Skip to main content
Log in

Tropes for Causation

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Metaphysica

Abstract

Tropes, as distinguished from other possible kinds of entities such as universals, states of affairs, events and bare particulars, are best-suited to play the role of causal relata.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For example, Cartwright (1989) maintains that substances have irreducible capacities to make changes in the world because of their nature.

  2. Of the first sort there is, for instance, Molnar’s (2003) account, in which he argues that powers are individual intrinsic properties of their bearers. (Molnar’s view will be discussed below.) Reductive/explanatory analyses are Lewis’s (1997) or, in a non-Humean vein, Armstrong’s (1968).

  3. For the distinction of the event/state of affairs that I am roughly introducing here, see J. Bennett (1988).

  4. To speak of ‘particular’ properties instead of ‘individual’ properties could be misleading. A particular is something that parts a whole. For instance, each particular man parts the whole of the ‘dividual’ manhood thus being man. But one could also admit that there are individuals without accepting this account for their individuality. Given that ‘individual’ makes reference to what is not divisible in the sense that a dividual is, it seems more appropriate to speak of individual properties. Russell is, of course, trying to define the essence of individuals and universals. The former he takes to be concrete things, the latter transcendental properties and relations.

  5. A more complex way of saying what I really mean here, but that takes into account Platonic universals as well, would be something like this: universal properties are to many. However, this way of speaking would obscure the discussion. A further possibility is to say that individual properties, unlike universals, are not capable of multiple instantiation; but now the problem is that individual properties do not properly “instantiate”. Moreover, this would imply a relation between universals and individuals accounting for their distinction, which seems unnecessary and maybe a petitio principii.

  6. For instance, Whittle (2003: 376) writes that ‘tropes as sui generis property instances, such as ‘the redness of this poppy’ or ‘the love of Bob for Katy’ (…) are intrinsic to the entities which have them’ (original italics).

  7. In a sense, the point is that identity conditions for substances or events are harder to determine/specify than identity conditions for properties. After all, the former do need properties.

  8. ‘Harmless’ because the fact that they belong to their bearers necessarily still leaves open the possibility that they are not essential properties of them.

  9. The idea that individual properties are ontologically distinct because distinct substances individuate them can be distinguished from the idea that individual properties are dependent existents: the second can hold even if the first does not. Consider the individual brown that happens to belong to Aaron’s staff. Does it need some kind of ontological support, such as a substance (a staff or a tree), to subsist? One can answer this question in the affirmative and at the same time deny that the staff or the tree provide the conditions of individuation for the property. John Marenbon (1997) has argued that this was Abelard’s view: ‘Accidents do not individuate substances, nor are forms individuated by the substances to which they are attached; indeed, any given form might have been attached to a different particular substance from that to which it is in fact attached. (...) [T]he particular whiteness which makes this body white might have in fact made a different body white, although once in this body it cannot be in another’ (p. 120; my italics). Moreover, even if we accept, against Abelard’s last condition, that individual properties can be actually transferred, they could still need substances (or events) to subsist: properties would be transferred from substance to substance without intermediaries other than substances.

  10. I think that his transference theory of causation is mistaken. See Garcia-Encinas (2004).

  11. Molnar (2003: 43) unfairly compares the view that properties could exist without bearers with Platonism. This is clearly unwarranted because it implies that individual properties without bearers would exist in something like a Platonic realm, which is not the case: whether individual properties are beings in our own realm does not depend on whether or not they have bearers.

  12. States of affairs are irreducible complex structures that consist minimally of the following: a particular entity (a substance, an event or a bare particular), a property and a special relation between these terms. There is no ad hoc reason why the property in question should be universal.

  13. See, for instance, Ehring (2002) where he argues that a trope’s nature is determined by its membership in a natural class, where the class also includes possibilia.

  14. These views have been defended, for instance, by David Armstrong (1997) and Quine (1953), respectively.

  15. A terminological note could be useful here. I will use and have been using ‘different’ for something like ‘discernible’, where the latter does not have epistemological implications: two entities are different if they have different (natural) properties. ‘Distinct’ is like ‘other’ or ‘numerically other’. The idea is to propose a discourse that does not exclude the possibility that there are indiscernible (non-different) but distinct (other) entities. In other words, the idea is to propose a discourse where Bradley’s dictum that ‘distinction implies difference’ could be subject to consideration. I also think that the dictum is false (see note 22). But this should not matter—yet.

  16. I think that there is nothing obscure or suspicious in the idea that effects are differences made by causes or in the idea that causes are difference makers, that is, effect makers. They are difference makers in the sense, not only that the world would have been different had they not occurred, but also in the sense that they are makers of being.

  17. Please keep in mind that the cause of a given effect is not being considered as part of the relevant properties of the effect. Otherwise, the argument could seem suspect. The idea is that a different effect is another effect; but this leaves open the possibility that the same effect is caused by different causes, for instance. I failed to see this in Garcia-Encinas (2003).

  18. Ned Hall (2000) proposes to lay the blame on transitivity. However, if I am right and causes and effects are (sums of) properties, this drastic movement is also unnecessary.

  19. For instance, Sydney Shoemaker (1980) or Molnar (2003: 194–198, specially).

  20. Again, non-trivial means that we should not take non-natural properties into account.

  21. To work under the possibility that the principle is false seems reasonable enough. But I think I can also offer a reason why it is false. To conceive of something as distinct, as a numerically other entity, is not to think of it as being in any relation of agreement or difference with any other thing. And a reason must be given to assume otherwise; a reason must be given why, as Johnson (1964: 22) would put it, ‘otherness presupposes comparison’.

  22. As Armstrong does, this difficulty is usually written in terms of objects or substances (see Moreland 1985: 59), but it can be safely applied to other sorts of possible indiscernibles, such as causal relata.

References

  • Abelard, P. Logica Ingredientibus in B. Geyer (ed.) (1919–1933) Peter Abaelard’s Philosophische Schriften Aschendorff.

  • Aristotle Aristotle´s Categories and De Interpretatione J.L. Ackrill (trans.) (1963) Oxford: Claredon Press.

  • Armstrong, D.M. (1968) A Materialist Theory of Mind London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Armstrong, D.M. (1978) Nominalism and Realism vol. I: Universals and Scientific Realism Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Armstrong, D.M. (1989) Universals: an Opinionated Introduction Colorado: Westview.

    Google Scholar 

  • Armstrong, D.M. (1997) A World of States of Affairs Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bennett, J. (1988) Events and Their Names Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boethius Second Commentary on Porphyry’s Isagoge, vol. 64. In The Patrologia Latina Database Jacques-Paul Migne’s (ed.) Patrologia Latina 1844 & 1855. http://pld.chadwyck.co.uk/.

  • Campbell, K. (1990) Abstract Particulars Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, N. (1989) Nature’s Capacities and their Measurement Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1967) ‘Causal Relations’ The Journal of Philosophy, 64:691–703.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1969) ‘The Individuation of Events’ in his (1980) Essays on Actions and Events Oxford: Clarendon Press, pp. 163–180.

    Google Scholar 

  • Denby, D. A. (2001) ‘Determinable Nominalism’ Philosophical Studies 102: 297–327.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ehring, D. (1997) Causation and Persistence New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ehring D. (2002) ‘The Causal Argument against Natural Class Trope Nominalism’ Philosophical Studies 107: 179–190.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Garcia-Encinas, M.J. (2003) ‘A Posteriori Necessity in Singular Causation and the Humean Argument’ Dialectica 57(1):41-55.

    Google Scholar 

  • Garcia-Encinas, M.J. (2004) ‘Transference, or Identity Theories of Causation?’ Theoria 19(49):31-48.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hall, N. (2000) ‘Causation and the Price of Transitivity’ The Journal of Philosophy 97(4): 198–222.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, W. (1964) Logic, part I Dover: New York (1st ed. 1921).

    Google Scholar 

  • Kim, J. (1973) ‘Causation, Nomic Subsumption and the Concept of Event’ The Journal of Philosophy 70: 217-236.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1983) ‘New Work for a Theory of Universals’ Reprinted in his (1999) Papers in Metaphysics and Epistemology Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 8-55.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1986) ‘Postscripts to ‘Causation’’ in his Philosophical Papers vol. II Oxford: Blackwell, pp. 172–213.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1997) ‘Finkish Dispositions’ Philosophical Quarterly 47:143-158.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Loux, M. (1998) Metaphysics: a Contemporary Introduction London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marenbon, J. (1997) The Philosophy of Peter Abelard Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mertz, D.W. (1996) Moderate Realism and its Logic New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Molnar, G. (2003) Powers Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moreland, J.P. (1985) Universals, Qualities, and Quality-Instances Boston: University Press of America

    Google Scholar 

  • Mulligan, K., Simons, P. & Smith, B. (1984) ‘Truth-Makers’ Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 44: 287–322.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Paul, L.A. (2000) ‘Aspect Causation’ The Journal of Philosophy 97(4): 235–256.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W.O. (1953) ‘On What There is’ in his From a Logical Point of View Cambridge: Harvard University Press, pp. 1–19.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. (1912) ‘The World of Universals’ in his The Problems of Philosophy. Oxford: Clarendon Press, pp. 52–57.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schaffer, J. (2001) ‘The Individuation of Tropes’. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 79(2): 247–257.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shoemaker, S. (1980) ‘Causality and Properties’ in P. Inwagen (ed.) (1980) Time and Cause Dordrecht Reidel, pp. 109–135.

    Google Scholar 

  • Whittle, A. (2003) ‘Singularism’ Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 103: 371–379.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

This paper was written within research project HUM2007-63797 MEC. I want to thank an anonymous referee for his/her comments on a previous version.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to M. J. Garcia-Encinas.

About this article

Cite this article

Garcia-Encinas, M.J. Tropes for Causation. Int Ontology Metaphysics 10, 157–174 (2009). https://doi.org/10.1007/s12133-009-0047-1

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Revised:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s12133-009-0047-1

Keywords

Navigation