Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Space, time and function: intersecting principles of responsibility across the terrain of criminal justice

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Criminal Law and Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper considers the interpretive significance of the intersecting relationships between different conceptions of responsibility as they shift over space and time. The paper falls into two main sections. The first gives an account of several conceptions of responsibility: two conceptions founded in ideas of capacity; two founded in ideas of character, and one founded in the relationship between an agent and the outcome which she causes. The second main section uses this differentiated conceptual account to analyse and interpret certain aspects of the contemporary criminal law of England and Wales. In conclusion, the paper considers a number of hypotheses about what the evidence of certain shifts in the relationship between the three families of responsibility-conception can tell us about the current state and significance of criminal law among other systems of social governance.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For an elaboration of this argument in relation to the law of theft, deception and attempts, see Lacey, Wells, and Quick (2003, Chapter 4.II.a-d).

  2. I am in agreement with writers like Duff, Horder and Tadros that there is a distinction to be drawn between attributions of responsibility in specific cases and a broader judgment that a subject lacks in general the capacities which underpin responsibility. These latter subjects are properly regarded as exempt from criminal responsibility, and this is the most natural way to understand ‘defences’ such as insanity or infancy. Space however precludes me from pursuing this issue in more detail. See Duff (1986), Tadros (2005, Chapter 5), Horder (1996), Lacey (2000).

  3. (1976) AC 182.

  4. (1998) 4 All ER 265.

  5. See Gardner (1998), Kahan and Nussabaum (1996), Lacey (2000) and essays by Kyron Huigens, (‘Homicide in Aretaic Terms’) Kenneth W. Simons (‘Does Punishment for “Culpable Indifference” Simply Punish for Bad Character?”) and V. F. Nourse (‘Hearts and Minds’) in a special issue on The New Culpability: Motive, Character and Emotion in Criminal Law (ed. Guyora Binder) (2002) 6 Buffalo Criminal Law Review at pp. 97, 219, 361; and also see Huigens (1995) and Michaels (1998). On character and responsibility more generally, see Schoeman (1987), Gatens and Lloyd (1999) Chapters 3 and 6 (on Spinoza and responsibility), Arenella (1990), Williams (1981)

  6. For criticism of the normative recommendations of various character theories see Duff (1993, 2002) and Yankah (2004).

  7. See Lacey (1991). Victor Tadros also sees a place for capacity principles within his primarily character-based theory: Criminal Responsibility op cit and in particular Chapters 2, 5 & 12. In his view, however, the moral force of the capacity principle is itself parasitic on the more basic sense in which criminal law expresses a judgment of the character displayed in an agent’s conduct. Nonetheless, I think it could be argued that a vision of humans as, under normal conditions of agency, in some sense capacity-responsible for their beliefs, desires and dispositions does underlie Tadros’s account.

  8. For Tadros, actions which are ‘out of character’ may nevertheless be objects of responsibility, on the basis that D showed a culpable failure to resist, hence accepting, a vicious disposition.

  9. See Bayles (1982), Lacey (1988), Tadros (2005) and also footnote 5.

  10. Tadros (2005, pp 23–43). An agent acts, on Tadros’s view, qua agent, when he or she is motivated by reasons which cohere with his or her more general set of values and dispositions.

  11. Tadros (2005, Chapter 13). On the lack of any convincing account of where we draw the boundary between criminal and non-criminal conduct, see Katz (2002).

  12. R v Caldwell (1981) 73 Criminal Appeal Reports 13.

  13. Duff, ibid., pp.155–173. The gradual transformation of the presumption that a defendant intends the natural consequences of his or her actions from legal to merely evidential status through the course of the nineteenth and early twentieth centuries might be regarded as a further example of a shifting practice of character-based responsibilisation at the level of legal doctrine: see Lacey (2001a).

  14. R v Morgan (1976) AC 182: see Lacey et al. (2003, Chapter 5.II.b.iii and iv).

  15. R v Satnam (1984) 78 Criminal Appeal Reports 149.

  16. Criminal Justice Act 2003 ss. 98–101.

  17. R v Kingston (1994) 3 WLR 519.

  18. For a summary of the evidence in the UK, see Phillips and Bowling (2002, p. 579). See also Field and Roberts (2002), Hillyard, Pantazis, Tombs, and Gordon (2004), Home Office (2000), Lustgarten (2002) and MacPherson Report (1999).

  19. See the essays by Elizabeth Kolsky, Wendy Schneider and Martin Wiener in Dubber and Farmer (forthcoming).

  20. See for example Sex Offenders Act 1997, Sexual Offences Act 2003.

  21. See for example the Anti-Terrorism, Crime and Security Act 2001, whose nationality based distinctions were later found by the House of Lords to be in violation of the Human Rights Act: A and others v Secretary of State for the Home Department [2004] UKHL 5

  22. As quoted in The New York Times Monday June 13th 2005 p. A14.

  23. Crime and Disorder Act 1998; www.crimereduction.gov.uk/asbos5.htm; see Tim Newburn, ‘Young People, Crime and Youth Justice’, in Maguire et al. (ed.) The Oxford Handbook of Criminology pp. 531–578 at pp. 563–564; and Ken Pease, ‘Crime Reduction’, in Maguire et al. pp. 947–979 at pp. 969–970; Ramsay (2004).

  24. Dubber (2005). In Part III of his book, Dubber moves towards the development of a theory of ‘substantive due process’ which might have the capacity to confine and rationalize the police power within a framework appropriate to a modern constitutional democracy.

  25. For a persuasive analysis of the dangers of disguising the inevitably evaluative dimension of responsibility attributions, see Nourse (2002).

  26. See Zedner, ‘Victims’, in Maguire, Morgan and Reiner (eds.) The Oxford Handbook of Criminology op. cit.

  27. John Major, in a speech delivered in 1993.

References

  • Arenella, P. (1990). Character, choice and moral agency: The relevance of character to our moral culpability judgments. Social Philosophy & Policy, 7, 59.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ashworth, A., & Blake, M. (1996). The presumption of innocence in English criminal law. Criminal Law Review 306.

  • Bayles, M. (1982). Character, purpose and criminal responsibility. Law and Philosophy, 1, 5.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dubber, M. (2005). The police power. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Duff, R. A. (1986). Trials and punishments. Cambridge University Press.

  • Duff, R. A. (1993). Choice, character and criminal liability. Law and Philosophy, 12, 345.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Duff, R. A. (2002). Virtue, vice and criminal liability: Do we want an Aristotelian criminal law?. Buffalo Criminal Law Review, 6, 147.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eigen, J. P. (1999). Lesion of the will: Medical resolve and criminal responsibility in Victorian insanity trials. Law and Society Review, 33, 425.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Farmer, L. (1996). Criminal law, tradition and legal order. Cambridge University Press.

  • Field, S., & Roberts, P. (2002). Racism and police investigations. Legal Studies, 22, 493.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fletcher, G. (1978). Rethinking criminal law. Boston and Toronto: Little, Brown & Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gardner, J. (1998). The gist of excuses. Buffalo Criminal Law Review, 1, 575.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gatens, M., & Lloyd, G. (1999). Collective imaginings. London: Routledge, Chapters 3 and 6.

  • Hall, J. A. (1952). Theft, law and society. 2nd ed. Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hart, H. L. A. (1968). Punishment and responsibility. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hillyard P., Pantazis C., Tombs S., & Gordon D. (Eds.), (2004). Beyond criminology: Taking harm seriously. London: Pluto Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Home Office (2000) Statistics on race and the criminal justice system. London: Home Office.

    Google Scholar 

  • Honoré, T. (1988) Responsibility and luck: The moral basis of strict liability. Law Quarterly Review, 104, 530, reprinted in Tony Honor?, Responsibility and fault. Hart Publishing, 1999, p.14.

  • Horder, J. (1993). Criminal culpability: The possibility of a general theory. Law and Philosophy, 12, 193.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Horder, J. (1996). Determinism, liberalism and criminal law. Current Legal Problems, 49, 159.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huigens, K. (1995). Virtue and inculpation. Harvard Law Review, 108, 1423.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kahan, D. M., & Nussbaum, M. C. (1996). Two conceptions of emotion in criminal law. Columbia Law Review, 96, 269.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Katz, L. (2002). Villainy and felony: A problem concerning criminalization. Buffalo Criminal Law Review, 6, 451.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kinsey, R., Lea, J., & Young, J. (1986). Losing the fight against crime. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lacey, N. (1988). State punishment. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lacey, N. (1991). Reconstructing the criminal. Cambridge University Press.

  • Lacey, N. (2000). Partial excuses to homicide. In A. Ashworth & B. Mitchell (Eds.), Rethinking English homicide law. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lacey, N. (forthcoming). Character, capacity and outcome: Towards a framework for assessing the shifting pattern of criminal responsibility in modern English law. In M. Dubber & L. Farmer (Eds.), Modern histories of crime and punishment. Stanford University Press.

  • Lacey, N. (2001a). In search of the responsible subject: History, philosophy and criminal law theory. Modern Law Review, 64, 350–371.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lacey, N. (2001b). Responsibility and modernity in criminal law. Journal of Political Philosophy, 9, 249–277.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lacey, N. (2004). Criminalisation as regulation: The role of criminal law. In C. Parker, et al. (Eds.), Regulating law (pp. 144–167). Oxford University Press.

  • Lacey, N. (2006). Historicising contrasts in tolerance. In T. Newburn & P. Rock (Eds.), The politics of crime control (pp. 197–226). Oxford University Press. .

  • Lacey, N., Wells, C., & Quick, O. (2003). Reconstructing criminal law, 3rd ed. Cambridge University Press.

  • Lustgarten, L. (2002). The future of stop and search. Criminal Law Review, 603.

  • MacPherson Report (1999). The Stephen Lawrence inquiry. London: HMSO, Cm 4262.

  • Michaels, A. C. (1998). Acceptance: The missing mental state. S. California Law Review, 71, 953.

    Google Scholar 

  • Norrie, A. (2001). Crime, reason and history, 2nd ed. Cambridge University Press.

  • Nourse, V. F. (2002). Hearts and minds: Understanding the new culpability. Buffalo Criminal Law Review, 6, 361–388.

    Google Scholar 

  • Phillips, C., & Bowling, B. (2002). Racism, ethnicity, crime and criminal justice. In R. M. Maguire, & R. Reiner (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of criminology, 3rd ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pillsbury, S. H. (2002). A problem in emotive due process: California’s Three Strikes Law. Buffalo Criminal Law Review, 6, 483.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ramsay, P. (2004). What is anti-social behaviour? Criminal Law Review, 908–925.

  • Redmayne, M. (2002). The relevance of bad character. Cambridge Law Journal, 61, 684–714.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schoeman, F. (Ed.) (1987). Responsibility, character and the emotions. Cambridge University Press.

  • Smith, R. (1981). Trial by medicine. Edinburgh University Press.

  • Smith, K. J. M. (1998). Lawyers, legislators and theorists. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, P. F. (1982). Freedom and resentment. In G. Watson (Ed.), Free will. Oxford University Press.

  • Tadros, V. (2005). Criminal responsibility. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Teubner, G. (1993). Law as an autopoietic system. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Whitman, J. Q. (2003). Harsh justice. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams, B. (1981). Persons, character and morality. In Moral luck (p. 1). Cambridge University Press.

  • Williams, G. (1983). Textbook of criminal law. 2nd ed. London: Sweet and Maxwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yankah, E. N. (2004). Good guys and bad guys: Punishing character, equality and the irrelevance of moral character to criminal punishment. Cardozo Law Review, 24, 1019–1067.

    Google Scholar 

  • Young, J. (1999). The exclusive society. Sage.

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Nicola Lacey.

Additional information

Professor of Criminal Law and Legal Theory, London School of Economics. Parts of this paper are adapted from my ‘Character, Capacity and Outcome: Towards a framework for assessing the shifting pattern of criminal responsibility in modern English law’, in Markus Dubber and Lindsay Farmer (eds.) Modern Histories of Crime and Punishment (forthcoming, Stanford University Press). My thanks to the participants in the workshop ‘Modern Histories of Crime and Punishment’ held at the Buffalo Criminal Law Center and Baldy Center for Law and Social Policy in June 2005 and in the symposium on ‘Philosophy and the Criminal Law’ held at the British Academy in October 2005 for their constructive feedback; and in particular to Markus Dubber, Lindsay Farmer, Alan Norrie and Victor Tadros for comments and discussion.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Lacey, N. Space, time and function: intersecting principles of responsibility across the terrain of criminal justice. Criminal Law, Philosophy 1, 233–250 (2007). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11572-006-9025-7

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11572-006-9025-7

Keywords

Navigation