Skip to main content
Log in

The Methodology of Philosophical Practice: Eclecticism and/or Integrativeness?

  • Published:
Philosophia Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The need for philosophical practice to integrate various methods, both conceptual and those based on the use of emotions, raises the question as to whether its methodology is necessarily eclectic, in terms of the collection of various methodologies used in philosophy, or whether there is a way to move beyond eclecticism. This is the main subject of this paper. In other words, the question is whether there is such a thing as an ‘integrative’ methodology and, if so, what distinguishes such a method from mere eclecticism. In this text, we define the methodological procedure of integrativeness as the process of systematizing perspectives into an orientational answer to the demands of a specific problem. What differentiates such an approach from mere summation is a new contribution that results from a synergistic and systematic meeting of positions and argumentations whose final result differs from its initial elements. Diversity in the form of a multidimensional relationship towards life and the world results in numerous perspectives, which is a value that should be cultivated and integrated into a reflective and actional perception of the world.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The term ‘ocularcentrism’ is a product of a belief that in the Western culture knowledge is predominately determined by the visual paradigm, which reflects in the Western philosophy as well. The term was introduced by Martin Jay (1988, 1991) who developed a concept of ‘scopic regimes’ to explain the interplay of theory and praxis of visuality that dominates in a certain historical period. Ocularcentrism generally claims that in every given period in Western culture (and philosophy) a certain kind of scopic regime was at place, ie that the visual paradigm takes different forms. The scopic regime of the modernity is identified as ‘Cartesian perspectivism’ (subject and objects are detached, transcendental subject determines the object: subject receives information from the outside world and reflects them thus himself becoming the center of the world and, in effect, its creator). However, every scopic regime, every form of ocularcentrism, including the Cartesian perspectivism, is challenged by antiocularcentrism, which is especially prominent in the modern art with its subversive inclinations. (Jay 1988, Jay 1991, Rukavina 2010)

  2. The expression ‘worldview’ (Weltanschauung) comes from Kant (2000: 138), however he applied a different meaning to it. Here we rely on the determining of world-views suggested by variuous thinkers, eg Heidegger (‘unconscious intelligence’, ‘the independent formative process of intuition’, Heidegger 1982: 4, 6) or DeWitt (‘intertwined, interrelated, interconnected system of beliefs’, DeWitt 2010: 7). In the context of perspectivism, the specific ‘interests’ of the knower that are interconnected and not always reflected upon are more often discussed than world-view.

  3. Although it is likely obvious, the following should be mentioned: the expressions ‘to have one’s own truth’ and ‘closed perspectivism’ do not imply an opinion on the kind of conceptual autism that could be compared with extreme subjectivism or individual relativism. To claim that each person is ‘the measure of all things’ would lead to a solipsism that neither Nietzsche nor any other serious philosophical viewpoint can accept.

References

  • Agamben, G. (2013). Opus Dei: an archaeology of duty. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alexander, S. (1962). ‘They decide who lives, who dies. Medical miracle puts moral burden on small committee. Life (9 November 1962).

  • Boix Mansilla, V., & Dawes Duraising, E. (2007). Targeted assessment of students’ interdisciplinary work: an empirically grounded framework proposed. The Journal of Higher Education, 78(2), 215–237. doi:10.1353/jhe.2007.0008.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Čović, A. (2006). Pluralizam i pluriperspektivizam. Filozofska istraživanja, 26(1), 7–12.

    Google Scholar 

  • Crowder, G. (2003). Pluralism, relativism and liberalism in Isaiah Berlin. Referred paper. Resourced document. http://berlin.wolf.ox.ac.uk/lists/onib/crowder/IBVPREL2003.pdf. Accessed 14 October 2014.

  • DeWitt, R. (2010). Worldviews. An introduction to the history and philosophy of science. Second edition. Wiley-Blackwell.

  • Fatić, A. (2013a). Corruption, corporate character-formation and ‘value strategy’. Filozofija i društvo, 24(1), 60–80. doi:10.2298/FID1301060F.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fatić, A. (2015). Tasks for dreaming. The somatic cognition of emotions in moral judgment. In M. N. Weiss (Ed.), The socratic handbook (pp. 67–82). Wienna: Lit Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fatić, A. (2016). Virtue as identity: emotions and the moral personality. London: Rowman and Littlefield International.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fatić, A., & Dentsoras, D. (2014). Pleasure in epicurean and christian orthodox conceptions of happiness. South African Journal of Philosophy. doi:10.1080/02580136.2014.967594.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fatić, A. (2013b). Epicurean ethics as a foundation for philosophical counselling. Philosophical Practice, 8(1), 1127–1141.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feary, V. (2003). Virtue-based feminist philosophical counselling. Practical Philosophy, 6(1), 7–26.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feary, V. (2004). Spirituality and philosophical practice: counseling with clients in crisis. Philosophical Practice, 9(3), 1413–1425.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ferraiolo, W. (2010). The IDEA method: stoic counsel. Philosophical Practice, 5(2), 627–633.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goleman, D. (1995). Emotional intelligence: why it can matter more than IQ. New York: Bantam Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hadot, P. (1995). Philosophy as a way of life. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (1982). The basic problems of phenomenology (Albert Hofstadter (trans.). Revised edition). Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jay, M. (1988). Scopic regimes of modernity. In H. Foster (Ed.), Vision and visuality (p. 3323). New York: The New Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jay, M. (1991). The disenchantment of the eye: surrealism and the crisis of ocularcentrism. Visual Anthropology Review, 7(1), 15–38. doi:10.1525/var.1991.7.1.15.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (2000). Critique of the Power of Judgment. Paul Guyer (ed. and trans.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, doi: http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511804656.

  • Kolepman, L. M. (2013). The growth of bioethics as a second-order discipline. In J. R. Garrett, F. Jotterand, & C. D. Ralston (Eds.), The development of bioethics in the united states (pp. 137–158). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lahav, R. (2001). Philosophical Counselling as a Quest for Wisdom. Practical Philosophy, March Issue. Resource document. http://www.society-for-philosophy-in-practice.org/journal/pdf/4-1%2006%20Lahav%20-%20Quest%20for%20Wisdom.pdf. Accessed 28 December 2014.

  • Lewis, T., Amini, F., & Lannon, R. (2000). A general theory of love. London: Random House.

    Google Scholar 

  • Luhmann, N. (1987). Soziale systeme: grundriβ einer allgemeinen theorie. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mills, J. (2001). Philosophical counselling as psychotherapy: an eclectic approach. International Journal of Philosophical Practice, 1(1), 1–28.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mittelstraß, J. (1982). Wissenschaft als Lebensform. Reden über philosophische Orientierungen in Wissenschaft und Univeristät. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nietzsche, F. (2006). On the genealogy of morality. In A.-P. Keith (Ed.), Carol Deithe (trans.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Österman, B. (2014). Neo-socratic dialogus as a paradigmatic setting for philosophizing. Philosophical Practice, 9(3), 1426–1435.

    Google Scholar 

  • Repko, A. F. (2007). Integrating interdisciplinarity: How the theories of common ground and cognitive interdisciplinarity are informing the debate on interdisciplinary integration. Issues in Integrative Studies, 25, 1–31.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rukavina, K. (2010). “Okulocentrizam” ili privilegiranje vida u zapadnoj kulturi. Filozofska istraživanja, 32(3–4), 539–556.

    Google Scholar 

  • Slote, M. (2009). Moral sentimentalism. Oxford: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780195391442.001.0001.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Solomon, X. (1999). A better way to think about business: how personal integrity leads to corporate success. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yalom, I., & Leszcz, M. (2005). Theory and practice of group psychotherapy (5th ed.). New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

A part of this research was supported under Marie Curie Newfelpro funding scheme (CONVINce-ME project, FP7-PEOPLE-2011-COFUND program; Government of the Republic of Croatia and the Ministry of Science, Education and Sport). The project was hosted by the Institute for Medical Ethics and History of Medicine, Ruhr University Bochum. The research for the article also arises from Project no. 179049 (“Policies of Remembrance and National Identity: The Regional and European Context”) funded by the Serbian Ministry of Education and Research, which is implemented by the Institute for Philosophy and Social Theory, University of Belgrade, 2010–2015.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Aleksandar Fatić.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of Interest

The authors declare that they have no conflict of interest.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Fatić, A., Zagorac, I. The Methodology of Philosophical Practice: Eclecticism and/or Integrativeness?. Philosophia 44, 1419–1438 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-016-9770-3

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Revised:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-016-9770-3

Keywords

Navigation