Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Making Sense of Child Welfare When Regulating Human Reproductive Technologies

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Journal of Bioethical Inquiry Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Policy-makers have attempted to frame the ethical requirements that are relevant to the creation of human beings via reproductive technologies. Various reports and laws enacted in New Zealand, Canada, Australia, and Britain have introduced tests for how we should weigh child welfare when using these technologies. A number of bioethicists have argued that child welfare should be interpreted as a “best interests” test. Others have argued that there are ethical reasons why we should abandon this kind of test. I will argue that at least some of the relevant policy can be interpreted as requiring those wishing to exercise their procreative liberty to have a reasonable plan to care and nurture any resulting child, thereby respecting the internal preconditions of that liberty. This interpretation of child welfare requirements answers some of the ethical worries about a child welfare test.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Of course, there are other legal and ethical issues to be considered with regard to commercial surrogacy arrangements beyond the scope of this paper, such as whether it objectifies and uses women as means to an end, particularly in situations in which the surrogate and commissioning couple are from different socioeconomic strata and/or countries. See, for example, Scott Carney’s chapter “Cash on Delivery” in The Red Market (2011) on commercial surrogacy organizations in India.

References

  • Archard, D. 2004. Wrongful life. Philosophy 79(309): 403–419.

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Benatar, D. 2008. Better never to have been: The harm of coming into existence. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brazier, M., A. Campbell, and S. Golombok. 1998. Surrogacy: Review for health ministers of current arrangements for payments and regulation: Report of the review team. London: Department of Health.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, A., D. Brock, N. Daniels, and D. Wikler. 2000. From chance to choice: Genetics and justice. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Carney, S. 2011. The red market: On the trail of the world’s organ brokers, bone thieves, blood farmers, and child traffickers. New York: William Morrow.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feinberg, J. 1984. Harm to others. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gillett, G. 1987. AIDS and confidentiality. Journal of Applied Philosophy 4(1): 15–20.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Glover, J. 2008. Choosing children: Genes, disability, and design. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hanser, M. 1990. Harming future people. Philosophy and Public Affairs 19(1): 47–70.

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Harris, J. 2000. The welfare of the child. Health Care Analysis 8(1): 27–34.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Harris, J. 2004. On cloning: Thinking in action. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Human Fertilisation and Embryology Authority. 2009. Welfare of the child assessment. http://www.hfea.gov.uk/1414.html.

  • Jackson, E. 2002. Conception and the irrelevance of the welfare principle. The Modern Law Review 65(2): 176–203.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kamm, F. 1992. Creation and abortion: A study in moral and legal philosophy. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lafollette, H. 1980. Licensing parents. Philosophy and Public Affairs 9(2): 182–197.

    Google Scholar 

  • McCarthy, D. 2001. Why sex selection should be legal. Journal of Medical Ethics 27(5): 302–307.

    Article  CAS  PubMed Central  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • McMahan, J. 2001. Wrongful life: Paradoxes in the morality of causing people to exist. In Bioethics, ed. J. Harris, 445–478. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Neill, O. 1979. Begetting, bearing, and rearing. In Having children: Philosophical and legal reflections on parenthood, ed. O. O’Neill and W. Ruddock, 25–38. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parfit, D. 1984. Reasons and persons. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Savulescu, J. 2001. Procreative beneficence: Why we should select the best children. Bioethics 15(5–6): 413–426.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Scott, R. 2007. Choosing between possible lives. Oxford: Hart Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Steinbock, B. 1986. The logical case for “wrongful life.” The Hasting Center Report 16(2): 15–20.

    Article  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J. 1986. The non-identity problem. Ethics 96(4): 804–831.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to John McMillan.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

McMillan, J. Making Sense of Child Welfare When Regulating Human Reproductive Technologies. Bioethical Inquiry 11, 47–55 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11673-013-9495-y

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11673-013-9495-y

Keywords

Navigation