Yoshiya Matsuzaka, and Jun Tanji. 2009. Interval time coding by neurons in the presupplementary and supplementary motor areas. Nature Neuroscience 12: 502–507. doi:10.1038/nn.2272.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  17. Strawson, Galen. 2010. Freedom and belief. New York: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199247493.001.0001.

  18. Strawson Peter. 1963. Freedom and resentment. Proceeding of the British Academy 48: 1–25

  19. Dennett, Daniel C. 1984. Elbow room: The varieties of free will worth wanting. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Frankfurt, Henry G. 1988. Freedom of the will and the concept of a person. The Journal of Philosophy 68: 5–20.

  21. Fischer, Martin J., and Mark Ravizza. 2000. Responsibility and Control: A Theory of Moral Responsibility. Cambridge studies in philosophy and law. Cambridge, New York: Cambridge University Press.

  22. McKenna, Michael. 2009. Compatibilism. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/compatibilism. Accessed 14 October 2015.

  23. O’Connor, Timothy. 2013. Free will. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/freewill. Accessed 14 October 2015.

  24. Roskies, Adina L. 2010. Why Libet’s studies don’t pose a threat to free will. In Conscious will and responsibility, eds. Walter Sinnot-Armstrong, Lynn Nadel, 11–22. New York: Oxford University Press, Inc. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780195381641.003.0003.

  25. Bode, Stefan, Carsten Murawski, Chun Siong Soon, Philipp Bode, Jutta Stahl, and Philip L. Smith. 2014. Demystifying “free will”: The role of contextual information and evidence accumulation for predictive brain activity. Neuroscience & Biobehavioral Reviews 47: 636–645. doi:10.1016/j.neubiorev.2014.10.017.

  26. Dennett, Daniel C. 2013. Intuition pumps and other tools for thinking. London: Penguin Books UK.

Download references

Acknowledgments

We thank Ceci Verbaarschot for her extensive and useful feedback on an earlier version of this paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Giulio Mecacci.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Mecacci, G., Haselager, P. A Reason To Be Free. Neuroethics 8, 327–334 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s12152-015-9241-8

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s12152-015-9241-8

Keywords

Navigation